Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T03:40:27.739Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 October 2018

Rutger Claassen
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Capabilities in a Just Society
A Theory of Navigational Agency
, pp. 239 - 258
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abizadeh, Arash. 2008. “Democratic Theory and Border Coercion. No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders.” Political Theory 36 (1): 3765.Google Scholar
Abizadeh, Arash. 2012. “On the Demos and Its Kin: Nationalism, Democracy, and the Boundary Problem.” American Political Science Review 106 (4): 867–82.Google Scholar
Agné, Hans. 2010. “Why Democracy Must Be Global: Self-Founding and Democratic Intervention.” International Theory 2 (3): 381409.Google Scholar
Alexander, John. 2008. Capabilities and Social Justice. The Political Philosophy of Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry. 2008. “What Is Freedom of Association and What Is Its Denial?Social Philosophy and Policy 25 (2): 121.Google Scholar
Alkire, Sabine. 2002. Valuing Freedoms. Sen's Capability Approach and Poverty Reduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 1999. “What Is the Point of Equality?Ethics 109 (2): 287337.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2009. “Democracy: Instrumental vs. Non-Instrumental Value.” In Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy, edited by Christiano, Thomas and Christman, John, 213–27. Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2010a. “Justifying the Capability Approach to Justice.” In Measuring Justice. Primary Goods and Capabilities, edited by Brighouse, Harry and Robeyns, Ingrid, 81100. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2010b. “The Fundamental Disagreement between Luck Egalitarians and Relational Egalitarians.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 36: 124.Google Scholar
Anderson, Joel. 2008. “Disputing Autonomy. Second-Order Desires and the Dynamics of Ascribing Autonomy.” SATS − Nordic Journal of Philosophy 9 (1): 726.Google Scholar
Anderson, Joel. 2014. “Regimes of Autonomy.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (3): 355–68.Google Scholar
Anderson, Joel, and Christman, John. 2005. “Introduction.” In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism. New Essays, edited by Christman, John and Anderson, Joel, 123. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Joel, and Honneth, Axel. 2005. “Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition, and Justice.” In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism. New Essays, edited by Anderson, Joel and Christman, John, 127–49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Antony, Louise. 2000. “Natures and Norms.” Ethics 111: 836.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 1998. The Human Condition. 2nd edn. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 1984. “Politics.” In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Volume II, edited by Barnes, Jonathan, 19862129. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 1989. “Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare.” Philosophical Studies 56 (1): 7793.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2000a. “Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism.” Ethics 110 (2): 339–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2000b. “Perfectionism and Politics.” Ethics 111 (1): 3763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2003. “Liberal Neutrality on the Good: An Autopsy.” In Perfectionism and Neutrality. Essays in Liberal Theory, edited by Wall, Steven and Klosko, George, 191218. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2006. “Distributive Justice and Basic Capability Equality: ‘Good Enough’ Is Not Good Enough.” In Capabilities Equality. Basic Issues and Problems, edited by Kaufman, Alexander, 1743. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2009. “The Supposed Right to a Democratic Say.” In Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy, edited by Christiano, Thomas and Christman, John, 197212. Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2010a. “Democratic Equality and Relating as Equals.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 36: 2552.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard. 2010b. “Two Cheers for Capabilities.” In Measuring Justice. Primary Goods and Capabilities, edited by Brighouse, Harry and Robeyns, Ingrid, 101–27. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Arrhenius, Gustaf. 2005. “The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory.” In Democracy Unbound: Basic Explorations I, edited by Tersman, Folke, 1429. Stockholm: Filosofiska Institutionen, Stockholms Universitet.Google Scholar
Atkinson, Anthony. 2015. Inequality. What Can Be Done? Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelsen, David, and Nielsen, Lasse. 2015. “Sufficiency as Freedom from Duress.” Journal of Political Philosophy 13 (4): 406–26.Google Scholar
Axelsen, David, and Nielsen, Lasse 2017. “Capabilitarian Sufficiency: Capabilities and Social Justice.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 18 (1): 4659.Google Scholar
Baber, H. E. 2007. “Adaptive Preference.” Social Theory and Practice 33 (1): 105–26.Google Scholar
Baderin, Alice. 2016a. “Political Theory and Public Opinion: Against Democratic Restraint.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 15 (3): 209–33.Google Scholar
Baderin, Alice. 2016b. “Two Forms of Realism in Political Theory.” European Journal of Political Theory 13 (2): 132–53.Google Scholar
Bagnoli, Carla, ed. 2013. Constructivism in Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bagnoli, Carla, 2014. “Starting Points: Kantian Constructivism Reassessed.” Ratio Juris 27 (3): 311–29.Google Scholar
Baldwin, Thomas. 2009. “Recognition: Personal and Political.” Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 8 (3): 311–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balint, Peter. 2015. “Identity Claims: Why Liberal Neutrality Is the Solution, Not the Problem.” Political Studies 63 (2): 495509.Google Scholar
Barclay, Linda. 2003. “What Kind of Liberal Is Martha Nussbaum?SATS − Nordic Journal of Philosophy 4 (2): 524.Google Scholar
Barclay, Linda. 2012. “Natural Deficiency or Social Oppression? The Capabilities Approach to Justice for People with Disabilities.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (4): 500–20.Google Scholar
Barclay, Linda. 2016. “The Importance of Equal Respect: What the Capabilities Approach Can and Should Learn from Human Rights Law.” Political Studies 64 (2): 385400.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 2001. Culture & Equality. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Bartelson, Jens. 2008. “Globalizing the Democratic Community.” Ethics & Global Politics 1 (4): 159–74.Google Scholar
Becker, Lawrence. 1980. “The Moral Basis of Property Rights.” In Nomos XXII: Property, edited by Roland Pennock, J. and Chapman, John W., 187220. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Beetham, David. 1995. “What Future for Economic and Social Rights?Political Studies 43 (1): 4160.Google Scholar
Begon, Jessica. 2015. “What Are Adaptive Preferences? Exclusion and Disability in the Capability Approach.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 32 (3): 241–57.Google Scholar
Begon, Jessica. 2017. “Capabilities for All? From Capabilities to Function to Capabilities to Control.” Social Theory and Practice 43 (1): 154–79.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 2009. The Idea of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Benbaji, Yitzak. 2005. “The Doctrine of Sufficiency: A Defense.” Utilitas 17 (3): 301–32.Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla. 2012. “Is There a Human Right to Democracy? Beyond Interventionism and Indifference.” In Philosophical Dimensions of Human Rights, edited by Corradetti, Claudio, 191214. Dordrecht/Heidelberg/New York/London: Springer.Google Scholar
