Published online by Cambridge University Press: 13 June 2017
In Chapter 4, we looked at concrete algorithms for reasoning in ALC and some of its extensions. In this chapter, we are taking a more abstract viewpoint and discuss the computational complexity of reasoning, which essentially is the question of how efficient we can expect any reasoning algorithm for a given problem to be, even on very difficult (“worst-case”) inputs. Although we will concentrate on the basic reasoning problems satisfiability and subsumption for the sake of simple exposition, all results established in this chapter also apply to the corresponding KB consistency problem. In fact, there are very few relevant cases in which the computational complexity of satisfiability and of KB consistency diverge. We start with ALC and show that the complexity of satisfiability and of subsumption depend on the TBox formalism that is used: without TBoxes and with acyclic TBoxes, it is PSPACE-complete while general TBoxes raise the complexity to EXPTIME-complete. Then we consider two extensions of ALC, ALCOI and ALCOIQ, and show that satisfiability and subsumption are more difficult in these DLs: in ALCOI, satisfiability and subsumption are EXPTIME-complete already without TBoxes. We show only hardness to illustrate the increase in complexity. In ALCOIQ, reasoning even becomes NEXPTIME-complete (without TBoxes). Again, we show only hardness. Finally, we consider two extensions of ALC that render reasoning undecidable: role value maps and a certain concrete domain based on the natural numbers and incrementation.
Before starting to analyse the computational complexity of DLs, let us recall some basics of complexity theory. A complexity class is a set of problems that share some relevant computational property such as being solvable within the same resource bounds. For example, PTIME is the class of all problems that can be solved by a deterministic Turing machine in time polynomial in the size of the input. In this chapter, we will mainly be concerned with the following standard complexity classes, which we order according to set inclusion:
The reader is referred to standard textbooks on complexity theory for the exact definition of these classes [AB09, Sip97, Pap94]. It is commonly believed that the inclusions shown above are all strict, but proofs have not yet been found.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.