Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T19:56:33.820Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On cooperative libertines and wicked puritans

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 October 2023

Roger Giner-Sorolla
Affiliation:
School of Psychology, University of Kent, Canterbury, Kent, UK. [email protected] [email protected]; https://www.kent.ac.uk/psychology/people/227/giner-sorolla-roger
Simon Myers
Affiliation:
School of Psychology, University of Kent, Canterbury, Kent, UK. [email protected] [email protected]; https://www.kent.ac.uk/psychology/people/227/giner-sorolla-roger

Abstract

We agree with Fitouchi et al. that self-denial is sometimes moralized to signal capacity for cooperation, but propose that a person's cooperative character is more precisely judged by willingness to follow cultural, group, and interpersonal goals, for which many rules can serve as proxies, including rules about abstention. But asceticism is not a moral signal if its aims are destructive, while indulging impulses in a culturally approved way can also signal cooperation.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Fitouchi et al. argue that puritanical morality is concerned with signaling and diagnosing cooperation. We agree that self-denial is sometimes moralized to serve this function, but propose a more accurate scope. Specifically, puritanical adherence only signals resources for cooperation – resources that can also bend toward non-cooperative ends. A person's cooperative character is more precisely judged by willingness to follow cultural, group, and interpersonal goals, for which many arbitrary rules can serve as proxies, including rules about abstention. But asceticism is not a moral signal if its intent is destructive; and indulging impulses in a culturally approved way can also signal cooperation.

First, the assumption that selfishness is self-evidently automatic, and that cooperation is self-evidently controlled, does not fit the whole story of research on the topic (e.g., Buckholtz, Reference Buckholtz2015; Nitschke, Forbes, & Lamm, Reference Nitschke, Forbes and Lamm2022; Speer, Smidts, & Boksem, Reference Speer, Smidts and Boksem2022). Fitouchi et al. note failures to replicate “intuitive cooperation” effects. They recognize that intuitive selfishness may be moderated by prosocial disposition. But many findings still reveal intrinsic motives to help. Cain, Dana, and Newman (Reference Cain, Dana and Newman2014) call intrinsic prosociality “giving,” versus “giving in” to a social norm or social pressure to be unselfish. Evidence for giving comes from the “warm glow” literature on prosocial behavior (Andreoni, Reference Andreoni1990; Dunn, Aknin, & Norton, Reference Dunn, Aknin and Norton2014). If some people get a “helper's high,” a prosocial disposition needs no self-control. More recently, Bago, Bonnefon, and De Neys (Reference Bago, Bonnefon and De Neys2021) have shown that individual differences in cooperation and selfishness both result from intuitive processes, rather than greater or lower control. If self-control is secondary to intuitive cooperativeness, then when diagnosing morality, cooperativeness itself is surely a better cue.

We are not saying that puritanism plays no part in moral inference. It might work as a multiplier, given baseline assumptions of prosocial intent. But tellingly, people are not seen as more moral when they give up short-term pleasures for evil ends. For example, after the September 11th attacks, attempts to acknowledge the suicide attackers as “courageous” were strongly resisted. Their ultimate self-sacrifice could not be seen as virtue, given the evil of their aims (Kyle, Reference Kyle2017). A self-controlled villain is worse, not better, than a sloppy, pleasure-seeking one. Likewise, self-control contributes to judgments of good (but not bad) character as a necessary ingredient to carry out good intentions, not as a virtue on its own (Gai & Bhattacharjee, Reference Gai and Bhattacharjee2022). In actual behavior, too, self-control is not always beneficent. As a trait, it can facilitate less frequent but more successful antisocial acts (Mathes et al., Reference Mathes, Lane, Helmers, Jamnik, Hendrickson and Aleshire2017), and can work toward selfish ends when social control is low (Uziel & Hefetz, Reference Uziel and Hefetz2014).

More parsimoniously, we see puritanical morality as one of many rules that might be adopted by a society to signal willingness to abide by other rules concerning harm and help. Rules that require self-abnegation may indeed have an advantage in practice. They are costly to enact, but can be enacted consistently, because they require no food, drink, or partner to be available. Indeed, proscriptive morality (i.e., following social/moral norms about what should not be done) has been shown to carry a stronger motivational force than prescriptive morality (i.e., seeking a prosocial end for its own sake) (Janoff-Bulman & Carnes, Reference Janoff-Bulman and Carnes2013; Janoff-Bulman, Sheikh, & Hepp, Reference Janoff-Bulman, Sheikh and Hepp2009). However, the important ingredient of proscriptive morality is still the adherence to the norm in the first place, and indulgence is just one of many things that can be proscribed.

