We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
In Chapters 8, 9, and 10 we examined gravitational phenomena that take place in the near zone, the region of space which contains the source of the gravitational field, and which is confined to a radius R that is much smaller than λc, the characteristic wavelength of the emitted radiation. This near-zone physics excluded radiative phenomena, and the dynamics of the system was entirely conservative. In Chapter 11 we moved to the wave zone, situated at a distance R that is much larger than λc, and studied the gravitational waves produced by processes taking place in the near zone; this wave-zone physics is all about radiative phenomena. In the first part of this chapter we continue our exploration of wave-zone physics by describing how gravitational waves transport energy, momentum, and angular momentum away from their source. These radiative losses imply that the near-zone physics cannot be strictly conservative, and in the second part of the chapter we identify the radiation-reaction forces which produce the required dissipation within the system. This chapter, therefore, is all about the linkage between the near and wave zones.
Radiative losses and radiation reaction are subtle topics in general relativity, and the mathematical description of these phenomena is technically demanding. To ease our entry into this subject, in Sec. 12.1 we first review the situation in the simpler context of flat-spacetime electromagnetism. We return to gravity in Sec. 12.2, in which we develop a general description of radiative losses in general relativity.
In this chapter we embark on a general program to specialize the formulation of general relativity to a description of weak gravitational fields. We will go from the exact theory, which governs the behavior of arbitrarily strong fields, such as those of neutron stars and black holes, to a useful approximation that applies to weak fields, such as those of planets, main-sequence stars, and white dwarfs. This approximation will reproduce the predictions of Newtonian theory, but we will formulate a method that can be pushed systematically to higher and higher order to produce an increasingly accurate description of a weak gravitational field. We shall find that the method is so successful that it can actually handle fields that are not so weak. For example, it provides a perfectly adequate description of gravity at a safe distance from a neutron star, and it can be used as a foundation to study the motion of a binary black-hole system, provided that the mutual gravity between bodies is weak.
The foundation for these methods is “post-Minkowskian theory,” the topic of this chapter and the next. In post-Minkowskian theory the strength of the gravitational field is measured by the gravitational constant G, and the Einstein field equations are formally expanded in powers of G. At zeroth post-Minkowskian order there is no field, and one deals with Minkowski spacetime.
In November 1915, Einstein completed a calculation whose result so agitated him that he worried that he might be having a heart attack. He later wrote to a friend that “for several days I was beside myself in joyous excitement.” What Einstein calculated was the contribution to the advance of the perihelion of Mercury from the first post-Newtonian corrections to Newtonian gravity provided by his newly completed theory of general relativity. This had been a notorious and unsolved problem in astronomy, ever since Le Verrier pointed out in 1859 that there was a discrepancy of approximately 43 arcseconds per century in the rate of advance between what was observed and what could be accounted for in Newtonian theory from planetary perturbations (refer to Secs. 3.1 and 3.4). Many earlier attempts to devise relativistic theories of gravity, including Einstein's own “Entwurf” (outline) theory of 1913 with Marcel Grossmann, had failed to give the correct answer. Now armed with the correct field equations, Einstein found an approximate vacuum solution that could be applied to the geodesic motion of Mercury around the Sun. He found that the orbit was almost Keplerian, but with a perihelion that advances at a rate that matched Le Verrier's observations.
For Einstein, this success with Mercury was the first concrete evidence that his theory, over which he had struggled so mightily for the past four years, might actually be correct.
Post-Newtonian theory is the theory of weak-field gravity within the near zone, and of the slowly moving systems that generate it and respond to it. It was first encountered in Chapter 7, where it was embedded within the post-Minkowskian approximation; the idea relies on the slow-motion condition introduced in Sec. 6.3.2. But while post-Minkowskian theory deals with both the near and wave zone, here we focus exclusively on the near zone. In this chapter we develop the post-Newtonian theory systematically.
We begin in Sec. 8.1 by collecting the main ingredients obtained in Chapter 7, including the near-zone metric to 1PN order and the matter's energy-momentum tensor Tαβ. In Sec. 8.2 we present an alternative derivation of the post-Newtonian metric, based on the Einstein equations in their standard form; this is the “classic approach” to post-Newtonian theory, adopted by Einstein, Infeld, and Hoffmann in the 1930s, and by Fock, Chandrasekhar, and others in the 1960s. Although it produces the same results, we will see that the classic approach presents us with a number of ambiguities that are not present in the post-Minkowskian approach. In Sec. 8.3 we explore the coordinate freedom of post-Newtonian theory, and construct the most general transformation that preserves the post-Newtonian expansion of the metric. And in Sec. 8.4 we derive the laws of fluid dynamics in post-Newtonian theory; these will be applied to the motion of an N-body system in Chapter 9.
In this chapter we apply the results of Chapter 8 to situations in which a fluid distribution breaks up into a collection of separated bodies. Our aim is to go from a fine-grained description involving the fluid variables {ρ*, p, Π, ν} to a coarse-grained description involving a small number of center-of-mass variables for each body. We accomplish this reduction in Sec. 9.1, and in Sec. 9.2 we apply it to a calculation of the spacetime metric in the empty region between bodies; the metric is thus expressed in terms of the mass-energy MA, position rA(t), and velocity νA(t) of each body. In Sec. 9.3 we derive post-Newtonian equations of motion for the center-of-mass positions, and in Sec. 9.4 we show that the same equations apply to compact bodies with strong internal gravity. In Sec. 9.5 we allow the bodies to rotate, and we calculate the influence of the spins on the metric and equations of motion; we also derive evolution equations for the spin vectors. We conclude in Sec. 9.6 with a discussion of how point particles can be usefully incorporated within post-Newtonian theory, in spite of their infinite densities and diverging gravitational potentials.
From fluid configurations to isolated bodies
We consider a situation in which a distribution of perfect fluid breaks up into a number N of separated components. We call each component a “body,” and label each body with the index A = 1, 2, …, N.
In Chapter 1 we introduced the foundations of Newtonian gravity, and presented the equations that govern the gravitational potential of spherical and nearly spherical bodies. We also examined the center-of-mass motion of extended bodies, and witnessed the remarkable near-decoupling of the external dynamics – the motion of each body as a whole – from the internal dynamics – the internal fluid motions within each body. As we saw in Chapter 1, the details of internal structure, encapsulated in multipole moments of the mass distribution, have a limited influence on the motion of the body as a whole. In this chapter we take the focus away from the external dynamics and examine the internal structure and dynamics of extended, self-gravitating bodies. We shall return to the theme of the near-decoupling of the external and internal dynamics, and reveal the limited influence of the center-of-mass motion and the external bodies on the structure of a selected body.
We begin in Sec. 2.1 with a review of the equations of fluid mechanics that are relevant to the internal dynamics; these are best formulated in the moving reference frame of a selected body A in an N-body system. In Sec. 2.2 we examine the simplest models of internal structure, involving spherical symmetry, assuming that the body is non-rotating and not influenced by external bodies.
By the end of the modern period, a particular world view had become firmly entrenched in the public understanding. Unlike most philosophical positions, which are sharply distinguished from scientific theories, this world view was widely seen as a direct implication of science, and even as the sine qua non for all scientific activity. For shorthand, let's call this view “materialism.”
Materialism consisted of five central theses:
Matter is the fundamental constituent of the natural world.
Forces act on matter.
The fundamental material particles or “atoms” – together with the fundamental physical forces, whatever they turn out to be – determine the motion of all objects in nature. Thus materialism entails determinism.
All more complex objects that we encounter in the natural world are aggregates of these fundamental particles, and their motions and behaviors can ultimately be understood in terms of the fundamental physical forces acting on them. Nothing exists that is not the product of these same particles and forces. In particular, there are no uniquely biological forces (vitalism or “entelechies”), no conscious forces (dualism), and no divine forces (what came to be known as supernaturalism). Thus materialism implied the exclusion of dualism, downward causation (Bøgh Andersen et al., 2000), and divine activity.
Materialism is an ontological position, as it specifies what kinds of things do and do not exist. But it can also become a thesis concerning what may and may not count as a scientific explanation. When combined with a commitment to scientific reduction, for example, it entails that all scientific explanations should ultimately be reducible to the explanations of fundamental physics. Any other science, say biology or psychology, is incomplete until we uncover the laws that link its phenomena with physics. In its reductionist form – which historically has been its most typical form – materialism thus excludes interpretations of science that allow for “top-down” causation, also known as “strong emergence.” Materialists may be divided on whether, and if so how soon, these reductions will actually be accomplished. Still, it is an entailment of materialism in most of its modern forms that an omniscient knower would be able to reduce all higher-order phenomena to the locations and momentums of fundamental particles.
Ever since the elucidation of the molecular basis of living systems, we have known that all elementary processes of life are governed by information. Thus, information turns out to be a key concept in understanding living matter (Küppers, 1990). More than that: the flow of information at all levels of the living system reveals the properties of communication. This means that the information stored in the genome of the organism is expressed in innumerable feedback loops – a process through which the genetic information is continually re-evaluated by permanent interactions with the physical environment to which it is exposed. In this way, the living organism is built up, step by step, into a hierarchically organized network of unmatched complexity.
The fact that all phenomena of life are based upon information and communication is indeed the principal characteristic of living matter. Without the perpetual exchange of information at all levels of organization, no functional order in the living organism could be sustained. The processes of life would implode into a jumble of chaos if they were not perpetually stabilized by information and communication. In this chapter, I should like to consider some of the consequences that follow from this for our philosophical understanding of reality.
Scientists who speculate on philosophical questions usually agree that classical materialism – the view that reality consists of nothing but small massy particles bumping into one another in an absolute and unique space–time – is intellectually dead. Accounts of the universe now regularly involve notions such as that of manifold space–times, quantum realities that exist at a more ultimate level than, and are very different from, massy particles in one specific space, and informational codes that contain instructions for building complex integrated structures displaying new sorts of emergent property.
What this suggests is that the nature of the reality investigated by physics and biology is much more complex and mysterious than some Newtonian materialists thought (though of course Newton himself was as far from being a materialist as one can get). In particular, the role of information in any account of our universe has come to take on a new importance.
A host of surveys indicate that what Christians, and indeed other religious believers, today affirm as ‘real’ fails to generate any conviction among many of those who seek spiritual insight and who continue regretfully as wistful agnostics in relation to the formulations of traditional religions – notably Christianity in Europe, and in intellectual circles in the USA. Many factors contribute to this state of affairs, but one of these, I would suggest, is that the traditional language in which much Christian theology, certainly in its Western form, has been and is cast is so saturated with terms that have a supernatural reference and colour that a culture accustomed to think in naturalistic terms, conditioned by the power and prestige of the natural sciences, finds it increasingly difficult to attribute any plausibility to it. Be that as it may, there is clearly a pressing need to describe the realities that Christian belief wishes to articulate in terms that can make sense to that culture without reducing its content to insignificance.
Correspondingly, there is also a perennial pressure, even among those not given to any form of traditional religiosity, to integrate the understandings of the natural world afforded by the sciences with very real, ‘spiritual’ experiences, which include interactions with other people and awareness of the transcendent.
Copenhagen is the perfect setting for our discussion of matter and information. We have been charged ‘to explore the current concept of matter from scientific, philosophical, and theological perspectives’. The essential foundation for this work is the output of the intense intellectual struggles that took place here in Copenhagen during the twenties, principally between Niels Bohr, Werner Heisenberg, and Wolfgang Pauli. Those struggles replaced the then-prevailing Newtonian idea of matter as ‘solid, massy, hard, impenetrable, moveable particles’ with a new concept that allowed, and in fact demanded, entry into the laws governing the motion of matter of the consequences of decisions made by human subjects. This change in the laws swept away the meaningless billiard-ball universe, and replaced it with a universe in which we human beings, by means of our intentional effort, can make a difference in how the ‘matter’ in our bodies behaves.
The role of mind in nature
Unfortunately, most of the prevailing descriptions of quantum theory tend to emphasize puzzles and paradoxes in a way that makes philosophers, theologians, and even non-physicist scientists leery of actually using in any deep way the profound changes in our understanding of human beings in nature wrought by the quantum revolution. Yet, properly presented, quantum mechanics is thoroughly in line with our deep human intuitions. It is the 300 years of indoctrination with basically false ideas about how nature works that now makes puzzling a process that is completely in line with normal human intuition. I therefore begin with a non-paradox-laden description of the quantum universe and the place of our minds within it.
The matter concept has had an extraordinarily complex history, dating back to the earliest days of the sort of reflective thought that came to be called ‘philosophy’. History here, as elsewhere, offers a valuable means of understanding the present, so it is with history that I will be concerned – history necessarily compressed into simplified outline.
This story, like that of Caesar's Gaul, falls readily into three parts. First is the gradual emergence in early Greek thought of a factor indispensable to the discussion of the changing world and the progressive elaboration of that factor (or, more exactly, cluster of factors) as philosophic reflection deepened and divided. Second is the radical shift that occurred in the seventeenth century as the concept of matter took on new meanings, gave its name to the emerging philosophy of materialism and yielded place to a derivative concept, mass, in the fast-developing new science of mechanics. Third is the further transformation of the concept in the twentieth century in the light of the dramatic changes brought about by the three radically new theories in physics: relativity, quantum mechanics, and expanding-universe cosmology, with which that century will always be associated. Matter began to be dematerialized, as it were, as matter and energy were brought into some sort of equivalence, and the imagination-friendly particles of the earlier mechanics yielded way to the ghostly realities of quantum theory that are neither here nor there.