Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T05:58:10.026Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Quantum Markov blankets for meta-learned classical inferential paradoxes with suboptimal free energy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 September 2024

Kevin B. Clark*
Affiliation:
Cures Within Reach, Chicago, IL, USA [email protected] www.linkedin.com/pub/kevin-clark/58/67/19a https://access-ci.org/ Felidae Conservation Fund, Mill Valley, CA, USA Campus and Domain Champions Program, Multi-Tier Assistance, Training, and Computational Help (MATCH) Track, National Science Foundation's Advanced Cyberinfrastructure Coordination Ecosystem: Services and Support (ACCESS) Expert Network, Penn Center for Innovation, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA, USA Network for Life Detection (NfoLD), NASA Astrobiology Program, NASA Ames Research Center, Mountain View, CA, USA Multi-Omics and Systems Biology & Artificial Intelligence and Machine Learning Analysis Working Groups, NASA GeneLab, NASA Ames Research Center, Mountain View, CA, USA Frontier Development Lab, NASA Ames Research Center, Mountain View, CA, USA SETI Institute, Mountain View, CA, USA Peace Innovation Institute, The Hague 2511, Netherlands & Stanford University, Palo Alto, CA, USA Shared Interest Group for Natural and Artificial Intelligence (sigNAI), Max Planck Alumni Association, Berlin, Germany Biometrics and Nanotechnology Councils, Institute for Electrical and Electronics Engineers (IEEE), New York, NY, USA
*
*Corresponding author.

Abstract

Quantum active Bayesian inference and quantum Markov blankets enable robust modeling and simulation of difficult-to-render natural agent-based classical inferential paradoxes interfaced with task-specific environments. Within a non-realist cognitive completeness regime, quantum Markov blankets ensure meta-learned irrational decision making is fitted to explainable manifolds at optimal free energy, where acceptable incompatible observations or temporal Bell-inequality violations represent important verifiable real-world outcomes.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Applying a rational analysis framework of cognition, Binz et al. resolutely embrace the escalating use of meta-learning to re-construct Bayes optimal-learning algorithms and solutions to explain the metaphysical relationship of mind to environment. Such logicomathematical descriptions of cognition non-trivially approximate properties of mind, including agent-based decision processes, to that of ideal statistical inference and the structure of natural tasks and environments. The authors nonetheless fail to satisfactorily introduce Markov blankets, which would expand their cognitive construct beyond standard applications of analytical and numerical tools to demark relations represented in directed Bayesian networks or graphs and variational probabilistic inference. Markov or Pearl blankets, coined by Bruineberg, Dolega, Dewhurst, and Baltieri (Reference Bruineberg, Dolega, Dewhurst and Baltieri2021) to acknowledge the original decades-old epistemic concept developed by Pearl (Reference Pearl1988), earned deserving attention for their utility in decision sciences, offering tractable optimization methods to identify, partition, and understand groups of marginally and conditionally (in)dependent variables associated with complex systems and causal predictions and attributions. In more recent years, however, a trend started by Friston and coworkers (e.g., Hipόlito et al., Reference Hipolito, Ramstead, Convertino, Bhat, Friston and Parr2021; Friston et al., Reference Friston, Parr, Hipolito, Magrou and Razi2021; Ramstead, Badcock, & Friston, Reference Ramstead, Badcock and Friston2018) promotes extension of Markov blankets within a free-energy, active-inference framework to describe the physical interface and reciprocal interactions between agents and their environments. These so-called Friston blankets, a term also coined by Bruineberg et al. (Reference Bruineberg, Dolega, Dewhurst and Baltieri2021) to differentiate their usage from Pearl blankets, cleverly articulate embedded philosophical axioms of mind, body, and environment without fully capturing the logicomathematical rigor and cogency found in typical uses of Pearl blankets and Bayesian inference. Taking a reasonably conventional position on the state-of-art of Friston blankets, theorists supportive of free-energy models must either accept Markov blankets as formal technical innovations that enable practical worthwhile science in absence of known compelling philosophical conclusions about the nature of cognition and life or as dubious mathematics-driven metaphysics interpretations of reality with promising high-impact implications for elucidating cognition and life upon separate experimental biophysical validation. The merits of such a statement seemly convey a fair, albeit critical, edict to the scientific community – one that perhaps discouraged Binz et al. from clarifying Markov blankets and leaves the impression that good productive science enlisting Markov blankets as instruments for inference returns only theoretically mundane findings about cognition and, possibly, life. But, that is not the case and the authors' well-structured arguments may fool readers into believing that this position is true since Binz et al. disappointingly content themselves with only discussing classical Bayesian inference and non-paradoxical cognition, maybe because Friston and coworkers also never stray beyond a classical formulation of their free-energy principle for active inference.