Purity also loses standing as a universal signal of cooperation when group norms license rowdy behavior. If the dynamics of university “Greek” organizations and drinking societies are not proof enough, Lowe and Haws (Reference Lowe and Haws2014) showed that in a variety of self-control arenas such as spending and eating, people formed social bonds over shared indulgence as well as shared abstinence. Abstinence was preferred mainly when self-control failure was seen as more harmful than innocuous. Likewise, Rawn and Vohs’ (Reference Rawn and Vohs2011) model of “self-control for personal harm” marshals evidence that many dangerous, self-harming, and impulsive-seeming acts aim to gain social acceptance. True, in such cases people may internally need self-control to propel themselves into excesses they would otherwise recoil at. But the external signal being sent, most germane to their reputation, is one of indulgence.

Conversely, derogatory terms such as “prig,” “prude,” and “wowser” tell us that people who shy away from fun can pay a cost, by being seen as cold, unfriendly, even uncooperative. Uziel (Reference Uziel2018) reviews studies showing that self-control can have downsides in personal relationships and interpersonal problem solving: Lack of spontaneity engenders mistrust. More recently, Röseler, Ebert, Schütz, and Baumeister (Reference Röseler, Ebert, Schütz and Baumeister2021) found that people with high self-control were not always liked more. Self-control was a liability in socializing (vs. duty) situations and when the perceiver themselves had low self-control. This last effect shows that individual as well as cultural norms may determine whether tight or loose people are most to be trusted.

By their admission, Fitouchi et al.'s analysis covers only puritanism, one facet of the “purity” set of moral concerns. However, a focus on general social norms might bring in more purity concerns under a common roof. Although some observances and taboos plausibly concern pathogen control, other rules antithetical or irrelevant to immune defense take on lives of their own as cultural signifiers. Why the British and not the French historically abhor horse meat; why rotten-smelling dairy and fish concoctions have adherents in certain corners of Europe; the varied toleration worldwide of two people of the same gender who fall in love or have sex – all of these purity and impurity norms seem like arbitrary, sometimes costly, rules to follow. But they point toward a person's general rule-following tendency, taken as a very rough cue to whether they will cause harm or do good in society (for experimental evidence, see Chakroff, Russell, Piazza, & Young, Reference Chakroff, Russell, Piazza and Young2017). In conclusion, not just puritanism, but all kinds of culturally sanctioned observances are moralized to bear on judgments – justified or not – of a person's helpfulness or depravity.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Competing interest

None.

References

Andreoni, J. (1990). Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm-glow giving. The Economic Journal, 100(401), 464477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bago, B., Bonnefon, J.-F., & De Neys, W. (2021). Intuition rather than deliberation determines selfish and prosocial choices. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 150(6), 10811094.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buckholtz, J. W. (2015). Social norms, self-control, and the value of antisocial behavior. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 3, 122129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cain, D. M., Dana, J., & Newman, G. E. (2014). Giving versus giving in. The Academy of Management Annals, 8(1), 505533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakroff, A., Russell, P. S., Piazza, J., & Young, L. (2017). From impure to harmful: Asymmetric expectations about immoral agents. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 69, 201209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunn, E. W., Aknin, L. B., & Norton, M. I. (2014). Prosocial spending and happiness: Using money to benefit others pays off. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 23(1), 4147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gai, P. J., & Bhattacharjee, A. (2022). Willpower as moral ability. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 151(8), 19992006.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2013). Surveying the moral landscape: Moral motives and group-based moralities. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17(3), 219236.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Janoff-Bulman, R., Sheikh, S., & Hepp, S. (2009). Proscriptive versus prescriptive morality: Two faces of moral regulation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96(3), 521.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kyle, B. G. (2017). Courage, cowardice, and Maher's misstep. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 47(4), 565587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, M. L., & Haws, K. L. (2014). (Im) moral support: The social outcomes of parallel self-control decisions. Journal of Consumer Research, 41(2), 489505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mathes, E. W., Lane, D. J., Helmers, B. R., Jamnik, M. R., Hendrickson, M., & Aleshire, B. (2017). The dark side of self-control: High self-control leads to better outcomes when engaging in bad behaviors. Personality and Individual Differences, 105, 326329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nitschke, J. P., Forbes, P. A., & Lamm, C. (2022). Does stress make us more – or less – prosocial? A systematic review and meta-analysis of the effects of acute stress on prosocial behaviours using economic games. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 142, 104905.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rawn, C. D., & Vohs, K. D. (2011). People use self-control to risk personal harm: An intra-interpersonal dilemma. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 15(3), 267289.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Röseler, L., Ebert, J., Schütz, A., & Baumeister, R. F. (2021). The upsides and downsides of high self-control: Evidence for effects of similarity and situation dependency. Europe's Journal of Psychology, 17(1), 1.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Speer, S. P., Smidts, A., & Boksem, M. A. (2022). Cognitive control and dishonesty. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 26(9), 796808.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Uziel, L. (2018). The intricacies of the pursuit of higher self-control. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 27(2), 7984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uziel, L., & Hefetz, U. (2014). The selfish side of self-control. European Journal of Personality, 28(5), 449458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar