We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
As we have seen in Chapter 10, the main property of typed systems not possessed by untyped systems is that all reductions are finite, and hence every typed term has a normal form. In this appendix we shall prove this theorem for the simply typed systems in Chapter 10, and for an extended system from which the consistency of first-order arithmetic can be deduced.
The proofs will be variations on a method due to W. Tait, [Tai67]. (See also [TS00, Sections 6.8, 6.12.2] or [SU06, Sections 5.3.2–5.3.6].) Simpler methods are known for pure λ and CL, but Tait's is the easiest to extend to more complex type-systems.
We begin with two definitions which have meaning for any reduction concept defined by sequences of replacements. The first is a repetition of Definition 10.14. The second is the key to Tait's method.
Definition A3.1 (Normalizable terms) A typed or untyped CL-or λ-term X is called normalizable or weakly normalizable or WN with respect to a given reduction concept, iff it reduces to a normal form. It is called strongly normalizable (SN) iff all reductions starting at X are finite.
As noted in Chapter 10, SN implies WN. Also the concept of SN involves the distinction between finite and infinite reductions, whereas WN does not, so SN is a fundamentally more complex concept than WN.
In this chapter, a sequence of pure terms will be chosen to represent the natural numbers. It is then reasonable to expect that some of the other terms will represent functions of natural numbers, in some sense. This sense will be defined precisely below. The functions so representable will turn out to be exactly those computable by Turing machines.
In the 1930s, three concepts of computability arose independently: ‘Turing-computable function’, ‘recursive function’ and ‘λ-definable function’. The inventors of these three concepts soon discovered that all three gave the same set of functions. Most logicians took this as strong evidence that the informal notion of ‘computable function’ had been captured exactly by these three formally-defined concepts.
Here we shall look at the recursive functions, and prove that all these functions can be represented in λ and CL. (We shall not work with the Turing-computable functions because their representability-proof is longer.)
An outline definition of the recursive functions will be given here; more details and background can be found in many textbooks on computability or textbooks on logic which include computability, for example [Coh87], [Men97] or the old but thorough [Kle52].
Notation 4.1 This chapter is written in the same neutral notation as the last one, and its results will hold for both λ and CL unless explicitly stated otherwise.