We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Pseudo-science…has grown and flourished until, nowadays, it is becoming somewhat rampant. It has…an army of ‘reconcilers’, enlisted in its service, whose business seems to be to mix the black of dogma and the white of science into the neutral tint of what they call liberal theology.
T.H. Huxley, 1887
Only those who could inject spiritual dimensions into Darwinism could directly come to terms with it. For others, Darwinism produced conflicts in which the real issue was frequently obscured. In essence, one can say that Darwinism could be reinterpreted or transformed.
John Dillenberger
In the polemical world of T. H. Huxley liberal reconcilers of Christianity and evolution could be nothing but an ‘army’ bent on blending scientific truth with theological error. Their exploits were simply ‘pseudo-science’, the neutralising of issues as plain as black and white. Huxley was of course mistaken, though his caricature has persisted in a military metaphor. The reconcilers did not always confront clear-cut issues, much less did they blur them. One might well argue that they ‘engaged the advance lines of the realistic modern mind’, but to chide them for a ‘strange insensitiveness to all the implications of science’ and for a delusive belief that they had ‘made contributory to their faith the grand army of scientific inquiry’ seems altogether unjust. Scientists themselves, most of whom were overtly religious, could hardly agree on the theological ‘implications’ of their theories. The ‘grand army of scientific inquiry’ never did exist.
Species have been modified, during a long course of descent, … chiefly through the natural selection of numerous successive, slight, favourable variations; aided in an important manner by the inherited effects of the use and disuse of parts; and in an unimportant manner, that is in relation to adaptive structures, whether past or present, by the direct action of external conditions, and by variations which seem to us in our ignorance to arise spontaneously. It appears that I formerly underrated the frequency and value of these latter forms of variation, as leading to permanent modifications of structure independently of natural selection. But as my conclusions have lately been much misrepresented, and it has been stated that I attribute the modification of species exclusively to natural selection, I may be permitted to remark that in the first edition of this work, and subsequently, I placed in a most conspicuous position – namely, at the close of the Introduction – the following words: ‘I am convinced that natural selection has been the main but not the exclusive means of modification.’ This has been of no avail. Great is the power of steady misrepresentation; but the history of science shows that fortunately this power does not long endure.
Charles Darwin
If there is but one passage in all Darwin's publications that set the stage for the discussion of evolutionary theory in the closing decades of the nineteenth century, it is this paragraph from the conclusion to the last edition of the Origin of Species (1872).
For one hundred years it has been fashionable to employ military metaphors to characterise the religious debates over evolution in the later nineteenth century. Implicit in this historiography of ‘conflict’ and ‘warfare’ is the positivistic assumption that science and metaphysics, evolutionary theory and Christian theology, can or should be divorced. This book undertakes a revision of the received historiography by describing its polemical origins and baneful effects and by offering an interpretation of Protestant responses to Darwin that shows their affinities with the metaphysical and theological traditions from which Darwinism and post-Darwinian evolutionary thought derived.
In offering a non-violent interpretation of the post-Darwinian controversies this study supports and enlarges the standard revisionist thesis that Christian theology has been congenial to the development of modern science. What M. B. Foster, R. K. Merton, and R. Hooykaas inter alia have argued concerning the rise of physical science and technology in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries – namely, that the Christian (and especially the Reformed) doctrine of a contingent creation, ordered and superintended by a perpetual Providence, has led to the adoption of empirical methods in science and the extension of causo-mechanical explanations of nature – is here applied to the rise and spread of theories of biological evolution in the later nineteenth century.
[Darwin's ‘Origin of Species’] was badly received by the generation to which it was addressed. … But the present generation will probably behave just as badly if another Darwin should arise, and inflict upon them that which the generality of mankind most hate – the necessity of revising their convictions. Let them, then, be charitable to us ancients. … Let them as speedily perform a strategic right-about-face, and follow the truth wherever it leads It may be, that, as history repeats itself, their happy ingenuity will…discover that the new wine is exactly of the same vintage as the old, and that (rightly viewed) the old bottles prove to have been expressly made for holding it.
T. H. Huxley
It is an agreeable irony that T. H. Huxley, the incubus of late- Victorian theology, concluded his pioneering essay, ‘On the reception of the “Origin of Species”’, with an allusion to the biblical metaphor of wine and wineskins. It is at once more ironic and less agreeable that in this context he obliquely credited the ‘happy ingenuity’ of his generation for discovering that the new Darwinian wine was of the same vintage as older causo-mechanical explanations of natural phenomena, and thus that older theological bottles, ‘rightly viewed’, had been made expressly to contain it. Less agreeable, this latter irony, because it violates most of the preconceptions which, until quite recently, have been fostered by accounts of Christian responses to Darwin in the later nineteenth century.
