Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T04:18:04.518Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A limited skeptical threat

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 March 2018

Joshua May*
Affiliation:
Philosophy Department, University of Alabama at Birmingham, Birmingham, AL 35294-1260. [email protected]

Abstract

Doris argues that our choices are heavily influenced by forces that we wouldn't count as genuine reasons. This unsettling conclusion is motivated by a debunking argument so wide-ranging that it isn't foisted upon us by the sciences. Doris sometimes seems to lower his ambitions when offering instead a skeptical hypothesis argument, but that conflicts with his aims in the book.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ariely, D. (2012) The honest truth about dishonesty. Harper Collins.Google Scholar
Arpaly, N. (2003) Unprincipled virtue. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bateson, M., Nettle, D. & Roberts, G. (2006) Cues of being watched enhance cooperation in a real-world setting. Biology Letters 2(3):412–14.Google Scholar
Batson, C. D. (2011) Altruism in humans. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brueckner, A. (1994) The structure of the skeptical argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54(4):827–35.Google Scholar
Carlson, M., Charlin, V. & Miller, N. (1988) Positive mood and helping behavior: A test of six hypotheses. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 55(2):211–29.Google Scholar
Demaree-Cotton, J. (2016) Do framing effects make moral intuitions unreliable? Philosophical Psychology 29(1):122.Google Scholar
Doris, J. M. (2015b). Talking to our selves: Reflection, ignorance, and agency. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, R. (2006) The evolution of morality. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kumar, V. & May, J. (under review) How to debunk moral beliefs.Google Scholar
Landy, J. F. & Goodwin, G. P. (2015) Does incidental disgust amplify moral judgment? A meta-analytic review of experimental evidence. Perspectives on Psychological Science 10(4):518–36.Google Scholar
Latané, B. & Nida, S. (1981) Ten years of research on group size and helping. Psychological Bulletin 89(2):308–24.Google Scholar
May, J. (2013) Skeptical hypotheses and moral skepticism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43(3):341–59.Google Scholar
May, J. (2014) Does disgust influence moral judgment? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92(1):125–41.Google Scholar
May, J. (forthcoming). Regard for reason in the moral mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, C. B. (2013) Moral character. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. (2014) Process debunking and ethics. Ethics 124:727–49.Google Scholar
Oswald, F. L., Mitchell, G., Blanton, H., Jaccard, J. & Tetlock, P. E. (2013) Predicting ethnic and racial discrimination. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 105(2):171–92.Google Scholar
Seligman, M. E. P., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F. & Sripada, C. S. (2016) Homo prospectus. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2006) Moral skepticisms. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sparks, A. & Barclay, P. (2013) Eye images increase generosity, but not for long: The limited effect of a false cue. Evolution and Human Behavior 34(5):317–22.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (1975) Free agency. Journal of Philosophy 72(8):205220.Google Scholar