Benkler, Yochai, and Nissenbaum, Helen. 2006. “Commons-Based Peer Production and Virtue.” Journal of Political Philosophy 14 (4): 394419.Google Scholar
Benson, Paul. 1994. “Free Agency and Self-Worth.” The Journal of Philosophy 91 (12): 650–68.Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah. 2002. Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bertea, Stefano. 2013. “Constitutivism and Normativity: A Qualified Defence.” Philosophical Explorations 16 (1): 8195.Google Scholar
Beyleveld, Deryck. 2015. “Korsgaard v. Gewirth on Universalization: Why Gewirthians Are Kantians and Kantians Ought to Be Gewirthians.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (5): 573–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bilchitz, David. 2007. Poverty and Fundamental Rights: The Justification and Enforcement of Socio-Economic Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Biondo, Francesco. 2008. “Is Martha Nussbaum Really Political Liberal?Archiv Fur Rechts – Und Sozialphilosophie 94 (3): 311–24.Google Scholar
Blake, Michael. 2002. “Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 30 (3): 257–96.Google Scholar
Borchers, Dagmar. 2012. “Calculating on Identity? The Costs and Benefits of the Costs-of-Exit Debate.” In On Exit. Interdisciplinary Perspectives on the Right of Exit in Liberal Multicultural Societies, edited by Vitikainen, Annamari and Borchers, Dagmar, 5777. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Brennan, Geoffrey. 2012. “Political Liberty: Who Needs It?Social Philosophy & Policy 29 (1): 127.Google Scholar
Brighouse, Harry, and Fleurbaey, Marc. 2010. “Democracy and Proportionality.” Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (2): 137–55.Google Scholar
Brighouse, Harry, and Robeyns, Ingrid, eds. 2010. Measuring Justice: Primary Goods and Capabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brighouse, Harry, and Swift, Adam. 2006. “Equality, Priority, and Positional Goods.” Ethics 116 (3): 471–97.Google Scholar
Brownlee, Kimberley. 2013. “A Human Right against Social Deprivation.” The Philosophical Quarterly 63 (251): 199222.Google Scholar
Brownlee, Kimberley. 2015. “Freedom of Association: It's Not What You Think.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 35 (2): 267–82.Google Scholar
Bruckner, Donald. 2009. “In Defense of Adaptive Preferences.” Philosophical Studies 142 (3): 307–24.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Alan. 2010. “The Egalitarianism of Human Rights.” Ethics 120 (4): 679710.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Alan. 2013. The Heart of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Byskov, Morten. 2017. “Democracy, Philosophy, and the Selection of Capabilities.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 18 (1): 116.Google Scholar
Carter, Ian. 1996. “The Concept of Freedom in the Work of Amartya Sen: An Alternative Analysis Consistent with Freedom's Independent Value.” Notizie Di Politeia 43–4: 722.Google Scholar
Carter, Ian. 1999. A Measure of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carter, Ian. 2011. “Respect and the Basis of Equality.” Ethics 121 (3): 538–71.Google Scholar
Carter, Ian. 2014. “Is the Capability Approach Paternalist?Economics & Philosophy 30 (1): 7598.Google Scholar
Casal, Paula. 2007. “Why Sufficiency Is Not Enough.” Ethics 117 (2): 296326.Google Scholar
Celikates, Robin. 2014. “Freedom as Non-Arbitrariness or as Democratic Self-Rule? A Critique of Contemporary Republicanism.” In To Be Unfree: Republicanism and Unfreedom in History, Literature, and Philosophy, edited by Dahl, Christian and Nexo, Tue Andersen, 3754. Bielefeld: Transcript.Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2008. The Constitution of Equality. Democratic Authority and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2011. “An Instrumental Argument for a Human Right to Democracy.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 39 (2): 142–76.Google Scholar
Christman, John. 1994. The Myth of Property. Toward an Egalitarian Theory of Ownership. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Christman, John. 2004. “Relational Autonomy, Liberal Individualism, and the Social Constitution of Selves.” Philosophical Studies 117 (1–2): 143–64.Google Scholar
Christman, John. 2009. The Politics of Persons. Individual Autonomy and Socio-Historical Selves. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Christman, John. 2014. “Coping or Oppression: Autonomy and Adaptation to Circumstance.” In Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender, edited by Veltman, Andrea and Piper, Mark, 201–26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ciepley, David. 2013. “Beyond Public and Private: Toward a Political Theory of the Corporation.” American Political Science Review 107 (1): 139–58.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2007. “The Status Struggle. A Recognition-Based Interpretation of the Positional Economy.” Philosophy and Social Criticism 34 (9): 1021–49.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2009a. “Institutional Pluralism and the Limits of the Market.” Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 8 (4): 420–47.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2009b. “New Directions in Capability Theory: Republicanism and Deliberative Democracy (Book Review Essay).” Res Publica 15 (4): 421–28.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2011a. “Communication as Commodity. Should the Media Be on the Market?Journal of Applied Philosophy 28 (1): 6579.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2011b. “Making Capability Lists. Philosophy versus Democracy.” Political Studies 59 (3): 491508.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2011c. “The Commodification of Care.” Hypatia 26 (1): 4364.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2011d. “The Marketization of Security Services.” Public Reason 3 (2): 124–45.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2013. “Public Goods, Mutual Benefits, and Majority Rule.” Journal of Social Philosophy 44 (3): 270–90.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2014a. “Capability Paternalism.” Economics & Philosophy 30 (1): 5773.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2014b. “Human Dignity in the Capability Approach.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Human Dignity, edited by Düwell, Marcus, Braarvig, Jens, Brownsword, Roger, and Mieth, Dietmar, 240–9. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2015. “The Capability to Hold Property.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 16 (2): 220–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2016. “Ecological Rights of Future Generations: A Capability Approach.” In Human Rights and Sustainability. Moral Responsibilities for the Future, edited by Bos, Gerhard and Duwell, Marcus, 151–65. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2017. “Capabilities and Financial Market Regulation.” In Just Financial Markets? Finance in a Just Society, edited by Herzog, Lisa, 5677. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2018a. “Justice as a Claim to (Social) Property.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy. Available from https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/13698230.2017.1398867.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2018b. “Constructivism's Challenge: Justifying a Modern Self-Understanding.” Manscript in Preparation.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2019a (forthcoming). “Selecting a List: The Capability Approach's Achilles Heel.” In Handbook on the Capability Approach, edited by Chiappero, Enricca, Osmani, Siddiq, and Qizilbash, Mozaffar. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger. 2019b (forthcoming). “European Duties of Social Justice: A Kantian Framework.” Journal of Common Market Studies.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Claassen, Rutger, and Düwell, Marcus. 2013. “The Foundations of Capability Theory: Comparing Nussbaum and Gewirth.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (3): 493510.Google Scholar
