We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
It is far beyond the scope of these lectures to report on the development of the ideas, first of Restricted, then of General, Relativity and to show how they are logically built on the outcome of a number of crucial experiments, as the aberration of the light of fixed stars, the Michelson-Morley experiment, certain facts regarding the light from visual binary stars, the Eötvös-experiments which ascertained to a marvellously high degree of accuracy the universal character of the gravitational acceleration—that is to say that in a given field it is the same for any test-body of whatever material.
Yet before going into details about the metrical (or Riemannian) continuum, I wish to point out the main trend of thought that suggests choosing such a one as a model of space-time in order to account for gravitation in a purely geometrical way. In this I shall not follow the historical evolution of thought as it actually took place, but rather what it might have been, had the idea of affine connexion already been familiar to the physicist at that time. Actually the general idea of it emerged gradually (in the work of H. Weyl, A. S. Eddington and Einstein) from the special sample of an affinity that springs from a metrical (Riemannian) connexion—emerged only after the latter had gained the widest publicity by the great success of Einstein's 1915 theory. Today, however, it seems simpler and more natural to put the affine connexion, now we are familiar with it, in the foreground, and to arrive at a metric by a very simple specialization thereof.
The subject-matter of the previous chapter is called tensor algebra. It is characterized by the fact that only relations between invariants, vectors or tensors referring to the same point of the continuum are contemplated. From the point of view taken here, algebraic relations between vectors and tensors referring to different points are meaningless.
Remember, however, that we based the notion of tensors on that of vectors, and the latter on the notion of the gradient, and there is hardly any simple and natural alternative to this procedure. Now in forming the gradient we actually had to compare the values of an invariant at different points, and at the same time we made the first step at introducing analysis into our continuum. In this and the following chapters we shall have to extend it. Analysis will involve derivatives and integrals. We shall have to study both from the point of view of general invariance. However, this does not mean to look out only for invariants, but also for entities with tensorial character, because, as we have seen, an equation between them (or in other words a system of equations saying that a tensor vanishes) is conserved on transformation. We begin with space-time-integrals. That leads to a certain extension of the notion of tensors, viz. to tensor densities.
We had emphasized that there is no point in adding (or, more generally, in forming linear aggregates of) tensors or vectors referring to different points. This would have no simple meaning.
We have seen how convenient it is to regulate the UV divergences of perturbation theory by continuation in the dimension of space-time. To date, no-one has shown how to use the method in the complete theory. But in perturbation theory, as we will now demonstrate, it is consistent and well-defined. Now all results obtained by this method can be obtained by other, more physical methods (say, a lattice regulator). But frequently much more labor is involved. This is not a triviality, for in complicated situations, especially in gauge theories, it enables us to handle the technicalities of renormalization in a simple way.
The idea of dimensional continuation has been used for a long time in statistical mechanics (see, for example, Fisher & Gaunt (1964)). It became very prominent when Wilson & Fisher (1972) discovered the ε-expansion and applied it to field-theoretic methods in statistical mechanics (Wilson (1973), Mack (1972), and Wilson & Kogut (1974)). In the ε-expansion one works in 4 — ε spatial dimensions, and expands in powers of ε. At the same time, in a purely field-theoretic context, a need arose to find a way of regulating non-abelian gauge theories that preserved gauge invariance and Poincaré invariance. This led to dimensional regularization ('t Hooft & Veltman (1972a), Bollini & Giambiagi (1972), Cicuta & Montaldi (1972), and Ashmore (1972)).
In Chapter 2 we met a number of equations involving products of field operators at the same point. Examples are given by the equations of motion (2.1.10) and the Ward identities (2.7.6). These products we will call composite operators. When computed directly they have ultra-violet divergences: the product ø(x)ø(y) makes unambiguous sense if x is not equal to y, but if x equals y then we have ø(x)2, which diverges. Since the equations of motion and the Ward identities express fundamental properties of the theory, it is useful to construct finite, renormalized composite operators with which to express these same properties.
It could be argued that there is no need to have renormalized equations of motion. One could say that one only actually needs the equations of motion in the regulated theory, where they are finite. A situation of practical importance where we actually do need renormalized composite operators is the operator-product expansion, to be discussed in Chapter 10. This is used in a phenomenological situation such as deep-inelastic scattering (Chapter 14) where we wish to compute the behavior of a Green's function when some of its external momenta get large. Equivalently, we need to know how a product of operators, like ø(x)ø(y), behaves as x → y.
The structure of a quantum field theory often simplifies when one considers processes involving large momenta or short distances. These simplifications are important in improving one's ability to calculate predictions from the theory, and in essence form the subject of this book.