Weaknesses in Binz et al.'s narrow perspective on meta-leaning and cognition may be contrasted and reshaped by exciting findings produced with quantum decision theory, a strict valid quantum-statistical approach capable of defining probabilistic human inference unconfined by the physical mechanical world (Aerts & Aerts, Reference Aerts and Aerts1995; Aerts, Broakaert, Gabara, & Sozzo, Reference Aerts, Broakaert, Gabara and Sozzo2016; Ashtiani & Azgomi, Reference Ashtiani and Azgomi2015; Busemeyer & Bruza, Reference Busemeyer and Bruza2011; Busemeyer, Wang, & Lambert-Mogiliansky, Reference Busemeyer, Wang and Lambert-Mogiliansky2009; Clark, Reference Clark and Salander2011, Reference Clark and Floares2012, Reference Clark2014b, Reference Clark2015, Reference Clark2017; Pinto Moreira, Fell, Dehdashti, Bruza, & Wichert, Reference Pinto Moreira, Fell, Dehdashti, Bruza and Wichert2020; Pothos & Busemeyer, Reference Pothos and Busemeyer2013). Quantum decision theory, with the aid of quantum networks or graphs, quantum Bayesian inference, and other computational features, demonstrates robust successes in modeling and simulating difficult-to-render cognitive phenomena overlooked by Binz et al., especially causal judgment errors or paradoxes unaccounted for by classical decision theory, including conjunctive and disjunctive fallacies, the Allais paradox, and the Ellsberg or planning paradox (Atmanspacher & Römer, Reference Atmanspacher and Römer2012; Busemeyer, Pothos, Franco, & Trueblood, Reference Busemeyer, Pothos, Franco and Trueblood2011; Clark, Reference Clark2021b; Favre, Wittwer, Heinimann, Yukalov, & Sornette, Reference Favre, Wittwer, Heinimann, Yukalov and Sornette2016; Moreira & Wichert, Reference Moreira and Wichert2016a, Reference Moreira and Wichert2016b, Reference Moreira and Wichert2018b; Pothos & Busemeyer, Reference Pothos and Busemeyer2009, Reference Pothos and Busemeyer2013). The great explanatory power of quantum decision networks (Bianconi, Reference Bianconi2002a, Reference Bianconi2002b, Reference Bianconi2003; Bianconi & Barabási, Reference Bianconi and Barabási2001; Li, Iqbal, Perc, Chen, & Abbott, Reference Li, Iqbal, Perc, Chen and Abbott2013) permits expression of quantum Markov chains and blankets (Brandao, Piani, & Horodecki, Reference Brandao, Piani and Horodecki2015; Moreira & Wichert, Reference Moreira and Wichert2018a; Qi & Ranard, Reference Qi and Ranard2021; Sutter, Reference Sutter2018; Wichert, Pinto Moreira, & Bruza, Reference Wichert, Pinto Moreira and Bruza2020), which bound suboptimal free-energy classical inferential paradoxes from optimal free-energy quantum inferential solutions. In this context of meta-learned cognitive inference, both quantum Bayesian inference and Markov blankets provide epistemic tools, analogous to variational Bayesian inference and Pearl blankets, to legitimately approximate irrational human decision making and cognition within a cognitive-completeness constraint. That constraint, not considered by Binz et al., strongly limits degrees of freedom for emergence of meta-learned subjective physical reality (cf. Blume-Kohout & Zurek, Reference Blume-Kohout and Zurek2006; Brandao et al., Reference Brandao, Piani and Horodecki2015; Clark, Reference Clark2014a, Reference Clark2017, Reference Clark2019, Reference Clark2020, Reference Clark2021b, Reference Clark2023; Yearsley & Pothos, Reference Yearsley and Pothos2014), a scenario which helps affirm the idea that Markov blankets may yield meaningful philosophical conclusions regarding the nature of cognition and life.

Cognitive completeness (Tressoldi, Maier, Buechner, & Khrennikov, Reference Tressoldi, Maier, Buechner and Khrennikov2015; Yearsley & Pothos, Reference Yearsley and Pothos2014) encapsulates a black-box approach that isolates any studied cognitive system from the formidable environment-significant measurement problem of quantum mechanics. Some scientists insist the scalable neurophysiological contents of this black box map onto classical or quantum cognitive states relevant to particular sets of respective rational or irrational decisions and their corresponding outcome probabilities (Clark, Reference Clark2017, Reference Clark2021a; Wang & Busemeyer, Reference Wang and Busemeyer2015; Yearsley & Pothos, Reference Yearsley and Pothos2014). For example, if one abandons the constraint of cognitive realism – the assertion that all (meta-learned) cognitive events emerge from classical deterministic neurophysiology – then cognitive systems and their decisional outcomes may be completely described by dimensions or sets of similarity classes on the set of all probability distributions over deterministic and indeterminate (or stochastic) neuropsychological variables and associated environmental settings. Further, arguably more fundamental cognitive completeness and Markov blanket partitions imply non-disturbing measurements should be non-invasive on brain physiology and cognition, with disturbing measurements affecting outcomes of hidden neurophysiological and cognitive variables in a quantum-sensitive manner. Disturbing measurements violate temporal Bell or Leggett–Garg inequalities, signifying violations of classical (meta-learned) cognition, such as Markov-blanketed inferential paradoxes at suboptimal free energy. Restructuring these cognitive phenomena within quantum decision theory and quantum Markov blankets creates opportunities for irrational decision making to be organized into explainable manifolds at optimal free energy, tantamount to quantum active Bayesian inference where observable incompatibility or inequality violations are acceptable (Clark, Reference Clark2021a). Such theoretical elegance in describing complex cognition forces classical and quantum aspects of brain structure and function into a newer realm of logicomathematical formalism with verifiable, important real-world consequences.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.

Competing interest

None.