Claassen, Rutger, and Gerbrandy, Anna. 2016. “Rethinking Competition Law: From a Consumer Welfare to a Capability Approach.” Utrecht Law Review 12 (1): 115.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 1989. “On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice.” Ethics 99 (4): 906–44.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua. 2003. “For a Democratic Society.” In The Cambridge Companion To Rawls, edited by Freeman, Samuel, 86138. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua. 2006. “Is There a Human Right to Democracy?” In The Egalitarian Conscience. Essays in Honour of G.A. Cohen, edited by Sypnowich, Christine, 226–48. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Colburn, Ben. 2010a. “Anti-Perfectionisms and Autonomy.” Analysis 70 (2): 247–56.Google Scholar
Colburn, Ben. 2010b. Autonomy and Liberalism. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Colburn, Ben. 2011. “Autonomy and Adaptive Preferences.” Utilitas 23 (1): 5271.Google Scholar
Comim, Flavio, and Nussbaum, Martha, eds. 2014. Capabilities, Gender, Equality. Towards Fundamental Entitlements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Conradie, Ina, and Robeyns, Ingrid. 2013. “Aspirations and Human Development.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 14 (4): 559–80.Google Scholar
Copp, David. 1992. “The Right to an Adequate Standard of Living: Justice, Autonomy, and the Basic Needs.” Social Philosophy & Policy 9 (1): 231–61.Google Scholar
Crisp, Roger. 2003. “Equality, Priority, and Compassion.” Ethics 113 (4): 745–63.Google Scholar
Crocker, David. 2008. Ethics of Global Development. Agency, Capability, and Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crocker, David, and Robeyns, Ingrid. 2010. “Capability and Agency.” In Amartya Sen, edited by Morris, Christopher, 6090. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dagan, Hanoch, and Dorfman, Avihay. 2017. “The Human Right to Property.” Theoretical Inquires in Law 18 (2): 391416.Google Scholar
Dagan, Hanoch, and Heller, Michael. 2001. “The Liberal Commons.” Yale Law Journal 110 (4): 549623.Google Scholar
Dagger, Richard. 2005. “Autonomy, Domination, and the Republican Challenge to Liberalism.” In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism. New Essays, edited by Christman, John and Anderson, Joel, 177203. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint. Morality, Respect and Accountability. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
De Maagt, Sem. 2016. Constructing Morality: Transcendental Arguments in Ethics. PhD Dissertation. Utrecht: OFR Institute for Philosophy. Available from: https://dspace.library.uu.nl/handle/1874/345118 (accessed on June 6, 2018).Google Scholar
De Maagt, Sem. 2017. “Reflective Equilibrium and Moral Objectivity.” Inquiry 60 (5): 443–65.Google Scholar
Deakin, Simon. 2006. “‘Capacitas’: Contract Law and the Institutional Preconditions of a Market Economy.” European Review of Contract Law 2 (3): 317–41.Google Scholar
Deneulin, Séverine. 2002. “Perfectionism, Paternalism and Liberalism in Sen and Nussbaum's Capability Approach.” Review of Political Economy 14 (4): 497518.Google Scholar
Deneulin, Séverine. 2008. “Beyond Individual Freedom and Agency: Structures of Living Together in the Capability Approach.” In The Capability Approach. Concepts, Measures and Applications, edited by Comim, Flavio, Qizilbash, Mozaffar, and Alkire, Sabine, 105–24. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Deneulin, Séverine. 2013. “Recovering Nussbaum's Aristotelian Roots.” International Journal of Social Economics 40 (7): 624–32.Google Scholar
Deneulin, Séverine, and Shahani, Lila, eds. 2009. An Introduction to the Human Development and Capability Approach. London: Earthscan.Google Scholar
Dorsey, Dale. 2008. “Toward a Theory of the Basic Minimum.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 7 (4): 423–45.Google Scholar
Dowding, Keith. 2006. “Can Capabilities Reconcile Freedom and Equality?The Journal of Political Philosophy 14 (3): 323–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drydyk, Jay. 2008. “Durable Empowerment.” Journal of Global Ethics 4 (3): 231–45.Google Scholar
Drydyk, Jay. 2011. “Responsible Pluralism, Capabilities, and Human Rights.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 12 (1): 3961.Google Scholar
Drydyk, Jay. 2013. “Empowerment, Agency, and Power.” Journal of Global Ethics 9 (3): 249–62.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Gerald. 1988. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. “Liberalism.” In Public and Private Morality, edited by Hampshire, Stuart, 113–43. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Sovereign Virtue. The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2002. “Sovereign Virtue Revisited.” Ethics 113 (1): 106–43.Google Scholar
Ebels-Duggan, Kyla. 2011. “Critical Notice of Arthur Ripstein Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (4): 549–74.Google Scholar
Eggertsson, Thrainn. 2003. “Open Access versus Common Property.” In Property Rights. Cooperation, Conflict, and Law, edited by Anderson, Terry and McChesney, Fred, 7389. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1982. “Sour Grapes – Utilitarianism and the Genesis of Wants.” In Utilitarianism and Beyond, edited by Sen, Amartya and Williams, Bernard, 219–38. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, David. 2006. “Agency, Schmagency: Why Normativity Won't Come from What Is Constitutive of Action.” The Philosophical Review 115 (2): 169–98.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 1996. “The Survival of Egalitarian Justice in John Rawls's Political Liberalism.” Journal of Political Philosophy 4 (1): 6878.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2009. “Debate: On Christiano's The Constitution of Equality.” Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (2): 241–52.Google Scholar
Fabre, Cecile. 1998. “Constitutionalising Social Rights.” Journal of Political Philosophy 6 (3): 263–84.Google Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1970. “The Nature and Value of Rights.” Journal of Value Inquiry 4 (4): 243–57.Google Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ferracioli, Luara, and Terlazzo, Rosa. 2014. “Educating for Autonomy: Liberalism and Autonomy in the Capabilities Approach.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (3): 443–55.Google Scholar
Ferrero, Luca. 2009. “Constitutivism and the Inescapability of Agency.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, IV: 303–34. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fleurbaey, Marc. 2008. Fairness, Responsibility, and Welfare. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Formosa, Paul, and Mackenzie, Catriona. 2014. “Nussbaum, Kant, and the Capabilities Approach to Dignity.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (5): 875–92.Google Scholar
Frank, Robert. 1985. Choosing the Right Pond. Human Behavior and the Quest for Status. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frank, Robert. 1999. Luxury Fever. Why Money Fails to Satisfy in an Era of Excess. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Frank, Robert. 2008. “Should Public Policy Respond to Positional Externalities?Journal of Public Economics 92 (8–9): 1777–86.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1971. “The Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy 68: 520.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1987. “Equality as a Moral Ideal.” Ethics 98 (1): 2143.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1988. The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel. 2011. “Capitalism in the Classical and High Liberal Traditions.” Social Philosophy & Policy 28 (2): 1955.Google Scholar
Garnett, Michael. 2016. “Value Neutrality and the Ranking of Opportunity Sets.” Economic and Philosophy 32 (1): 99119.Google Scholar
Gewirth, Alan. 1978. Reason and Morality. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gewirth, Alan. 1996. The Community of Rights. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gewirth, Alan. 2007. “Duties to Fulfill the Human Rights of the Poor.” In Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right, edited by Pogge, Thomas, 219–36. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Giddens, Anthony. 1994. The Constitution of Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Gilabert, Paolo. 2013. “The Capability Approach and the Debate between Humanist and Political Perspectives on Human Rights. A Critical Survey.” Human Rights Review 14 (4): 299325.Google Scholar
Goodin, Robert. 2007. “Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 35 (1): 4068.Google Scholar
Gore, Charles. 1997. “Irreducibly Social Goods and the Informational Basis of Amartya Sen's Capability Approach.” Journal of International Development 9 (2): 235–50.Google Scholar
Gough, Ian. 2014. “Lists and Thresholds: Comparing the Doyal–Gough Theory of Human Need with Nussbaum's Capabilities Approach.” In Capabilities, Gender, Equality. Towards Fundamental Entitlements, edited by Comim, Flavio and Nussbaum, Martha, 357–81. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gould, Carol. 2004. Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gould, Carol. 2015. “A Social Ontology of Human Rights.” In Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, edited by Cruft, Rowan, Matthew Liao, S., and Renzo, Massimo, 177–95. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gourevitch, Alex. 2015. “Liberty and Its Economies.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 14 (4): 365–90.Google Scholar
Green, Jeffrey. 2016. “Liberalism and the Problem of Plutocracy.” Constellations 23 (1): 8495.Google Scholar
Green, Leslie. 1998. “Rights of Exit.” Legal Theory 4 (2): 165–85.Google Scholar
Griffin, James. 2000. “Welfare Rights.” Journal of Ethics 4 (1–2): 2743.Google Scholar
Griffin, James. 2008. On Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, James. 2010. “Human Rights: Questions of Aim and Approach.” Ethics 120 (4): 741–60.Google Scholar
Gutman, Amy. 2003. “Rawls on the Relationship between Liberalism and Democracy.” In The Cambridge Companion To Rawls, edited by Freeman, Samuel, 168–99. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1990. “Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification.” In Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, 43115. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1983. “Rawls on Liberty and It Priority.” In Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, 223–47. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hayward, Tim. 2013. “Human Rights versus Property Rights.” JWI Working Paper 04.Google Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2005. “Liberal Autonomy and Consumer Sovereignty.” In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism. New Essays, edited by Christman, John and Anderson, Joel, 204–25. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2006. “Envy and Efficiency.” Revue de Philosophie Économique 7 (2): 330.Google Scholar
Heath, Joseph. 2011. “Three Normative Models of the Welfare State.” Public Reason 3 (2): 1343.Google Scholar
Heller, Michael. 2001. “The Dynamic Analytics of Property Law.” Theoretical Inquires in Law 2 (1): 7995.Google Scholar
Hill, Thomas Jr. 1991. “Servility and Self-Respect.” In Autonomy and Self-Respect, 419. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hirsch, Fred. 1999. Social Limits to Growth. Lincoln: iUniverse.com.Google Scholar
Hirschman, Albert. 1970. Exit, Voice, and Loyalty. Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Holland, Breena. 2008. “Ecology and the Limits of Justice: Establishing Capability Ceilings in Nussbaum's Capability Approach.” Journal of Human Development 9 (3): 401–25.Google Scholar
Holmes, Stephen, and Sunstein, Cass. 2000. The Cost of Rights. Why Liberty Depends on Taxes. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
Holtug, Nils. 2007. “Prioritarianism.” In Egalitarianism. New Essays on the Nature and Value of Equality, edited by Holtug, Nils and Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper, 125–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition. The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2011. Das Recht Der Freiheit. Grundriss Einer Demokratischen Sittlichtkeit.Google Scholar
Hübenthal, Christoph. 2006. Grundlegung Der Christlichen Sozialethik. Münster: Aschendorff Verlag.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 2000. A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by Norton, David Fate and Norton, Mary J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2002. “Capability, Functioning and Perfectionism.” Apeiron 35 (4): 137–62.Google Scholar
Huseby, Robert. 2010. “Sufficiency: Restated and Defended.” Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (2): 178–97.Google Scholar
Jackson, Ben. 2012. “Property-Owning Democracy: A Short History.” In Property-Owning Democracy. Rawls and Beyond, edited by O'Neill, Martin and Williamson, Thad, 3352. Malden, MA and Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jaggar, Alison. 2006. “Reasoning About Well-Being: Nussbaums Methods of Justifying the Capabilities.” Journal of Political Philosophy 14 (3): 301–22.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1996. “The Metaphysics of Morals.” In Practical Philosophy, edited by Guyer, Paul, 353603. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Katzer, Matthias. 2010. “The Basis of Universal Liberal Principles in Nussbaum's Political Philosophy.” Public Reason 2 (2): 6075.Google Scholar
Kelleher, J. Paul. 2015. “Capabilities versus Resources.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (2): 151–71.Google Scholar
Kelly, Thomas, and McGrath, Sarah. 2010. “Is Reflective Equilibrium Enough?Philosophical Perspectives 24 (1): 325–59.Google Scholar
Khader, Serene. 2011. Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Khader, Serene. 2012. “Must Theorising about Adaptive Preferences Deny Women's Agency?Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (4): 302–17.Google Scholar
Klosko, George. 1990. “The Obligation to Contribute to Discretionary Public Goods.” Political Studies 38 (2): 196214.Google Scholar
Kolodny, Niko. 2014a. “Rule over None 1: What Justifies Democracy?Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (3): 195229.Google Scholar
