Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-02T21:29:49.488Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Selection and Causation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

We have argued elsewhere that natural selection is not a cause of evolution, and that a resolution-of-forces (or vector addition) model does not provide us with a proper understanding of how natural selection combines with other evolutionary influences. These propositions have come in for criticism recently, and here we clarify and defend them. We do so within the broad framework of our own ‘hierarchical realization model’ of how evolutionary influences combine.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bouchard, Frédéric, and Rosenberg, Alex (2004), “Fitness, Probability, and the Principles of Natural Selection”, Fitness, Probability, and the Principles of Natural Selection 55:693712.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert (1978), “Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory”, Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory 9:181206.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert (2006), “The Principle of Drift: Biology's First Law”, The Principle of Drift: Biology's First Law 102:319335.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert, and Ramsey, Grant (2007), “What's Wrong with the Emergentist Statistical Interpretation of Natural Selection and Random Drift?”, in Hull, David and Ruse, Michael (eds.), Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 6684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, David (2008), review of The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology edited by David Hull and Michael Ruse, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=13388.Google Scholar
Fisher, R. A. ([1930] 1999), The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection: A Complete Variorum Edition. Reprint. Edited by Henry Bennett. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter (2007), “Conditions for Evolution by Natural Selection”, Conditions for Evolution by Natural Selection 104:489516.Google Scholar
Hall, Ned (2004), “Two Conceptions of Causation”, in Collins, J., Hall, N., and Paul, L. A. (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 225276.Google Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M., and Woodward, James (1999), “Independence, Invariance, and the Causal Markov Condition”, Independence, Invariance, and the Causal Markov Condition 50:521583.Google Scholar
Lewontin, Richard (1974), The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Matthen, Mohan, and Ariew, André (2002), “Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness and Natural Selection”, Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness and Natural Selection 99:5583.Google Scholar
Millstein, Roberta L. (2002), “Are Random Drift and Natural Selection Conceptually Distinct?”, Are Random Drift and Natural Selection Conceptually Distinct? 17:3353.Google Scholar
Millstein, Roberta L. (2006), “Natural Selection as a Population-Level Causal Process”, Natural Selection as a Population-Level Causal Process 57:627653.Google Scholar
Reisman, K., and Forber, P. (2005), “Manipulation and the Causes of Evolution”, Manipulation and the Causes of Evolution 72:11131123.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex, and Bouchard, Frédéric (2005), “Matthen and Ariew's Obituary for Fitness: Reports of Its Death Have Been Greatly Exaggerated”, Matthen and Ariew's Obituary for Fitness: Reports of Its Death Have Been Greatly Exaggerated 20:343353.Google Scholar
Shapiro, L., and Sober, E. (2007), “Epiphenomenalism: The Dos and the Don’ts”, in Wolters, G. and Machamer, P. (eds.), Thinking about Causes: From Greek Philosophy to Modern Physics. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 235264.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1984), The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stephens, C. (2004), “Selection, Drift, and the ‘Forces’ of Evolution”, Selection, Drift, and the ‘Forces’ of Evolution 71:550570.Google Scholar
Walsh, Denis (1998), “The Scope of Selection: Neander and Sober on What Natural Selection Explains”, The Scope of Selection: Neander and Sober on What Natural Selection Explains 76:250264.Google Scholar
Woodward, James (2003), Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, James (2008), “Causation and Manipulability”, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-mani/.Google Scholar