We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
I do believe that one can discern general themes in the history of discovery in science and I shall even venture to mention some, but mainly for the purpose of emphasizing variety over uniformity.
Abraham Pais, 1986
Useful as the tripartite structure of detection, interpretation, and understanding is in appreciating the extended structure of discovery, we are far from showing that this is the only structure of discovery in astronomy, much less in science. In fact, we should be skeptical of such a simple view that a single structure is universal to all types of discovery. After all, we have seen that some classes (gas giant planets, giant and dwarf stars) have been inferred over very long periods rather than detected, while others (dwarf planets) have been suddenly declared. And as we saw in the last chapter, the discovery of new classes of astronomical objects is only one of many categories of discovery that historians and philosophers of science, ranging from Norwood Russell Hanson to Theodore Arabatzis, have distinguished.
Scientists themselves have cautioned against simplifying what they as practitioners recognize as a complex process. Referring to Thomas Kuhn’s attempts to find structure in the strikingly numerous discoveries from 1895 to 1905, including the contributions of Roentgen, Bohr, Planck, Einstein, Becquerel, Thomson, and Rutherford, the theoretical physicist Abraham Pais wrote that “Such facile and sweeping generalizations only serve to create serious pitfalls of simplicity. I do believe that one can discern general themes in the history of discovery in science and I shall even venture to mention some, but mainly for the purpose of emphasizing variety over uniformity. After decades spent in the midst of the fray I am more than ever convinced, however, that a search for all-embracing principles of discovery makes about as much sense as looking for the crystal structure of muddied waters.” In short, Pais confessed to “very strong reservations concerning the usefulness, let alone the necessity, of a search for general patterns or laws of history, specifically the history of discovery.”
Having dismissed earthly things, I applied myself to the exploration of the heavens.
Galileo, 1610
If ever a discoverer was perfectly prepared to make and exploit his discovery, it was the dexterous humanist Galileo aiming his first telescope at the sky.
Heilbron, 2010
I have announced this star as a comet; but the fact that the star is not accompanied by any nebulosity and that its movement is so slow and rather uniform, has caused me many times to seriously consider that perhaps it might be something better than a comet. I would be very careful, however, about making this conjecture public.
Giuseppe Piazzi, 1801
With the exception of Tycho Brahe’s proof in 1577 that comets were celestial phenomena based on their parallax and thus distance, and his inference that the stella nova of 1572 was celestial based on its lack of parallax, the problem of the discovery and interpretation of new classes of astronomical objects begins substantially with Galileo and the telescopic era 400 years ago. Galileo’s telescopic observations revealed what we would today recognize as two new classes of astronomical objects: moons around Jupiter and rings around Saturn. And while Galileo and his contemporaries soon realized the nature of the moons of Jupiter by analogy to our own Moon, the story of Saturn’s rings is much more complicated.
As we shall see, both Jupiter’s moons and Saturn’s rings stand as early examples of what would become commonplace in astronomy: that “seeing” isn’t always “knowing,” that “detection” does not constitute “discovery,” that recognizing a new class of astronomical objects can be a difficult and multifaceted endeavor. In this chapter we begin to dissect the process of discovery in astronomy, in particular as it applies to the discovery of new classes of objects. We shall find it to be a complex and extended series of events consisting most often of at least three components: detection, interpretation, and understanding. This is particularly true of new classes of objects when the observer may have no idea of the true nature of the object. Again and again astronomers ran up against the unexpected in their reconnaissance of the heavens. Their struggle to move beyond mere detection, to enter the difficult realm of interpretation, and to seek physical understanding – often long after the original detection – is a story that has only been told piecemeal, but that deserves systematic treatment because it represents the core of astronomy and the natural history of the heavens.
The title of this volume will bring to mind for some readers Martin Harwit’s book Cosmic Discovery: The Search, Scope, and Heritage of Astronomy, published more than three decades ago. As an astronomer, Harwit’s practical aims in that book were twofold: first, to determine what fields of astronomy have the largest number of potential discoveries and, second, to explore what fields of astronomy might promise the most immediate advances and striking returns. By analyzing just enough history to answer these questions, Harwit hoped to provide answers of use both to students entering the field facing the daunting question of what part of astronomy to study and to policymakers who had only limited resources to dole out for the advancement of astronomy. In this effort at applied history he had only mixed success, but by taking the concept of discovery as a serious object of analysis, Harwit did what only very few astronomers, historians, or philosophers have done before or since. While it will become clear that I differ with Harwit on many issues, not least the crucial question of what constitutes a new “class” of object, I record here my debt to him, and others, for their boldness in attacking a concept so broad as “discovery.”