Kolodny, Niko. 2014b. “Rule over None 2: Social Equality and the Justification of Democracy.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 42 (4): 287336.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 2004. “Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals.” The Tanner Lectures on Human Values.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 2007. “Autonomy and the Second Person Within: A Commentary on Stephen Darwall's The Second Person Standpoint.” Ethics 118 (1): 823.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 2008. “Realism and Constructivism in Twentieth-Century Philosophy.” In The Constitution of Agency, 302–26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 2009. Self-Constitution. Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. 2011. “Interacting with Animals: A Kantian Account.” In The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics, edited by Beauchamp, Tom and Frey, R. G., 91118. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kristinsson, Sigurdur. 2000. “The Limits of Neutrality: Toward a Weakly Substantive Account of Neutrality.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (2): 257–86.Google Scholar
Kukathas, Chandran. 2003. The Liberal Archipelago. A Theory of Diversity and Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will. 1989. Liberalism, Community and Culture. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will. 2002. Contemporary Political Philosophy. An Introduction. 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Laitinen, Arto. 2007. “Sorting Out Aspects of Personhood. Capacities, Normativity and Recognition.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 14 (5–7): 248–70.Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles. 1987. Patterns of Moral Complexity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lehavi, Amnon. 2008. “Mixing Property.” Seton Hall Law Review 38: 137212.Google Scholar
Levey, Ann. 2005. “Liberalism, Adaptive Preferences, and Gender Equality.” Hypatia 20 (4): 127–43.Google Scholar
Liao, S. Matthew. 2015. “Human Rights as Fundamental Conditions for a Good Life.” In Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, edited by Cruft, Rowan, Matthew Liao, S., and Renzo, Massimo, 79100. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John. 1960. “Two Treatises of Government.” In Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, edited by Laslett, Peter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lomasky, Loren. 1987. Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lomasky, Loren. 2000. “Liberty and Welfare Goods: Reflections on Clashing Liberalisms.” The Journal of Ethics 4 (1–2): 99113.Google Scholar
Lovett, Frank. 2009. “Domination and Distributive Justice.” The Journal of Politics 71 (3): 817–30.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1985. After Virtue. 2nd edn. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1999. “Social Structures and Their Threats to Moral Agency.” Philosophy 74: 311–29.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, Catriona. 2008. “Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority, and Perfectionism.” Journal of Social Philosophy 39 (4): 512–33.Google Scholar
Macpherson, C. B. 1978. “The Meaning of Property.” In Property. Mainstream and Critical Perspectives, edited by Macpherson, Crawford Brough, 114. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1978. “Critique of the Gotha Program.” In The Marx-Engels Reader, edited by Tucker, Robert, 525–42. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
Meade, James. 1964. Efficiency, Equality, and the Ownership of Property. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Menon, Nivedita. 2002. “Universalism without Foundations?Economy and Society 51 (1): 152–69.Google Scholar
Meyer, Lukas, and Roser, Dominic. 2009. “Enough for the Future.” In Intergenerational Justice, edited by Gosseries, Axel and Meyer, Lukas, 219–48. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1991. “Considerations on Representative Government.” In On Liberty and Other Essays, edited by Gray, John. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 1983. “Constraints on Freedom.” Ethics 94 (1): 6686.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 1999. Principles of Social Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 2004. “Justice, Democracy and Public Goods.” In Justice and Democracy. Essays for Brian Barry, edited by Dowding, Keith, Goodin, Robert, and Pateman, Carole, 127–49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 2009. “Democracy's Domain.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 37 (3): 201–28.Google Scholar
Miller, Seumas. 2001. Social Action. A Teleological Account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Seumas. 2010. The Moral Foundations of Social Institutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Morriss, Peter. 2002. Power. A Philosophical Analysis. 2nd edn. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Mulhall, Stephen, and Swift, Adam. 1996. Liberals and Communitarians. 2nd edn. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Munzer, Stephen. 1990. A Theory of Property. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Näsström, Sofia. 2003. “What Globalization Overshadows.” Political Theory 31 (6): 808–34.Google Scholar
Näsström, Sofia. 2007. “The Legitimacy of the People.” Political Theory 35 (5): 624–58.Google Scholar
Näsström, Sofia. 2011. “The Challenge of the All-Affected Principle.” Political Studies 59: 116–34.Google Scholar
Nelson, Eric. 2008. “From Primary Goods to Capabilities: Distributive Justice and the Problem of Neutrality.” Political Theory 36 (1): 93122.Google Scholar
Newman, Dwight. 2007. “Exit, Voice and ‘Exile’: Rights to Exit and Rights to Eject.” University of Toronto Law Journal 57 (1): 4379.Google Scholar
Nickel, James. 2005. “Poverty and Rights.” The Philosophical Quarterly 55 (220): 385402.Google Scholar
Nickel, James. 2007. Making Sense of Human Rights. 2nd edn. Malden and Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1988. “Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Supplementary Volume I: 145–84.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1990. “Aristotelian Social Democracy.” In Liberalism and the Good, edited by Bruce Douglas, R., Mara, Gerald M., and Richardson, Henry S., 203–52. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1993. “Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach.” In The Quality of Life, edited by Nussbaum, Martha and Sen, Amartya, 242–69. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1995. “Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundation of Ethics.” In World, Mind and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams, edited by Altham, J. E. J. and Harrison, Ross, 86131. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1997. “Capabilities and Human Rights.” Fordham Law Review 66 (2): 273300.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1998. “The Good as Discipline, The Good as Freedom.” In Ethics of Consumption. The Good Life, Justice, and Global Stewardship, edited by Crocker, David and Linden, Toby, 312–41. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2000a. “Why Practice Needs Ethical Theory.” In The Path of the Law and Its Influence. The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., edited by Burton, Steven, 5086. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2000b. Women and Human Development. The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2001. “Adaptive Preferences and Women's Options.” Economics & Philosophy 17 (1): 6788.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2003a. “Capabilities as Fundamental Entitlements: Sen and Social Justice.” Feminist Economics 9 (2–3): 3359.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2003b. “Political Liberalism and Respect: A Response to Linda Barclay.” SATS – Nordic Journal of Philosophy 4 (2): 2544.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of Justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2011a. “Capabilities, Entitlements, Rights: Supplementation and Critique.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 12 (1): 2337.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2011b. Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach. Cambridge: The Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2011c. “Perfectionist Liberalism and Political Liberalism.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 39 (1): 345.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller. 2002. “‘Mistresses of Their Own Destiny’: Group Rights, Gender, and Realistic Rights of Exit.” Ethics 112 (2): 205–30.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller. 2003. “Poverty, Well-Being and Gender: What Counts, Who's Heard?Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (3): 280316.Google Scholar