References

Aerts, D., & Aerts, S. (1995). Applications of quantum statistics in psychological studies of decision processes. Foundations of Science, 1, 8597.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aerts, D., Broakaert, J., Gabara, L., & Sozzo, S. (Eds.) (2016). Quantum structures in cognitive and social sciences. Frontiers Research Topics Ebook. Frontiers Media SA. ISBN 978-2-88919-876-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashtiani, M., & Azgomi, M. A. (2015). A survey of quantum-like approaches to decision making and cognition. Mathematical Social Sciences, 75, 4980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Atmanspacher, H., & Römer, H. (2012). Order effects in sequential measurements of noncommuting psychological observables. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 56, 274280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bianconi, G. (2002a). Growing Cayley trees described by a Fermi distribution. Physical Review E: Statistical, Nonlinear, Soft Matter Physics, 66, 036116.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bianconi, G. (2002b). Quantum statistics in complex networks. Physical Review E: Statistical, Nonlinear, Soft Matter Physics, 66, 056123.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bianconi, G. (2003). Size of quantum networks. Physics Review E, 67(5, Pt 2), 056119.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bianconi, G., & Barabási, A.-L. (2001). Bose-Einstein condensation in complex networks. Physics Review Letters, 86, 56325635.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Blume-Kohout, R., & Zurek, W. H. (2006). Quantum Darwinism: Entanglement, branches, and the emergent classicality of redundantly stored quantum information. Physical Review A, 73(6), 062310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandao, F. G. S. L., Piani, M., & Horodecki, P. (2015). Generic emergence of classical features in quantum Darwinism. Nature Communications, 6, 7908.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bruineberg, J., Dolega, K., Dewhurst, J., & Baltieri, M. (2021). The emperor's new Markov blankets. Behavior and Brain Sciences, 45, e183.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Busemeyer, J. R., & Bruza, P. (2011). Quantum models of cognition and decision making. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 13 978-1107419889.Google Scholar
Busemeyer, J. R., Pothos, E., Franco, R., & Trueblood, J. S. (2011). A quantum theoretical explanation for probability judgment “errors”. Psychological Reviews, 118, 193218.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Busemeyer, J. R., Wang, Z., & Lambert-Mogiliansky, A. (2009). Empirical comparison of Markov and quantum models of decision making. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53, 423433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, K. B. (2011). Live soft-matter quantum computing. In Salander, E. C. (Ed.), Computer search algorithms (pp. 124). Nova Science Publishers, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61122-527-3.Google Scholar
Clark, K. B. (2012). A statistical mechanics definition of insight. In Floares, A. G. (Ed.), Computational intelligence (pp. 139162). Nova Science Publishers, Inc. ISBN 978-1-62081-901-2.Google Scholar
Clark, K. B. (2014a). Basis for a neuronal version of Grover's quantum algorithm. Frontiers in Molecular Neuroscience, 7, 29.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, K. B. (2014b). Evolution of affective and linguistic disambiguation under social eavesdropping pressures. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37(6), 551552.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, K. B. (2015). Insight and analysis problem solving in microbes to machines. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 119, 183193.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, K. B. (2017). Cognitive completeness of quantum teleportation and superdense coding in neuronal response regulation and plasticity. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. eLetter. https://royalsocietypublishing.org/doi/suppl/10.1098/rspb.2013.3056Google Scholar
Clark, K. B. (2019). Unpredictable homeodynamic and ambient constraints on irrational decision making of aneural and neural foragers. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 42, e40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, K. B. (2020). Digital life, a theory of minds, and mapping human and machine cultural universals. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 43, e98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, K. B. (2021a). Quantum decision corrections for the neuroeconomics of irrational movement control and goal attainment. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 44, e127.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, K. B. (2021b). Classical and quantum information processing in aneural to neural cellular decision making on Earth and perhaps beyond. Bulletin of the American Astronomical Society, 53(4), 33.Google Scholar
Clark, K. B. (2023). Neural field continuum limits and the partitioning of cognitive-emotional brain networks. Biology, 12(3), 352.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Favre, M., Wittwer, A., Heinimann, H. R., Yukalov, V. I., & Sornette, D. (2016). Quantum decision theory in simple risky choices. PLoS ONE, 11(12), e0168045.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Friston, K. J., Parr, T., Hipolito, I., Magrou, L., & Razi, A. (2021). Parcels and particles: Markov blankets in the brain. Network Neuroscience, 5(1), 211251.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hipolito, I., Ramstead, M. J. D., Convertino, L., Bhat, A., Friston, K., & Parr, T. (2021). Markov blankets in the brain. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 125, 8897.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Li, Q., Iqbal, A., Perc, M., Chen, M., & Abbott, D. (2013). Coevolution of quantum and classical strategies on evolving random networks. PLoS ONE, 8(7), e68423.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moreira, C., & Wichert, A. (2016a). Quantum-like Bayesian networks for modeling decision making. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 11.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moreira, C., & Wichert, A. (2016b). Quantum probabilistic models revisited: The case of disjunction effects in cognition. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 26.Google Scholar
Moreira, C., & Wichert, A. (2018a). Are quantum-like Bayesian networks more powerful than classical Bayesian networks? Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 28, 7383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreira, C., & Wichert, A. (2018b). Introducing quantum-like influence diagrams for violations of the Sure Thing Principle. International symposium on quantum interactions Q1 2018: 91–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearl, J. (1988). Probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems: Networks of plausible inference. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc. ISBN 1558604790.Google Scholar
Pinto Moreira, C., Fell, L., Dehdashti, S., Bruza, P., & Wichert, A. (2020). Towards a quantum-like cognitive architecture for decision-making. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 43, e171e178.Google Scholar
Pothos, E. M., & Busemeyer, J. R. (2009). A quantum probability explanation for violations of “rational” decision theory. Proceedings of Biological Sciences, 276, 21712178.Google ScholarPubMed
Pothos, E. M., & Busemeyer, J. R. (2013). Can quantum probability provide a new direction for cognitive modeling? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 255327.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Qi, X.-L., & Ranard, D. (2021). Emergent classicality in general multipartite states and channels. Quantum. https://arxiv.org/abs/2001.01507CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramstead, M. J. D., Badcock, P. B., & Friston, K. J. (2018). Answering Schrödinger's question: A free-energy formulation. Physics of Life Reviews, 24, 116.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sutter, D. (2018). Approximate quantum Markov chains. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-78732-9.Google Scholar
Tressoldi, P. E., Maier, M. A., Buechner, V. L., & Khrennikov, A. (2015). A macroscopic violation of no-signaling in time inequalities? How to test temporal entanglement with behavioral observables. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1061.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wang, Z., & Busemeyer, J. (2015). Reintroducing the concept of complementarity to psychology. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1822.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wichert, A., Pinto Moreira, C., & Bruza, P. (2020). Balanced quantum-like Bayesian networks. Entropy, 22(2), 17011726.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yearsley, J. M., & Pothos, E. M. (2014). Challenging the classical notion of time in cognition: A quantum perspective. Proceedings of the Royal Society London B: Biological Sciences, 281, 20133056.Google ScholarPubMed