It will be at once remarked, that the spiral arrangement so strongly developed in 51 Messier, is traceable, more or less distinctly, in several of the sketches ... we are in the habit of calling all objects spirals in which we have detected a curvilinear arrangement not consisting of regular re-entering curves; it is convenient to class them under a common name, though we have not the means of proving that they are similar systems.
William Parsons, Third Earl of Rosse, 1850
Extremely little is known of the nature of nebulae, and no significant classification has yet been suggested; not even a precise definition has been formulated.
Edwin Hubble, 1917
It was on February 5, 1963 that the puzzle was suddenly resolved . . . I noticed that four of the six lines exhibited increasing spacing and strength toward the red . . . I started taking the ratio of the wavelength of each line to that of the nearest Balmer line. The first ratio was 1.16, the second 1.16, the third . . . 1.16! . . . Clearly, a redshift of 0.16 explained all the observed emission lines! The extraordinary implications of a “star” of 13th magnitude having a redshift of 0.16 were immediately clear.
Maarten Schmidt, 1983
Unlike the realms of the planets and stars, long distinguished by the “wanderers” moving among the fixed stars, the realm of the galaxies had to be discovered. Curiously, however, some of its members had been detected long before they were known to be outside our stellar system. As we saw in Chapter 3, a few objects such as Andromeda and the Magellanic Clouds had long been seen with the naked eye, and in the eighteenth century Charles Messier and William Herschel detected numerous fuzzy objects catalogued as “nebulae.” But these nebulae were largely believed to be in the realm of the stars, as indeed many of them were. How it was determined that some comprised separate systems of stars far beyond our own is a storied part of the history of astronomy, approached in this chapter through the lens of discovery and its complexities. Despite prescient early guesses and some more scientific inferences, it was only Edwin Hubble in the early twentieth century who provided definitive proof that “extragalactic” objects existed beyond our own Milky Way Galaxy.
If both observation and conceptualization, fact and assimilation to theory, are inseparably linked in discovery, then discovery is a process and must take time.
Thomas Kuhn, 1962
The idea of discovery is conceptually too complex for any “average” historical, psychological, or sociological analysis. Put more controversially, settling on the meaning of “discovery” is too important to our understanding of science to be abandoned to scientific discoverers or to psychologists or to sociologists or to historians of science. Conceptual analysis is important enough to be pursued by conceptual analysts, and not just given over to fact-gatherers.
Norwood Russell Hanson, 1967
Epistemologically the problem [of the nature of discovery] is insoluble from an individualistic point of view. If any discovery is to be made accessible to investigation, the social point of view must be adopted; that is, the discovery must be regarded as a social event.
Ludwik Fleck, 1935
Discovery is not an atomized contribution to knowledge that others need merely recognize and accept, but rather represents a retrospective characterization of a complex process of transformative negotiation, characterization that simultaneously formalizes the essential character of the discovery and confers upon it the stamp of objectivity as, by implication, an aspect of the physical world that was there waiting to be “discovered.”
The first step in wisdom is to know the things themselves. This notion consists in having a true idea of the objects; objects are distinguished and known by classifying them methodologically and giving them appropriate names. Therefore, classification and name-giving will be the foundation of our science.
Linnaeus, 1735
The initial classifier of any unknown subject necessarily begins with no idea of how to choose the key parameters. How then to produce a classification imbued with any fundamental physical significance or predictive power?
Allan Sandage, 2004
The MK system [for stellar classification] has no authority whatever; it has never been adopted as an official system by the International Astronomical Union – or by any other astronomical organization. Its only authority lies in its usefulness; if it is not useful, it should be abandoned.
W. W. Morgan, 1979
In contrast to the discovery of new laws, processes, or properties, one of the hallmarks of the discovery of localizable natural objects such as we have been discussing in this volume is an almost irresistible temptation to classify them. A new object will barely have been discovered before the human mind tries to determine where it “fits” in the order of things already known. This is undoubtedly an ancient instinct, and one of the basic characteristics of a developing and even a mature science, as basic to astronomy as it is to biology, geology, chemistry, and physics. To put it another way, the recognition of new classes and their classification is an integral part of natural history, and a particularly challenging activity when the discovery involves a new class of objects. The origin of the categories in which we think is a question rarely raised except in the rarefied reaches of philosophy, but it goes to the core of discovery. In discovery it may flare briefly and sporadically, as in the case of Pluto, or at more sustained length as in the case of stellar luminosity types. But once routine, the origin of the categories is often forgotten, even as they determine the way we think of things.