Olsaretti, Serena. 2004. Liberty, Desert and the Market. A Philosophical Study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Olsaretti, Serena. 2005. “Endorsement and Freedom in Amartya Sen's Capability Approach.” Economics and Philosophy 21 (1): 89108.Google Scholar
Olson, Kevin. 2006. Reflexive Democracy. Political Equality and the Welfare State. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
O'Neill, Martin. 2008. “What Should Egalitarians Believe?Philosophy & Public Affairs 36 (2): 119–56.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Martin. 2012. “Free (and Fair) Markets without Capitalism.” In Property-Owning Democracy. Rawls and Beyond, edited by O'Neill, Martin and Williamson, Thad, 75100. Malden and Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
O'Neill, Martin, and Williamson, Thad, eds. 2012. Property-Owning Democracy. Rawls and Beyond. Malden and Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora. 1979. “The Most Extensive Liberty.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 80: 4559.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora. 1989. “Constructivisms in Ethics.” In Constructions of Reason, 206–18. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora. 2001. “Practical Principles and Practical Judgment.” Hastings Center Report July–August: 1523.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora. 2007. “Normativity and Practical Judgment.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 4 (3): 393405.Google Scholar
Oshana, Marina. 1998. “Personal Autonomy and Society.” Journal of Social Philosophy 29 (1): 81102.Google Scholar
Ostrom, Elinor. 1990. Governing the Commons. The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pallikkathayil, Japa. 2010. “Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity.” Ethics 121 (1): 116–47.Google Scholar
Pallikkathayil, Japa. 2016. “Neither Perfectionism nor Political Liberalism.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 44 (3): 171–96.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 2000. “Equality or Priority?” In The Ideal of Equality, edited by Clayton, Matthew and Williams, Andrew, 81125. New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Patten, Alan. 2012. “Liberal Neutrality: A Reinterpretation and Defense.” Journal of Political Philosophy 20 (3): 249–72.Google Scholar
Peter, Fabienne. 2013. “The Human Right to Political Participation.” Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy 7 (2): 116.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 1993. The Common Mind. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism. A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2001. “Capability and Freedom: A Defence of Sen.” Economics and Philosophy 17 (1): 120.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2003. “Agency-Freedom and Option-Freedom.” Journal of Theoretical Politics 15 (4): 387403.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2008. “The Basic Liberties.” In The Legacy of HLA Hart, edited by Kramer, Matthew, 201–24. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2010. “Freedom in the Spirit of Sen.” In Amartya Sen, edited by Morris, Christopher, 91114. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2012. On the People's Terms. A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2014. Just Freedom. New York/London: Norton.Google Scholar
Pierik, Roland, and Robeyns, Ingrid. 2007. “Resources versus Capabilities: Social Endowments in Egalitarian Theory.” Political Studies 55 (1): 133–52.Google Scholar
Piketty, Thomas. 2014. Capital in the Twenty-First Century. Cambridge: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Platz, Jesse von. 2014. “Are Economic Liberties Basic Rights?Politics, Philosophy & Economics 13 (1): 2344.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2002. “Can the Capability Approach Be Justified?Philosophical Topics 30 (2): 167228.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2007. “Severe Poverty as a Human Rights Violation.” In Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor?, edited by Pogge, Thomas, 1154. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2008. World Poverty and Human Rights. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Qizilbash, Mozaffar. 1998. “The Concept of Well-Being.” Economics & Philosophy 14 (1): 5173.Google Scholar
Qizilbash, Mozaffar. 2011. “Sugden's Critique of the Capability Approach.” Utilitas 23 (1): 2551.Google Scholar
Qizilbash, Mozaffar. 2016. “Some Reflections on Capability and Republican Freedom.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 17 (1): 2234.Google Scholar
Quong, Jonathan. 2011. Liberalism Without Perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999a. A Theory of Justice. Revised edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999b. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 2001a. Justice as Fairness. A Restatement. Cambridge: The Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 2001b. “Two Concepts of Rules.” In Collected Papers, edited by Rawls, John and Freeman, Samuel, 2046. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 2005. Political Liberalism. Expanded edn. New York: Columbia Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2010. “Human Rights Without Foundations.” In The Philosophy of International Law, edited by Besson, Samantha and Tasioulas, John, 321–37. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reidy, David. 2012. “On the Human Right to Democracy: Searching for Sense without Stilts.” Journal of Social Philosophy 43 (2): 177203.Google Scholar
Reitman, Oonagh. 2004. “On Exit.” In Minorities within Minorities. Equality, Rights and Diversity, edited by Eisenberg, Avigail and Spinner-Halev, Jeff, 189208. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry. 1997. Practical Reasoning About Final Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry. 2000. “Some Limitations of Nussbaum's Capabilities.” Quinnipiac Law Review 19 (2): 309–32.Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry. 2001. “Autonomy's Many Normative Presuppositions.” American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (3): 287303.Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry. 2007. “The Social Background of Capabilities for Freedoms.” Journal of Human Development 8 (3): 389414.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2004. “Authority and Coercion.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 32 (1): 235.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2009. Force and Freedom. Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2005a. “Selecting Capabilities for Quality of Life Measurement.” Social Indicators Research 74 (1): 191215.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2005b. “The Capability Approach: A Theoretical Survey.” Journal of Human Development 6 (1): 93117.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2006. “The Capability Approach in Practice.” Journal of Political Philosophy 14 (3): 351–76.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2008. “Sen's Capability Approach and Feminist Concerns.” In The Capability Approach. Concepts, Measures and Applications, edited by Comim, Flavio, Qizilbash, Mozaffar, and Alkire, Sabine, 105–24. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2016. “Capabilitarianism.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 17 (3): 397414.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2017a. “Having Too Much.” In Nomos LVIII: Wealth, edited by Knight, Jack and Schwartzberg, Melissa, 144. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2017b. Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice. The Capability Approach Re-Examined. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers.Google Scholar
