We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
One does not often find written today “The great object of science is to ameliorate the condition of man, by adding to the advantages which he naturally possesses.” Has science failed us? If so, how?
This essay is based on a talk given for the Third Tykociner Memorial Lecture at the University of Illinois, Urbana, in 1976. The lecture series, named in honor of Joseph Tykociner, focuses on the relationship between science and art.
1
Professor Tykociner was concerned with what is common to the arts and the sciences as well as the interplay between these very different areas, a subject that has always intrigued me. Whether what is common is more important than what is obviously different will probably be argued about for ever. However, the sharp distinction between the sciences and the arts that has been recently much talked about may not be that well posed. We might as well ask, considering the vastly different techniques employed, whether what the musician, painter, and playwright have in common is more important than where they differ.
I believe that there does exist a deep commonality of purpose among the arts and the sciences. But you will have to decide for yourselves whether this is significant enough – considering their many differences – to be worth emphasizing.
Has modern science made our universe “an unbounded theater of the absurd,” or is this anxiety misplaced? What do we mean by “the scientific method,” and how does it differ from other methods of understanding our world? Is science a description of reality? Is it metapor or truth? Who decides what science is, and what is to be taught in class rooms?
This essay is based on an essay originally written for The Rights of Memory: Essays on History, Science and American Culture, edited by Taylor Littleton, and published by University of Alabama Press in 1986. It is based on a lecture given at Auburn University.
1
Robert Penn Warren has spoken on “the use of the past.” One such is surely to situate the present. If for science the present seems unfriendly we might, for comfort, recall the inscription on the dome of the great hall of the National Academy of Sciences in Washington:
TO SCIENCE PILOT OF INDUSTRY MULTIPLIER OF THE HARVEST EXPLORER OF THE UNIVERSE REVEALER OF NATURE'S LAWS ETERNAL GUIDE TO TRUTH
The nineteenth-century optimist who wrote these words is, alas, no longer with us. Instead we have the professional demonstrator, the fundamentalist preacher, and the moralist legislator. Perhaps it is too much to say that we have fallen on the winter of our discontent.
But there are cold winds that blow from Washington, and the chill of indifference, even hostility, from the country as a whole, makes it somewhat unlikely that these words would be written today.
In the last nine hundred years of scholarship and research a remarkable body of work has been created. But can this continue indefinitely? In spite of our great progress, we may ask if science has limits? And if science has limits, what are they?
The essay is based on a lecture given at a symposium celebrating the 900th anniversary of Bologna University in 1988.
It is with pride and pleasure that I speak to you on this nine hundred-year celebration, this anniversary of the signing of your Magna Carta: nine hundred years of intellectual activity, nine hundred years of continuous university existence. Of course, during these nine hundred years we expect a certain sufficiency of bureaucracy, excess of tenured faculty, occasional bad teaching, and some sleepy students. But these nine hundred years are also (I'll try not to be too effusive) a triumph of our all too human intellect – possibly alone in the universe – our struggle to understand, our struggle against brute nature and dark superstition. Is it out of place to paraphrase that cigar-smoking, whiskey-drinking, charmer? “Neverhave so many (all human beings) owed so much (of what we enjoy) to so few (ladies and gentlemen, that is us).”
You are probably thinking, “Can he be serious?” Yes, this is a grand occasion but doesn't he read the papers? Radiation, plutonium, ozone, and new viruses. Hasn't he heard of the dangers as well as the limits of science?
The essays in this collection are taken from articles and lectures that I have written or delivered over many years – some of which I hadn't looked at in quite a while. Putting them together I am struck by the recurrence of certain themes. This shouldn't be surprising since I have been thinking about these subjects for a long time. They occur in somewhat different contexts and reflect the evolution of my thoughts on the relation of science to other human activities.
Since some of the articles were written years ago, I have occasionally included footnotes to update matters where the situation has dramatically changed; but otherwise I have pretty much left things the way they were because that was the way I thought about them at the time.
What is more problematic is that in the originals there are paragraphs and even sections that are repeated from one article to the next. As with itinerant actors and musicians over the centuries, each performance is pieced together from those that have come before – self-plagiarism. But each is presented in a new package and sometimes the package is as interesting as the content.
So I've deleted extended repetitions; also in some of the essays I have excised sections that, in my opinion, don't contribute to the main line of thought and, sometimes, are discussed in other essays.
Mathematics is one of the major hurdles that stand between most of us and an understanding of science, especially physics. Those who attempt to write a book on science, accessible to the non-scientist are warned that every equation cuts the, already small, number of potential readers in half. So, can we do without mathematics? Could we express our thoughts in ordinary language? Yes, it might be possible; but it would be extraordinarily cumbersome. Reflect for a moment: music would be possible without musical notation, but imagine giving musicians instructions, for even a simple symphony, using ordinary language without the musician's language: bars, notes etc. – Now all together, flutes, oboes, and strings. This is what physics and much of the rest of science would be without mathematics – possible, but severely crippled.
This essay is based on a chapter originally published in An Introduction to the Structure and Meaning of Physics in 1968.