This method of viewing the heavens seems to throw them into a new kind of light. They now are seen to resemble a luxuriant garden, which contains the greatest variety of productions, in different flourishing beds; and one advantage we may at least reap from it is, that we can, as it were, extend the range of our experience to an immense duration. For, to continue the simile I have borrowed from the vegetable kingdom, is it not almost the same thing, whether we live successively to witness the germination, blooming, foliage, fecundity, fading, withering, and corruption of a plant, or whether a vast number of specimens, selected from every stage through which the plant passes in the course of its existence, be brought at once to our view?
William Herschel, 1789
Nothing seems to be more important philosophically than the revelation that the evolutionary drive, which has in recent years swept over the whole field of biology, also includes in its sweep the evolution of galaxies and stars, and comets and atoms, and indeed all things material.
Harlow Shapley, 1967
Throughout this volume we have witnessed many narratives of discovery, each groundbreaking in its own way. But one of the greatest achievements of the twentieth century was synthesizing these discoveries into one great master narrative, itself constituting a great discovery. That master narrative is cosmic evolution, the story of the universe from its beginning with the Big Bang 13.7 billion years ago stretching down to the present moment when evolution still continues. The discovery of cosmic evolution was foreshadowed by the luxuriant gardens of William Herschel, who recognized already in the late eighteenth century that individual celestial objects at varying stages of development allow us to “extend the range of our experience to an immense duration.”
It is hardly exaggerated to say that the spectral classification now adopted is of similar value as a botany, which divide the flowers according to their size and color. To neglect the c-properties in classifying stellar spectra is nearly the same thing as if the zoologist, who has detected the deciding differences between a whale and a fish, would continue in classifying them together.
Ejnar Hertzsprung, 1908
There seem, therefore to be two series of stars, one very bright and of almost the same brightness, whatever the spectrum, the other diminishing rapidly in brightness with increasing redness ... These series were first noticed by Dr. Hertzsprung, of Potsdam, and called by him “giant” and “dwarf” stars.
Henry Norris Russell, 1913
The message of the Companion of Sirius, when decoded, ran: “I am composed of material 3,000 times denser than anything you have come across; a ton of my material would be a little nugget you could put in a matchbox.” What reply can one make to such a message? The reply which most of us made in 1914 was – “Shut up. Don’t talk nonsense.”
Arthur S. Eddington, 1927
As historian David DeVorkin has written, by the early twentieth century, American astrophysicists were becoming world leaders in astronomical natural history thanks to the unparalleled power of astrophysics to reveal the nature of celestial bodies. “Akin to the naturalist, the typical American professional astronomer was collector and classifier. Instead of museum shelves and cases, astronomers stored their systematic observations in plate vaults and letterpress log books, and displayed them in catalogues sponsored by universities and observatories.” In particular, as more and more stellar spectra were gathered, they hinted at numerous variations in the nature of the stars. Once stellar physics was understood later in the twentieth century the reasons became clear: stellar structure depended on mass, temperature, and luminosity, and the range of all of these physical variables was enormous. Moreover, stars existed in a variety of different ages, and (it turned out) in a variety of stages. Stars were born, lived, and died; once the concept of stellar evolution was accepted, the problem was determining which stars were in which stages and how the physics worked under varying conditions, among the greatest puzzles in the history of science. In short, William Herschel’s gardens, first explored with his work on the nebulae, were luxuriant beyond his wildest dreams when it came to the stars themselves.
It would have been fairer, and would send a less distorted message about how this kind of science is actually done, if the [Nobel] award had been made collectively to all members of the two groups [for the discovery of the accelerating universe].
Martin Rees, 2012
Agreeing on what constitutes discovery and assessing the process by which discovery occurs and is accepted are an integral part of accelerating discovery.
Robert Williams
The Natural History of Discovery
Our natural history of discovery in this volume, analogous to the natural history of the heavens that astronomers have undertaken over the last 400 years, has uncovered some surprising conclusions. Focusing on new classes of astronomical objects – defined in our study by those eighty-two objects listed in Appendices 1 and 2 and as discussed in Chapter 8 – we have found that the discovery of virtually every class of object displays an extended structure. Thomas Kuhn and others foreshadowed such a structure already fifty years ago, but unlike Kuhn’s anatomy of discovery, which involved anomaly, paradigms, a distinction between normal and revolutionary science, and a subordination of discovery to the concept of revolutions, we place discovery at center stage in science. We find a macrostructure consisting most often of detection, interpretation, and understanding, and a microstructure involving not only the nuanced problems of those three stages and their conceptual content, but also social and technical elements.
But what a field of novelty is here opened to our conceptions! A shining fluid, of a brightness sufficient to reach us from the remote regions of a star of the 8th, 9th, 10th, 11th or 12th magnitude, and of an extent so considerable as to take up 3, 4, 5, or 6 minutes in diameter! Perhaps it has been too hastily surmised that all milky nebulosity, of which there is so much in the heavens, is owing to starlight only.