Ronzoni, Miriam. 2010. “Constructivism and Practical Reason: On Intersubjectivity, Abstraction and Judgment.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (1): 74104.Google Scholar
Rose, Carol. 1998. “The Several Futures of Property: Of Cyberspace and Folk Tales, Emissions Trades and Ecosystems.” Minnesota Law Review 83 (1): 129–82.Google Scholar
Rössler, Beate. 2004. The Value of Privacy. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Rostbøll, Christian. 2011. “Kantian Autonomy and Political Liberalism.” Social Theory and Practice 37 (3): 341–64.Google Scholar
Rostbøll, Christian. 2015a. “Non-Domination and Democratic Legitimacy.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 18 (4): 424–39.Google Scholar
Rostbøll, Christian. 2015b. “The Non-Instrumental Value of Democracy: The Freedom Argument.” Constellations 22 (2): 267–78.Google Scholar
Rostbøll, Christian. 2016. “Kant, Freedom as Independence, and Democracy.” The Journal of Politics 78 (3): 792805.Google Scholar
Rothstein, Bo. 1998. Just Institutions Matter. The Moral and Political Logic of the Universal Welfare State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1997. “The Social Contract.” In The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings, edited by Gourevitch, Victor, 39152. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sadurski, Wojciech. 1990. “Joseph Raz on Liberal Neutrality and the Harm Principle.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 10 (1): 122–33.Google Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2012. “Can the Innate Right to Freedom Alone Ground a System of Public and Private Rights?European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3): 460–9.Google Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas. 1972. “A Theory of Freedom of Expression.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 1 (2): 204–26.Google Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas. 2003a. “Rawls on Justification.” In The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, edited by Freeman, Samuel, 139–67. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas. 2003b. “The Diversity of Objections to Inequality.” In The Difficulty of Tolerance, 202–18. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schemmel, Christian. 2011. “Why Relational Egalitarians Should Care About Distributions.” Social Theory and Practice 37 (3): 365–90.Google Scholar
Schuppert, Fabian. 2014. Freedom, Recognition and Non-Domination. A Republican Theory of (Global) Justice. Dordrecht/Heidelberg/New York/London: Springer.Google Scholar
Searle, John. 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Searle, John. 2004. “Social Ontology and Political Power.” In Freedom and Neurobiology. Reflections on Free Will, Language, and Political Power, 79110. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, John. 2005. “What Is an Institution?Journal of Institutional Economics 1 (1): 122.Google Scholar
Searle, John. 2010. Making the Social World. The Structure of Human Civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Segall, Shlomi. 2007. “In Solidarity with the Imprudent: A Defense of Luck Egalitarianism.” Social Theory and Practice 33 (2): 177–98.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1979. “Equality of What.” The Tanner Lectures on Human Values.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1983. “Poverty, Relatively Speaking.” Oxford Economic Papers, New Series 35 (2): 153–69.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1985a. Commodities and Capabilities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1985b. “Well-Being, Agency and Freedom: The Dewey Lectures 1984.” The Journal of Philosophy 82 (4): 169221.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1990. “Justice: Means versus Freedoms.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (2): 111–21.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1992. Inequality Reexamined. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999a. “Democracy as a Universal Value.” Journal of Democracy 10 (3): 317.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999b. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2001. “Reply.” Economics and Philosophy 17 (1): 5166.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2004a. “Capabilities, Lists, and Public Reason: Continuing the Conversation.” Feminist Economics 10 (3): 7780.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2004b. “Elements of a Theory of Human Rights.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 32 (4): 315–56.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2005. “Human Rights and Capabilities.” Journal of Human Development 6 (2): 151–66.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2010. “The Place of Capability in a Theory of Justice.” In Measuring Justice. Primary Goods and Capabilities, edited by Brighouse, Harry and Robeyns, Ingrid, 239–53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sher, George. 1997. Beyond Neutrality. Perfectionism & Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shields, Liam. 2012. “The Prospects for Sufficientarianism.” Utilitas 24 (1): 101–17.Google Scholar
Shue, Henry. 1996. Basic Rights. Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy. 2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Siedentop, Larry. 2014. Inventing the Individual. The Origins of Western Liberalism. Cambridge: The Belknapp Press.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 2013. “Democratic Authority and the Boundary Problem.” Ratio Juris 26 (3): 326–57.Google Scholar
Smith, Matthew, and Seward, Carolina. 2009. “The Relational Ontology of Amartya Sen's Capability Approach: Incorporating Social and Individual Causes.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 10 (2): 213–35.Google Scholar
Song, Sarah. 2012. “The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory: Why the Demos Should Be Bounded by the State.” International Theory 4 (1): 3968.Google Scholar
Srinivasan, Sharath. 2007. “No Democracy without Justice: Political Freedom in Amartya Sen's Capability Approach.” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 8 (3): 457–80.Google Scholar
Stark, Cynthia. 1997. “The Rationality of Valuing Oneself: A Critique of Kant on Self-Respect.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1): 6582.Google Scholar
Stark, Cynthia. 2009. “Respecting Human Dignity: Contract versus Capabilities.” Metaphilosophy 40 (3–4): 366–81.Google Scholar
Stein, Mark. 2009. “Nussbaum: A Utilitarian Critique.” Boston College Law Review 50: 489531.Google Scholar
Steiner, Hillel. 1994. An Essay on Rights. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stiglitz, Joseph. 2012. The Price of Inequality. London/New York: W.W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
Stilz, Anna. 2009. Liberal Loyalty. Freedom, Obligation, and the State. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stoljar, Natalie. 2000. “Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition.” In Relational Autonomy. Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, edited by Mackenzie, Catriona and Stoljar, Natalie, 94111. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stoljar, Natalie. 2014. “Autonomy and Adaptive Preference Formation.” In Autonomy, Oppression, and Gender, edited by Veltman, Andrea and Piper, Mark, 227–52. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stout, Lynn. 2012. The Shareholder Value Myth. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Publishers.Google Scholar