The biological theorist took for his central problem the question of the mutability of organic species and the conditions of their origin. The philosopher of science, on the other hand, proposed to cover a broader field, seeking to trace out not simply the course of biological development, but the evolution of the entire phenomenal universe from star-dust up to mind and social life. The aim of the one is a theory of species, of the other a doctrine of cosmical progress. … The theory of Darwin accounts for the genesis of natural kinds through adaptation to environment in virtue of natural selection under the conditions of the struggle for existence.
Spencer's ‘synthetic system’ explains the world and life on the basis of ‘the continuous redistribution of matter and motion’. Darwinism acquires a bearing on fundamental problems because of its relations, for in itself it is no more than the first principle of a special department of science. The Spencerian philosophy … is so inclusive in its scope that the synthesis undertaken involves from time to time the transcending of the limits of phenomenal inquiry.
A. C. Armstrong
Britain's leading Lamarckian was Herbert Spencer (1820–1903). His System of Synthetic Philosophy (1860–96) set forth a physical law which determined the evolution of ‘definite, coherent heterogeneity’ throughout the universe; his life-work proceeded from beginning to end on the assumption that biological adaptation occurs primarily through the inherited effects of environment and habit.
Ideals may well be theoretically divided into good and bad, into superior and inferior, but men – and the actual battle is one of men against men – cannot be thus divided and set off against one another. … Each one of them contains within himself in varying degree the true and the false, the high and the low, spirit and matter.
Benedetto Croce
Metaphors are indispensable figures of speech. By them the abstract is made concrete, the dull and dead is recreated with interest and vivacity, and the complex is cast in recollectable form. What would literature be without the elaborate metaphors of Dante's Commedia and Bunyan's Pilgrim's Progress, the enchanting allegories of George MacDonald and C. S. Lewis, and the evocative modern parables in Abbott's Flatland and Orwell's Animal Farm? Likewise metaphors, or ‘models’, are vital to the scientific enterprise. Without the model of ocean waves Huygens might not have formulated the wave theory of light; without the ‘billiard ball’ model of molecular collisions, the kinetic theory of gases would be difficult to explain; and apart from Bohr's planetary model of the atom, the development of atomic theory could have been greatly retarded.
Yet particular metaphors are always dispensable, if not in literature, whose themes are eternal, then in science and the philosophy of science, where discovery and understanding are often contingent on the model or metaphor employed. Thus Darwin acknowledged that the term ‘natural selection’, which he conceived by analogy with the ‘artificial selection’ of breeders, was less satisfactory than Herbert Spencer's phrase, ‘the survival of the fittest’, after Alfred Russel Wallace pointed out that this was ‘the plain expression of the fact’.
Natural selection…replaces a transcendental explanation with a natural one. To be sure, it does not explain force, and thus leaves the whole subject shrouded in as deep fundamental mysticism as ever. But science does not hope to explain force and power, and will be satisfied to account for natural phenomena by…natural forces acting in accordance with natural laws. Natural selection was a great step in this direction.
H. W. Conn
Evolution has not taken place by the action of ‘Natural Selection’ alone, but…partly, perhaps mainly, through laws which may be most conveniently spoken of as special powers and tendencies existing in each organism; and partly through influences exerted on each such organism by surrounding conditions and agencies organic and inorganic, terrestrial and cosmical, among which the ‘survival of the fittest’ plays a certain but subordinate part.
St George Mivart
The last of Darwin's works directly concerned with organic evolution was the Descent of Man. From the time of its publication until his death in 1882 Darwin occupied himself with long-standing researches which served to illustrate the broader significance of his theory. The first and last fruits of his labour – The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (1872) and The Formation of Vegetable Mould through the Action of Worms, with Observations on Their Habits (1881) – had a psychological interest. Other volumes reported his work on plants: Insectivorous Plants (1875), The Movements and Habits of Climbing Plants (1875), The Effects of Cross and Self Fertilisation in the Vegetable Kingdom (1876), and The Different Forms of Flowers on Plants of the Same Species (1877).
When one discusses Darwinism, to what does one refer? Is it a theoretical Darwinism, … what Neo-Darwinism retained or adapted from Darwin? Or is it the historical Darwinism, with its doubts, its retractions, its concessions to critics, from the first edition of the Origin of Species to the ‘Essay on Instinct’? … [Would it not be] simpler to start with Darwin himself and what he wrote than with an imaginary Darwinism whose existence in the realm of ideas creates unnecessary difficulties?