The first simplification to be considered involves the very existence of the theory. The problem is that there are usually ultra-violet divergences caused by large fluctuations of the field(s) on short distance scales. These manifest themselves in Feynman graphs as divergences when loop momenta go to infinity with the external momenta fixed. The simplification is that the divergences can be cancelled by renormalizations of the parameters of the action. Consequently our first task will be to treat the ultra-violet renormalizations. Renormalization is essential, for otherwise most field theories do not exist.
We will then expose the methods needed to handle high-energy/short-distance problems. The aim is to be able to make testable predictions from a strong interaction theory, or to improve the rate of convergence of the perturbation expansion in a weakly coupled theory. The simplifications generally take the form of a factorization of a cross-section or of an amplitude, each factor containing the dependence of the process on phenomena that happen on one particular distance scale.
A characteristic feature of relativistic quantum field theories is that symmetries of the classical theory are not always present after quantization. We do not mean here the spontaneous breaking that is characterized by a non-invariant vacuum and by the presence of the Goldstone bosons. Rather we mean a situation where there is no conserved current for the symmetry despite the absence of any terms in the action that appear to break the symmetry. Such breaking of a symmetry is called anomalous.
If the classical action is invariant, then a naive application of Noether's theorem gives us a conserved current. That is, there is no anomalous symmetry breaking. What prevents the argument from being correct is the presence of UV divergences. The current is a composite operator, i.e., a product of elementary fields at the same point, and to define it, some kind of regularization and renormalization is needed. The renormalization may invalidate the equations used to prove Noether's theorem.
For simplicity, we will consider only global symmetries, as opposed to local, or gauge, symmetries. The simplest cases of global symmetries were considered in Chapter 9. These could be treated by using an ultra-violet regulator that preserved the symmetry. The proof of Noether's theorem can then be made in the cut-off theory.
In this chapter we come to the general theory of renormalization. The basic difficulty is that a graph may not only possess an overall divergence. It may have in addition many subdivergences which can be nested or can overlap in very complicated ways. Most of our effort must go to disentangling these complications.
We will begin by investigating some simple graphs. These will show us how to set up the formalism in the general case. The ultimate result is the forest formula of Zimmermann (1969). Contrary to its reputation, this is not an esoteric procedure, designed for pedantically rigorous treatments. Rather, the forest formula is merely a general way of writing down what is in fact the natural and obvious way of extracting the divergences from any integral. Its power is demonstrated by the ease of treating overlapping divergences, the handling of which is normally considered the bête noire of renormalization theory.
The forest formula is applied to individual Feynman graphs. It extracts the finite part of a graph by subtracting its overall divergence and its subdivergences. We will, of course, need to show that the subtractions can be implemented as actual counterterms in the Lagrangian. We will also show that the counterterms are local, i.e., polynomial in momentum.
A common situation in physics is that in investigating phenomena on a certain distance scale, one sees no hint of those phenomena that happen at much shorter distance scales. In a classical situation this observation seems evident. For example, one can treat fluid dynamics without any knowledge of the atomic physics that generates the actual properties of the fluids. However, in a quantum field theory this decoupling of short-distance phenomena from long-distance phenomena is not self-evident at all.
Consider an e+ — e- annihilation experiment at a center-of-mass energy well below 10GeV, the threshold for making hadrons containing the b-quark. There is, for practical (or experimental) purposes, no trace of the existence of this quark. However, the quark is present in Feynman graphs as a virtual particle, and can have an apparently significant effect on cross-sections. Our task in this chapter is therefore to prove what is known as the decoupling theorem. This states that a Feynman graph containing a propagator for a field whose mass is much greater than the external momenta of the graph is in fact suppressed by a power of the heavy mass. The physics at low energy is described by an effective low-energy theory that is obtained by deleting all heavy fields from the original theory.
It is important to show that renormalization of a gauge theory can be accomplished without violating its gauge invariance. Gauge invariance is physically important; among other things it is used (via the Ward identities) to show that the unphysical states decouple ('t Hooft (1971a)).
In Chapter 9 we considered the case that the basic Lagrangian of a theory is invariant under a global symmetry, as opposed to a gauge symmetry, such as we will be investigating in this chapter. We showed that the counterterm Lagrangian is also invariant under the symmetry. Suppose now that the basic Lagrangian is invariant under a gauge symmetry. One might suppose that the counterterms are also invariant under the symmetry, just as for a global symmetry. This is not true, however, since the introduction of gauge fixing (as explained in Sections 2.12 and 2.13) destroys manifest gauge invariance of the Lagrangian. One might instead point out that the theory with gauge fixing is BRS invariant and deduce that the counterterms are BRS invariant. This deduction is false. To see this, we recall that an ordinary internal symmetry relates Green's functions with certain external fields to other Green's functions differing only by change of symmetry labels. However, BRS symmetry relates a field to a composite field (2.13.1).