Street, Sharon. 2010. “What Is Constructivism in Ethics and Metaethics?Philosophy Compass 5 (5): 363–84.Google Scholar
Stroud, Barry. 1968. “Transcendental Arguments.” The Journal of Philosophy 65 (9): 241–56.Google Scholar
Strudler, Alan. 2017. “What to Do with Corporate Wealth?Journal of Political Philosophy 25 (1): 108–26.Google Scholar
Sugden, Robert. 2003. “Opportunity as a Space of Individuality: Its Value and the Impossibility of Measuring It.” Ethics 113 (4): 783809.Google Scholar
Sugden, Robert. 2006. “What We Desire, What We Have Reason to Desire, Whatever We Might Desire: Mill and Sen on the Value of Opportunity.” Utilitas 18 (1): 3351.Google Scholar
Sumner, L. W. 2006. “Utility and Capability.” Utilitas 18 (1): 119.Google Scholar
Talbott, William. 2005. Which Rights Should Be Universal? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tan, Kok-Chor. 2008. “A Defense of Luck Egalitarianism.” The Journal of Philosophy 55 (11): 665–90.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, John. 2002. “Human Rights, Universality, and the Values of Personhood.” European Journal of Philosophy 10 (1): 79100.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, John. 2010. “Taking Rights out of Human Rights.” Ethics 120 (4): 647–78.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1985. “Atomism.” In Philosophy and the Human Sciences, 187210. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Temkin, Larry. 2003a. “Egalitarianism Defended.” Ethics 113 (4): 764–82.Google Scholar
Temkin, Larry. 2003b. “Equality, Priority or What?Economics and Philosophy 19 (1): 6187.Google Scholar
Terlazzo, Rosa. 2014. “The Perfectionism of Nussbaum's Adaptive Preferences.” Journal of Global Ethics 10 (2): 183–98.Google Scholar
Terlazzo, Rosa. 2016. “Conceptualizing Adaptive Preferences Respectfully: An Indirectly Substantive Account.” Journal of Political Philosophy 24 (2): 206–26.Google Scholar
Teschl, Miriam, and Comim, Flavio. 2005. “Adaptive Preferences and Capabilities: Some Preliminary Conceptual Explorations.” Review of Social Economy 63 (2): 229–47.Google Scholar
Tierney, Brian. 1997. The Idea of Natural Rights. Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law and Church Law 1150–1625. Atlanta: Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Tomasi, John. 2012. Free Market Fairness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tuck, Richard. 1979. Natural Rights Theories. Their Origin and Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2012. “Kant, Ripstein and the Circle of Freedom: A Critical Note.” European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3): 450–9.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2013. “Justice, Disagreement and Democracy.” British Journal of Political Science 43 (1): 177–99.Google Scholar
Van Duffel, Siegfried. 2013. “Natural Rights to Welfare.” European Journal of Philosophy 21 (4): 641–64.Google Scholar
Van Hees, Martin. 2012. “Rights, Goals and Capabilities.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 12 (3): 247–59.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, Philippe. 1995. Real Freedom for All. What (If Anything) Can Justify Capitalism? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vizard, Poly. 2007. “Specifying and Justifying a Basic Capability Set: Should the International Human Rights Framework Be given a More Direct Role?Oxford Development Studies 35 (3): 225–50.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1988. The Right to Private Property. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1989. “Autonomy and Perfectionism in Raz's Morality of Freedom.” Southern California Law Review 62: 10971152.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1999. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2004. “Liberalism, Political and Comprehensive.” In Handbook of Political Theory, edited by Gaus, Gerald F. and Kukathas, Chandran, 8999. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Wall, Steven. 1998. Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wall, Steven. 2006. “Rawls and the Status of Political Liberty.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (2): 245–70.Google Scholar
Wall, Steven, and Klosko, George. 2003. “Introduction.” In Perfectionism and Neutrality. Essays in Liberal Theory, edited by Wall, Steven and Klosko, George, 127. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Weinstock, Daniel. 2004. “Beyond Exit Rights: Reframing the Debate.” In Minorities within Minorities. Equality, Rights and Diversity, edited by Eisenberg, Avigail, 227–46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wenar, Leif. 2005. “The Nature of Rights.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (3): 223–52.Google Scholar
Wenar, Leif. 2013. “The Nature of Claim-Rights.” Ethics 123 (2): 202–29.Google Scholar
Westlund, Andrea. 2003. “Selflessness and Responsibility for Self: Is Deference Compatible With Autonomy?The Philosophical Review 112 (4): 483523.Google Scholar
Whelan, Frederick. 1983. “Prologue: Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem.” In Liberal Democracy, edited by Roland Pennock, J. and Chapman, John W., 1347. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
White, Michael. 2012. Political Philosophy. A Historical Introduction. 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
White, Stuart. 1997. “Freedom of Association and the Right to Exclude.” Journal of Political Philosophy 5 (4): 373–91.Google Scholar
White, Stuart. 2003. The Civic Minimum. On the Rights and Obligations of Economic Citizenship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
White, Stuart. 2013. “Freedom of Association.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, edited by LaFollette, Hugh, 373–82. London: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Wilkinson, Richard, and Pickett, Kate. 2010. The Spirit Level. Why Equality Is Better for Everyone. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Williamson, Thad. 2012. “Realizing Property-Owning Democracy.” In Property-Owning Democracy. Rawls and Beyond, edited by O'Neill, Martin and Williamson, Thad, 225–48. Malden and Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Winch, Peter. 1990. The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy. 2nd edn. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wolff, Jonathan, and De-Shalit, Avner. 2007. Disadvantage. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 2011. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ypi, Lea. 2008. “Statist Cosmopolitanism.” Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (1): 4871.Google Scholar
Zale, Kellen. 2016. “Sharing Property.” University of Colorado Law Review 87: 501–79.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Rutger Claassen, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
  • Book: Capabilities in a Just Society
  • Online publication: 04 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108561853.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Rutger Claassen, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
  • Book: Capabilities in a Just Society
  • Online publication: 04 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108561853.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Rutger Claassen, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
  • Book: Capabilities in a Just Society
  • Online publication: 04 October 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108561853.013
Available formats
×