Jacques Roger
The works of Charles Darwin (1809–1882) have been cited more frequently than read, and read far more often than understood. Religious reactionaries and the sycophants of scientism have alike forced Darwin to serve their dubious ends, while even persons of moderation have represented as Darwinism either more or less than the primary texts allow. Under these circumstances, which have only lately begun to change, a just understanding of Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection must be founded on Darwin's statement of it. Fortunately, there is at least one passage in the Origin of Species that remained substantially unaltered throughout the book's six editions (1859–72), which distils the essence of Darwinism into less than five hundred words.
PALEY. May I, without impertinence, Mr Darwin, inquire in what sort of estimation you were held among the orthodox Christians of your time?
DARWIN. I hardly know how to answer your question. I enjoyed the friendship of many of them, and incurred, so far as I am aware, the ill will of none. Why should I, indeed? I never assailed their doctrines.
PALEY. But was not the Christian world alarmed by your speculations? Did it not protest against them? Had your contemporaries grown wiser than the Apostle, and did they believe that all danger from philosophy falsely so called had passed away?
DARWIN. No; but they thought, I imagine, that philosophy falsely so called could be exposed as false.
If ever there was a contradiction in terms it must surely have been Christian Darwinism. What concourse could a mere theory of biological development have with a religion which proclaimed God to be Maker of heaven and earth? What constructive relationship could possibly subsist between a theory which taught the survival of the fittest ‘fortuitous’ variations in a brutal struggle for existence and a theology which taught God's designing providence in a creation that he saw was ‘good’? What conceivable logic could there be in uniting a theory of mankind's physical and psychical evolution from lower animals with a belief that human beings were uniquely created in the image of God? The name Christian might have been annexed to anti-Darwinism or perhaps to some version of evolution which did honour to the purposes and character of the Creator, but never, surely, to that theory set forth by the agnostic naturalist Charles Darwin.
It has been a matter of controversy…whether evolutionary theory demonstrates the need for a new religion to include the new idea of an evolving Universe or whether nothing more is needed than a transformed – or for the first time clearly understood – Christianity.
John Passmore
Darwin's theological perplexity and his eventual uneasy agnosticism might be better construed as evidence of the incompleteness of his work than as proof of its essential heterodoxy. Such at any rate is an interpretation which Darwinian commentators, old and new, would seem to allow. Huxley thought that evolution by natural selection is ‘neither Anti-theistic nor Theistic’, that ‘it simply has no more to do with Theism than the first book of Euclid has’. Chauncey Wright argued forcefully for the metaphysical ‘neutrality’ of the theory. David Hull has remarked that ‘the development of evolutionary theory since Darwin might well be described as a scientific theory in search of a metaphysics’. And in his Providence Lost Richard Spilsbury has written of contemporary Neo-Darwinians in much the same vein in which Geoffrey Wells wrote of Darwin forty years ago. ‘The fragmentary man’, said Wells, ‘can only manifest a fragmentary truth’. Darwin was ‘a specialist getting on with his job, in a sociological, political, and religious vacuum’. He was ‘incomplete’, and ‘Darwinism accordingly inadequate as a philosophy by which men may live’.
Of course Darwinism has never been held in a ‘vacuum’, apart from ultimate beliefs, nor has it ever been purged of its metaphysical susceptibilities.
It is no vulgar ‘act of faith’ that is at issue here, no ignoble acquiescence in orthodoxy or submission to an establishment. What is at issue is the faith in science itself, or in what passes as the necessary logic of science. The theory of natural selection is in many respects almost the ideal scientific theory: it is eminently naturalistic, mechanical, objective, impersonal and economical. … [Darwin] never doubted that he was a passive, disinterested observer accurately recording the laws revealed in nature. …
It was for this reason that Darwinism did not turn out to be the implacable enemy of religion that was first suspected. For Darwinism shared with religion the belief in an objective knowledge of nature. If religion's belief was based on revelation and Darwinism on science, with good will the two could be – as indeed they were – shown to coincide. The true challenge to orthodox religion came with the denial of the possibility of all objective knowledge. … Pre-Kant and pre-Kierkegaard, Darwinism appears as the citadel of tradition.
Gertrude Himmelfarb
For more than forty years after the publication of the Origin of Species evolutionary thought in Britain and America was in a state of great confusion. Theory vied with theory, philosophy with philosophy, to explain the manner in which life and matter had assumed its present forms. The theory of natural selection, which in Darwin's view described ‘the most important, but not the exclusive’, means of organic modification, was subjected not only to base and baseless theological attacks, but to some well-founded scientific criticisms.