William Herschel, 1791
Here in dividing the different parts of which the sidereal heavens are composed into proper classes, I shall have to examine the nature of the various celestial objects that have been hitherto discovered, in order to arrange them in a manner most comfortable to their construction.
William Herschel, 1802
If discovery in the realm of the planets was difficult, in the realm of the stars the problems were only multiplied. While Pluto, representing the outer edge of the solar system as it was known in 1930, was about forty times the distance of the Earth from the Sun (40 astronomical units, or 4 billion miles), the nearest star was 25 trillion miles, a factor of nearly 7000 times more distant. Put another way, rather than light minutes or light hours for the planets, the nearest stellar distances were measured in light-years, and the more distant ones in hundreds or thousands of light-years. Whereas a light beam from Pluto would take a few hours to travel to Earth, the nearest starlight (other than our own Sun!) would take 4.2 years. In terms of distance, astronomers studying the stars clearly entered a new realm in discovery and interpretation when it came to techniques of observation and methods of inference.
Astronomers at the time, however, knew little about the distances they were dealing with. The fixed stars of time immemorial notwithstanding, so-called sidereal astronomy did not become an important part of astronomy until the eighteenth century, when observers such as the French astronomers Nicholas-Louis de la Caille and Charles Messier focused on objects in the realm of the stars, and especially when William Herschel began using his newly constructed large telescopes in England. The Copernican theory implied vast stellar distances, but those distances remained unknown until 1838 with the first determinations of stellar parallax, and even then only the distances to the nearest stars could be measured. A few years earlier Auguste Comte famously highlighted the composition of the stars as the very prototype of a problem that could never be solved. But the development of spectroscopy in the 1850s and 1860s enabled just that, a stunning feat in the annals of human thought that unlocked the secrets of the sidereal realm – but only slowly and grudgingly.
On August 24, 2006, the International Astronomical Union (IAU) – the only institution that counts when it comes to official designations of astronomical bodies – declared that Pluto was not a planet. More specifically, astronomers demoted Pluto from a planet to a dwarf planet, and (to the chagrin of many scientists and the confusion of the general public) declared that a dwarf planet was not a planet all, thus reducing the number of classical planets in the solar system to eight for the first time since 1930 when Pluto was discovered. Pluto’s demotion not only meant a rewriting of the textbooks, but also set off a surprisingly intense scientific and public outcry – an interesting cultural phenomenon indicating not only the importance of classification to scientists, but also a deeper investment in astronomy among the general public than one might have thought.
As a longtime member of the IAU, I was among those voting on that fateful day in Prague. Although I had attended every triennial IAU General Assembly since 1988, many of them as an officer in its History of Astronomy Commission, I had never seen the meeting dominated by a single issue as it was on this occasion. Though literally hundreds of sessions were held over the two weeks of the meeting, discussing a broad panoply of astronomical subjects, and though numerous other resolutions were considered and passed at this General Assembly, the resolutions involving Pluto were the center of attention, the subject of numerous sessions, and the topic of the buzz in the hallways. As was tradition, the resolutions were voted on during the last day of the General Assembly, after much discussion the previous two weeks, leaving only 424 delegates to vote out of the thousands who had attended.
As explained in Section 8.2, Appendix 1 constitutes an exercise in constructing a comprehensive classification system for astronomy. The “Three Kingdom” system begins with the three Kingdoms of planets, stars, and galaxies – the three canonical divisions adopted in textbooks for almost a century, since it became clear that galaxies were indeed a separate “realm of the nebulae,” as Hubble put it. For each Kingdom six astronomical Families are then delineated, based on the object’s origin (Proto-), location (Circum- and Inter-), subsidiary status (Sub-), and tendency to form systems (Systems), in addition to the “Central” Family (planet, star, or galaxy) with respect to which the other Families are defined. These considerations give rise to astronomy’s eighteen Families, and the symmetry of the six Families of each Kingdom reflects their physical basis in gravity’s action in all three Kingdoms. The system then distinguishes eighty-two classes of objects, a large subset of which are the subject of this volume.
Like biology, the Three Kingdom (3K) system is hierarchical, extending from Kingdom to Family to Class, with the possible extension to further categories lower in the hierarchy such as Type and Subtype. As in biological classification it occasionally adds an intermediate Subfamily level wherever useful. With the benefit of hindsight (and with utility in mind), the system incorporates some classes as they have historically been defined, and adds others as they might be defined in a coherent and consistent system. The criterion adopted for class status is, wherever possible, the physical nature of the object, rather than orbital, dynamical, temperature, morphological, spectral, or any other characteristics. Some of the principles of classification are discussed in Section 8.2.