In science, the saying goes, one weighs and measures, one deals in numbers; there is perhaps a suggestion that those elsewhere deal in a currency of less substance. At this point eyes close and minds go to sleep; the decimals unfortunately awaken memories of sultry afternoons in algebra class. It is, of course, true that physics deals with numbers and occasionally with very accurate measurement. One is impressed when an extraordinarily complex calculation of the quantity of magnetism the electron possesses, referred to a certain standard magnet, agrees with experimental observation to ten decimal places.
Is a correct theory necessarily a good theory? The strength of theoretical structures lies not so much in their correctness, but in how concrete they are as well as the precision with which questions can be formulated.
This essay is based on an excerpt from the paper “The BCM Theory of Synapse Modification at 30: Interaction of Theory with Experiment,” by Leon N Cooper and Mark F. Bear, originally published in Nature Reviews Neuroscience, in November 2012.
The usefulness of a theoretical structure lies in its concreteness and in the precision with which questions can be formulated. The more precise the questions, the easier it is to compare theoretical consequences with experience. An approach that has been very successful is to find the minimum number of assumptions that imply as logical consequences the qualitative features of the system that we are trying to describe. If we pose the question this way, it means that we agree to simplify. As Albert Einstein once said, “Make things as simple as possible, but no simpler”. Of course, there are risks, and it is here that science becomes as much art as logic. One risk is that we simplify too much and in the wrong way, that we leave out something essential. This is the intellectual risk. Another risk is political – that we may choose to ignore in the first approximation some facet that an important individual has spent a lifetime elucidating.
Why is art often thought of in opposition to science? We do both a disservice by focusing on their differences while neglecting their similarities. Is it possible that at a deep level these two have similar goals?
This essay is based on an article originally published in the journal Daedalus, 1986, vol. 115(3).
We might ask why this question of the difference between art and science is posed. Why are we not talking about the similarities or differences between a painter and a musician, or between a sculptor and a poet? Why is the distinction between the scientist and the artist of special concern? I would like to suggest that this is less an intellectual than a sociological question. It is perhaps because, unfortunately, more and more people who call themselves scientists live, think, and work in a different part of society, both intellectually and socially, from the part inhabited by those who call themselves artists.
There are indeed enormous differences of style in science. Yet, one characteristic of science is that the way things are said in science is almost always less important than what is said, whereas the way a concept is expressed in art is almost always more important than what is expressed.
There is a vast difference between science being created and science being presented (in textbooks, for example). For science being created, I see a closeness between art and science.
In his play Copenhagen, Michael Frayn created a dramatic work with references to some of the most pressing issues in twentieth-century physics. But does knowledge of physics help in an understanding of the play?
This essay is based on program notes written for Trinity Repertory's production of the Michael Frayn play Copenhagen, directed by Oskar Eustis in December of 2002.
Of course Michael Frayn's Copenhagen is not about physics. It is about the memories and interactions of three important, passionate, figures struggling to make sense of a meeting that took place in Nazi-occupied Denmark in September of 1941. The question that dominates the play is why did Heisenberg, head of the German nuclear project, make that visit to Bohr, his old mentor, one of the creators of quantum theory and nuclear physics.
Since memory of the past is shaped by the present, and since each of the characters, particularly Heisenberg, has reasons of their own for wanting to reinterpret what their intentions were, we probably never can be sure what the actual reason for the visit was. (According to the quantum superposition principle, might it have been a combination of all of the various possibilities – all of the above, as the multiple-choice question puts it.)
But two of the three characters, Bohr and Heisenberg, happen to be among the founders of modern quantum theory – certainly one of the great intellectual achievements of the twentieth century.
Euclid's Elements provides one of the earliest and best examples of a system in which complex relationships follow from a small set of very simple assumptions. But is space Euclidian? Is it curved? Does light travel in straight lines? What do such questions mean?
This essay is based on a chapter originally published in An Introduction to the Structure and Meaning of Physics in 1968.
Euclid's Elements
Geometry, like Latin, with generations of repetition has become synonymous with the trials of adolescence and evidence of the inhumanity of adults to their young. Much has passed since Plato had inscribed over the doors of his Academy, “Let no man ignorant of geometry enter here”, or since Edna St. Vincent Millay wrote, “Euclid alone has looked on beauty bare.” What there is in the Elements of Euclid that made them the model for the science of Galileo and Newton, and for the philosophy of Descartes. Why they provide a gem-like example of a mathematical system and of a physical theory remains a mystery to numberless students for whom Euclid evokes only a memory of pain.
In a world beset by uncertainty, the demonstrations of geometry at one time seemed a model for what a sure argument should be. A dispute in the marketplace begins obscurely, and ends in turmoil. In political arguments opinion sways first to one side and then to the other, fluttering like a butterfly, finding no place secure enough to rest.
Fraud is a problem in science, as it is in many human activities. Instances of fraud are relatively rare, but when they happen they tend to garner a lot of attention. Does fraud undermine the sanctity of science – and by the way who ever said science should be sanctified?
