Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T06:59:51.009Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Addressing genetic essentialism: Sharpening context in behavior genetics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 September 2023

Brian Byrne
Affiliation:
University of New England, Armidale, NSW, Australia [email protected] www.une.edu.au/staff-profiles/hass/bbyrne
Richard K. Olson
Affiliation:
Institute for Behavioral Genetics, University of Colorado, Boulder, CO, USA [email protected] www.colorado.edu/ibg/richard-k-olson

Abstract

Evidence of a causal role for genes in human behavior underpins genetic essentialism, the scientifically flawed and socially hazardous idea that heritable characteristics are immutable. Behavior geneticists can challenge this idea by designing research that brings the contextual dependence of heritability estimates into sharper focus, and by incorporating a relevant statement into research reports and public outreach.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

In their well-argued paper, Madole & Harden take aim at concerns of some scientists that genome-wide association study (GWAS) research will reinforce the idea that inequalities in society are fixed and proper.

They declare that “such a picture…is unwarranted” on the grounds that “genetic causes for human behavioral traits are non-uniform, non-unitary and non-explanatory” (target article, sect. 3.3, para. 4). We agree that the concerns have no scientific bases, but consider that the concerns, and more generally worries about genetic essentialism (Dar-Nimrod & Heine, Reference Dar-Nimrod and Heine2011), are grounded in reality. In this commentary, we explore that reality and suggest ways in which behavioral genetics might address its influence on public discourse and policy.

Genetic essentialism is a family of beliefs centered on the ideas that if genes are known to play a role in shaping human differences then those differences are, to a considerable extent, natural and entrenched. The differences cover not only society-wide structures that license privilege, so-called social Darwinism, but ones expressed in individuals, often enough focused on less favorable outcomes in health and behavior, which are also seen as hard to alter. Admittedly, this pessimism can go hand-in-hand with a sense of relief in that a genetically influenced difficulty can be seen as no-one's “fault.” This is the mixed-blessing model developed by Haslam and Kvaale (Reference Haslam and Kvaale2015). But genetic essentialism can, and does, undermine the acceptance by individuals of efficacious interventions and hamper their implementation by professionals (Haslam & Kvaale, Reference Haslam and Kvaale2015; Lebowitz, Ahn, & Nolen-Hoeksema, Reference Lebowitz, Ahn and Nolen-Hoeksema2013).

We propose two ways that behavior-genetic research community could contribute to combatting genetic essentialism, whose adverse effects are now well documented (Dar-Nimrod & Heine, Reference Dar-Nimrod and Heine2011). One is in the design of the research agenda, the other in public communication of research results. Regarding research: The aphorism that “genes are not destiny” can be, and if possible should be, brought into clear focus by demonstrating its truth within the study of single phenotype. There exist useful demonstrations of different patterns of heritability across groups defined by location (e.g., lower heritability of early reading in Scandinavia compared to the United States and Australia, Samuelsson et al., Reference Samuelsson, Byrne, Olson, Hulslander, Wadsworth, Corley and DeFries2008) and across groups defined by time (e.g., an increase in heritability of educational attainment in Norway for males born after 1940, Heath et al., Reference Heath, Berg, Eaves, Solaas, Corey, Sundet and Nance1985). In addition, demonstrations of gene–environment interplay, where it exists (see Grasby, Coventry, Byrne, & Olson, Reference Grasby, Coventry, Byrne and Olson2019), underline the dependence of some heritability estimates on environmental factors such as socioeconomic level. And in an additional and informative level of complexity, illustrations of different cross-national patterns of gene–environment interaction can deepen insights into environmental influences on phenotypes (Grasby et al., Reference Grasby, Coventry, Byrne and Olson2019; Tucker-Drob & Bates, Reference Tucker-Drob and Bates2016).

Researchers can, and should, also maximize opportunities afforded by analytic maneuvers to expose contextual influences on heritability estimates. For example, in a study using the classical twin design when samples are mixed in terms of location, time, or participant type, the choice to standardize scores within groups can generate higher estimates of genetic influence than the choice of not to standardize. In our cross-national study of early reading (Byrne, Olson, & Samuelsson, Reference Byrne, Olson and Samuelsson2013), Scandinavian children in grade 1 read at a lower average level than those in the United States and Australia, because of the later start of reading instruction in Sweden and Norway. Employing within-country standardization, the genetic influence on reading comprehension was estimated at 0.62; in the absence of within-country standardization, the estimate dropped to 0.38 with a corresponding rise in the shared environment effect. As a thought experiment, imagine a whole-world twin study without country standardization; doubtless the biggest influence on variation in reading ability at any particular age will not be genes but curriculum policies and the resources available for education, showing up in analyses as shared environment. Such a picture would reinforce the value of projects like that of Lyytinen and colleagues (Ojanen et al., Reference Ojanen, Ronimus, Ahonen, Chansa-Kabali, February, Jere-Folotiya and Lyytinen2015), aimed at bringing the benefits of basic reading research to educational practice in less developed nations. Unthinking acceptance of the conclusion, derived from twin studies conducted largely in the United States, Europe, and Australia, that half or more of the variance in reading skill is heritable would tend to undermine efforts like Lyytinen's. Thus, where it is appropriate to privilege a humans in general perspective over humans within particular contexts, analytic choices can be made to do exactly that.

Thus, in designing behavior-genetic research, features that enhance the visibility of context on heritability estimates should be front and center. International cooperation would be one way to promote this goal, in cases at least where there might be reasons to believe that country differences could influence levels and expression of a phenotype. Geneticists working on devising polygenic risk scores for human conditions, especially diseases, may be ahead of behavior geneticists in that there are calls to increase the ancestral diversity of participant groups (Surigo, Williams, & Tishkoff, Reference Surigo, Williams and Tishkoff2019) in response to (a) the predominance of populations with European ancestry in studies to date, and (b) accumulating evidence that scores derived from European samples do not always hold up in predicting disease status in African, Asian, Latino, and other ancestry groups (Belsky et al., Reference Belsky, Moffitt, Sugden, Williams, Houts, McCarthy and Caspi2013; Grinde et al., Reference Grinde, Qibin, Thornton, Simin, Shadyab, Chan and Sofer2019). Behavior genetics would probably replace ancestral groups with sociocultural ones on the grounds that it is those groups that afford the most likely source of contextual influence on patterns of heritability, not ancestry-driven differences in linkage disequilibrium, and in the other sources of variability in polygenic risk score analyses (Surigo et al., Reference Surigo, Williams and Tishkoff2019).

Armed with a substantial corpus of data on contextual dependence of heritability estimates, behavior genetics could develop a core statement to allay the concerns of “end-users” such as educators, clinical psychologists, criminologists, and lawyers that genes are indeed destiny. A group such as the Behavior Genetics Association could be tasked with crafting such a statement, which could then be incorporated, suitably modified for particular circumstances, into research publications and, more generally, into public outreach campaigns.

Acknowledgments

Many colleagues have contributed to the research and ideas incorporated into our commentary; here we acknowledge in particular Stefan Samuelsson, Linköping University, who initiated and led the Scandinavian component of our twin studies.

Financial support

Our research was supported by the Australian Research Council (DP 150102441, DP 0663498, DP 0770805), the National Institute for Child Health and Human Development (P50 HD 27802, R01 HD 38526), the Swedish Research Council (2011-1905), and the Swedish Council for Working Life and Social Research (2011-0177).

Competing interest

None.

References

Belsky, D. W., Moffitt, T. E., Sugden, K., Williams, B., Houts, R., McCarthy, J., & Caspi, A. (2013). Development and evaluation of a genetic risk score for obesity. Biodemography and Social Biology, 59, 85100. doi: doi.org/10.1080/19485565.2013.774628CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Byrne, B., Olson, R. K., & Samuelsson, S. (2013). Subsample standardization in twin studies of academic achievement. In Annual conference of the behavior genetics association, July, Marseilles, France.Google Scholar
Dar-Nimrod, I., & Heine, S. J. (2011). Genetic essentialism: On the deceptive determinism of DNA. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 800818. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0021860.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grasby, K. L., Coventry, W. L., Byrne, B., & Olson, R. K. (2019). Little evidence that socioeconomic status modifies heritability of literacy and numeracy in Australia. Child Development, 90, 623637. doi: 10.111/cdev.12920CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grinde, K. E., Qibin, Q., Thornton, T. A., Simin, L., Shadyab, A. H., Chan, K. H. K., … Sofer, T. (2019). Generalizing polygenic risk scores from Europeans to Hispanics/Latinos. Genetic Epidemiology, 43, 5062. doi: doi.org/10.1002/gepi.2216CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haslam, N., & Kvaale, E. P. (2015). Biogenetic explanations of mental disorder: The mixed-blessings model. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 24, 399404. https://doi.org/10.1177/096372141558808CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, A. C., Berg, K., Eaves, L. J., Solaas, M. H., Corey, L. A., Sundet, J., … Nance, W. E. (1985). Education policy and the heritability of educational attainment. Nature, 314, 734736.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lebowitz, M. S., Ahn, W.-K., & Nolen-Hoeksema, S. (2013). Fixable or fate? Perceptions of the biology of depression. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 81, 518527. https://doi.org/10.1037/a00311730CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ojanen, E., Ronimus, M., Ahonen, T., Chansa-Kabali, T., February, P., Jere-Folotiya, J., … Lyytinen, H. (2015). GraphoGame – A catalyst for multi-level promotion of literacy in diverse contexts. Frontiers in Psychology. 6(671), 113. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00671CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Samuelsson, S., Byrne, B., Olson, R. K., Hulslander, J., Wadsworth, S., Corley, R., … DeFries, J. C. (2008). Response to early literacy instruction in the United States, Australia, and Scandinavia: A behavioral-genetic analysis. Learning and Individual Differences, 18, 289295. doi: doi.org/10.1016/j.lindif.2008.03.004CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Surigo, G., Williams, S. M., & Tishkoff, S. A. (2019). The missing diversity in human genetic studies. Cell, 177, 2631. doi: doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2019.02.048CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tucker-Drob, E. M., & Bates, T. C. (2016). Large cross-national differences in gene × socioeconomic status interaction on intelligence. Psychological Science, 27, 138149. doi: doi.org/10.1177/0956797615612727CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed