No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Advanced testing of the LoT hypothesis by social reasoning
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 28 September 2023
Abstract
I elaborate on Quilty-Dunn et al.'s integration of the language-of-thought hypothesis in social reasoning by outlining two discrepancies between the experimental paradigms referred to by the authors and the social world: Self-referential projection and deliberate thinking in experiments. Robust tests of the hypothesis in social reasoning should include observational, natural, and cross-cultural approaches.
- Type
- Open Peer Commentary
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press
References
Colman, A. M. (2003). Depth of strategic reasoning in games. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(1), 2–4. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1364-6613(02)00006-2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
De Neys, W. (2022). Advancing theorizing about fast-and-slow thinking. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1–68. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X2200142XGoogle ScholarPubMed
Evans, J. St. B. (2008). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255–278. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093629CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gigerenzer, G. (1996). On narrow norms and vague heuristics: A reply to Kahneman and Tversky. Psychological Review, 103(3), 592–596. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.103.3.592CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grüning, D. J., & Krueger, J. I. (2021). Strategic thinking: A random walk into the rabbit hole. Collabra: Psychology, 7(1), 24921. https://doi.org/10.1525/collabra.24921CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grüning, D. J., & Krueger, J. I. (2022). Strategic thinking in the shadow of self-enhancement: Benefits and costs. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/gtc2mGoogle Scholar
Hedden, T., & Zhang, J. (2002). What do you think I think you think?: Strategic reasoning in matrix games. Cognition, 85(1), 1–36. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(02)00054-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertwig, R., Leuker, C., Pachur, T., Spiliopoulos, L., & Pleskac, T. J. (2022). Studies in ecological rationality. Topics in Cognitive Science, 14(3), 467–491. https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12567CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahneman, D., Slovic, S. P., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I. (2008). From social projection to social behaviour. European Review of Social Psychology, 18(1), 1–35. https://doi.org/10.1080/10463280701284645CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I. (2013). Social projection as a source of cooperation. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22(4), 289–294. https://doi.org/10.1177/0963721413481352CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I., & Grüning, D. J. (2021). Psychological perversities and populism. In Forgas, J. P., Crano, W. D., & Fiedler, K. (Eds.), The psychology of populism (pp. 125–142). Routledge.10.4324/9781003057680-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I., Grüning, D. J., & Heck, P. R. (2023). Inductive reasoning model. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/3yasfGoogle Scholar
Kurdi, B., & Dunham, Y. (2021). Sensitivity of implicit evaluations to accurate and erroneous propositional inferences. Cognition, 214, 104792. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104792CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Orne, M. T. (1962). On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand characteristics and their implications. American Psychologist, 17(11), 776–783. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0043424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarz, N. (1994). Judgment in a social context: Biases, shortcomings, and the logic of conversation. In Zanna, M. P. (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 26, pp. 123–162). Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0065-2601(08)60153-7Google Scholar
Schwarz, N. (1999). Self-reports: How the questions shape the answers. American Psychologist, 54(2), 93–105. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.54.2.93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vranas, P. B. (2000). Gigerenzer's normative critique of Kahneman and Tversky. Cognition, 76(3), 179–193. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(99)00084-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zizzo, D. J. (2010). Experimenter demand effects in economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 13, 75–98. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10683-009-9230-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Target article
The best game in town: The reemergence of the language-of-thought hypothesis across the cognitive sciences
Related commentaries (30)
A language of episodic thought?
Advanced testing of the LoT hypothesis by social reasoning
Animal thought exceeds language-of-thought
Compositionality in visual perception
Concept learning in a probabilistic language-of-thought. How is it possible and what does it presuppose?
Developmental and multiple languages-of-thought
Do nonlinguistic creatures deploy mental symbols for logical connectives in reasoning?
Evidence for LoTH: Slim pickings
Incomplete language-of-thought in infancy
Is core knowledge in the format of LOT?
Is evidence of language-like properties evidence of a language-of-thought architecture?
Is language-of-thought the best game in the town we live?
Language-of-thought hypothesis: Wrong, but sometimes useful?
Linguistic meanings in mind
Linguistic structure and the languages-of-thought
Natural logic and baby LoTH
Neither neural networks nor the language-of-thought alone make a complete game
Never not the best: LoT and the explanation of person-level psychology
On the hazards of relating representations and inductive biases
Perception is iconic, perceptual working memory is discursive
Properties of LoTs: The footprints or the bear itself?
Putting relating at the core of language-of-thought
Representational structures only make their mark over time: A case from memory
Stop me if you've heard this one before: The Chomskyan hammer and the Skinnerian nail
The computational and the representational language-of-thought hypotheses
The language of tactile thought
The language-of-thought as a working hypothesis for developmental cognitive science
The reemergence of the language-of-thought hypothesis: Consequences for the development of the logic of thought
Toward biologically plausible artificial vision
Using the sender–receiver framework to understand the evolution of languages-of-thought
Author response
The language-of-thought hypothesis as a working hypothesis in cognitive science