Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-f46jp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-02T21:10:03.320Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Motivational whack-a-mole: Foundational boxes cannot be unpacked

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2025

Ezgi Ozgan
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Bilkent University, Ankara, Turkey [email protected] [email protected]
Jedediah W. P. Allen*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Bilkent University, Ankara, Turkey [email protected] [email protected]
*
*Corresponding author.

Abstract

The proposed “black-box” problem and its solution are drawn from the same substance-oriented framework. This framework's assumptions have consequences that re-create the black-box problem at a foundational level. Specifically, Murayama and Jach's solution fails to explain novel behavior that emerges through an organism's development. A process-oriented theoretical shift provides an ontological explanation for emergent behavior and eliminates the black-box problem altogether.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allen, J. W., & Bickhard, M. H. (2013). Stepping off the pendulum: Why only an action-based approach can transcend the nativist–empiricist debate. Cognitive Development, 28(2), 96133. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogdev.2013.01.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, J. W., & Bickhard, M. H. (2022). Emergent constructivism: Theoretical and methodological considerations. Human Development, 66(4–5), 276294. http://doi.org/10.1159/000526220CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickhard, M. H. (2003). An integration of motivation and cognition. In Smith, L., Rogers, C., & Tomlinson, P. (Eds.), Development and motivation: Joint perspectives (pp. 4156). British Psychological Society, Monograph Series II. http://doi.org/10.53841/bpsmono.2003.cat529.5Google Scholar
Bickhard, M. H. (2006). Developmental normativity and normative development. In Smith, L., & Voneche, J. (Eds.), Norms in human development (pp. 5776). Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511489778.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickhard, M. H., & Terveen, L. (1995). Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science: Impasse and solution. Elsevier Scientific.Google Scholar
Seibt, J. (2009). Forms of emergent interaction in general process theory. Synthese, 166(3), 479512. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9373-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Geert, P., & de Ruiter, N. (Eds.). (2022). Toward a process approach in psychology: Stepping into Heraclitus’ river. Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/9781108859189CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witherington, D. C. (2011). Taking emergence seriously: The centrality of circular causality for dynamic systems approaches to development. Human Development, 54(2), 6692. http://doi.org/10.1159/000326814CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witherington, D. C. (2014). Self-organization and explanatory pluralism: Avoiding the snares of reductionism in developmental science. Research in Human Development, 11(1), 2236. http://doi.org/10.1080/15427609.2014.874763CrossRefGoogle Scholar