This essay is based on an article originally published in the George Street Journal, 16(15), in 1991.
Recent highly publicized cases of “scientific fraud” have elicited much excited comment. We hear cries for watchdogs and oversight committees. We read perturbed editorials speaking of a scientific Watergate. But let's put the situation in perspective and avoid creating something worse than the disease – a cure.
In science, as elsewhere, lying, cheating, stealing, and fraud are distinctly unpleasant. Because scientists are human, one must anticipate that in their daily as well as their scientific activities, they will occasionally stray. What is surprising is our surprise. I recall my mother pointing out to me, a hopeful teenage scientist, an embarrassing situation in which scientists were involved. My smart-aleck response was, “So what? Everybody does it.” “But,” she responded, “these are scientists.”
Well, the fact is that scientists do it, too. Under pressure for promotions, grants and the necessity to publish, we can be “reasonably assured” that corners are cut, work is sometimes sloppy and, occasionally, I suppose, there is deliberate fraud.
The Second Amendment is silent on the issue of whether the right to keep and bear arms is absolute. Does it guarantee the right to carry loaded weapons into a kindergarten classroom?
In his famous parable, “The Silence of the Sirens,” Franz Kafka tells us that the sirens have a still more fatal weapon than their song, namely their silence. “It is conceivable,” he says, “that someone might possibly have escaped from their singing; but from their silence certainly never.”
That more fatal weapon, silence, is, perhaps, the key to the continuing ambiguity in the interpretation of the Second Amendment.
If the founders had wanted to guarantee “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms” they could have done so in a completely transparent manner: “Congress shall make no laws that infringe on the right of the people to keep and bear arms.” They did not. Why not? Why did they remain silent on so important an issue?
What they did say was: “A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.”
The most natural and unstrained interpretation of this statement is that it concerns the necessity for a “well regulated” militia (a pressing issue at the time) and forbids the government from disarming the militia.
Science and the so-called “scientific method” have been deconstructed and critiqued by many in the humanities. Do we have to redo science or is it okay as it is?
This article based on a talk given at a Partisan Review conference “Breaking Traditions 1896 and 1996”, and subsequently published in Partisan Review, 64(2), in 1997.
As a scientist (a hard scientist with a soft heart) before this audience, I believe it is appropriate to quote a remark made by Ed Bloom, a departed colleague. Once, when addressing the Modern Language Association, Ed said he felt like a lion thrown to the Christians.
I was very much influenced by Freud's writings on psychoanalysis, particularly by his theory of dreams. I didn't believe all of Freud's elaborations, but I thought he touched on concepts that were enormously deep, such as the unconscious, the conscious, and the very powerful interaction between them. It is of great interest to me since biologists and neurophysiologists expect to find the underlying physical correlate for such concepts as the unconscious. For example, we might say that the unconscious is related to stored memory and what is conscious is memory in play.
I seem to remember that Freud believed we would eventually find the biological basis for psychoanalytic concepts. But at the beginning of the past century that time had not arrived. So the best way was to proceed without such a basis. He was right.
The naïve scientific optimism of the nineteenth century has been replaced by cynicism regarding the ability of science to serve mankind. Some blame science for the breakdown of the social order of an idealized past. Does science serve mankind, or does mankind serve science?
This essay is based on a talk given at the opening ceremony of the conference “Science in the Service of Mankind,” Vienna, Austria, July 8-14, 1979.
The scientific optimist who wrote in the 1808 Elements of Natural Philosophy: “The great object of science is to ameliorate the condition of man, by adding to the advantages which he naturally possesses,” is no longer with us. He has been replaced by the environmentalist, the conservationist, the consumer advocate, and the professional demonstrator who criticize every aspect of science and most other human activities – who, regarding the splendor of this gathering and the obvious prosperity of its participants, might suggest that the appropriate question is: Can mankind afford to continue to serve science?
As is evident from the topics covered in this conference, in a material sense science has provided, and continues to provide, solutions for many problems. It is obvious that life as we have come to expect it would not be possible without the material fruits of science.
Can we understand consciousness? Can consciousness be constructed from ordinary materials? The implications would be monumental if it could, but would be no less so if it could not.
This essay is based on an article originally published in Neural Networks, 20(9), in 2007.
Toward the end of his wonderfully productive life, Francis Crick engaged in a search for neural correlates of mental states. At least a glimmer of possible correlates is provided by techniques such as magnetic resonance imaging (MRI); these have been extraordinarily effective in determining regions of the brain involved in various mental activities. An additional glimmer is provided by the remarkable progress that has been made in elucidating the cellular and molecular basis for learning and memory storage. Although these are suggestive of the neural correlates for which Crick was searching and although many words have been expended on possible substrates for mental states, the origin and nature of consciousness, our awareness of ourselves, remains a complete mystery.
The mystery is sufficiently vexing to provoke occasional claims that the problem is not soluble using ordinary scientific methods. I have heard it argued, for example, that consciousness is an epiphenomenon (secondary phenomenon). (I'm not sure what is intended by this argument, except to suggest that consciousness is not really there and so doesn't have to be explained.)