Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b6zl4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T11:24:13.870Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

OMEGA-CATEGORICAL PSEUDOFINITE GROUPS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 January 2025

DUGALD MACPHERSON*
Affiliation:
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF LEEDS LEEDS UK
KATRIN TENT
Affiliation:
MATHEMATISCHES INSTITUT UNIVERSITY OF MÜNSTER MÜNSTER GERMANY E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We explore the interplay between $\omega $-categoricity and pseudofiniteness for groups, and we conjecture that $\omega $-categorical pseudofinite groups are finite-by-abelian-by-finite. We show that the conjecture reduces to nilpotent p-groups of class 2, and give a proof that several of the known examples of $\omega $-categorical p-groups satisfy the conjecture. In particular, we show by a direct counting argument that for any odd prime p the ($\omega $-categorical) model companion of the theory of nilpotent class 2 exponent p groups, constructed by Saracino and Wood, is not pseudofinite, and that an $\omega $-categorical group constructed by Baudisch with supersimple rank 1 theory is not pseudofinite. We also survey some scattered literature on $\omega $-categorical groups over 50 years.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

This paper explores the interplay between two model-theoretic finitary conditions on infinite groups: $\omega $ -categoricity and pseudofiniteness. We recall that a countably infinite first order structure is $\omega $ -categorical if any countably infinite N with the same first order theory as M is isomorphic to M, or equivalently, if ${{\mathrm {Aut}}}(M)$ acts oligomorphically on M, that is, has finitely many orbits on $M^n$ for all n. We say a structure M is pseudofinite if it is infinite and every first order sentence true of M has a finite model. We make the following conjecture, motivating this paper.

Conjecture 1.1. Every $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite group G is definably finite-by-abelian-by-finite. More precisely, G has a definable 2-step nilpotent normal subgroup N of finite index which has finite derived subgroup.

We shall describe such G as “finite-by-abelian-by-finite”, and note that this is unambiguous: any finite-by-(abelian-by-finite) group is clearly (finite-by-abelian)-by-finite, and conversely, if G has a finite-by-abelian normal subgroup N of finite index, then its derived subgroup $N'$ is finite and characteristic in N so normal in G, and G is finite-by-(abelian-by-finite). Furthermore, as noted in the introduction to [Reference Evans and Wagner18], we may take N to be characteristic. The upshot is that we may suppose that the normal subgroups of G witnessing “finite-by-abelian-by-finite” are characteristic and hence (by $\omega $ -categoricity) definable without parameters, and from now on we just call such a group G an FAF group.

We show that Conjecture 1.1 reduces to the case of $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite p-groups of nilpotency class at most $2$ .

Proposition 1.2. Conjecture 1.1 holds if every $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite p-group of class at most 2 is FAF.

It is easy to give examples of $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite groups which are abelian (e.g., elementary abelian p-groups), and which are finite-by-abelian but not abelian-by-finite (see also the examples in 2.14). For the latter, the extraspecial p-groups of exponent p (p odd) provide examples: they are $\omega $ -categorical by [Reference Felgner19], and pseudofinite since they are smoothly approximated (in the sense of [Reference Kantor, Liebeck and Macpherson24]) by finite extraspecial p-groups, as noted in [Reference Kantor, Liebeck and Macpherson24, ‘Added in proof’]. See [Reference Milliet33, Appendix A] for further discussion of the model theory of extraspecial groups. The construction of extraspecial groups is generalized in [Reference Apps2, Theorem A], where it is shown that if G is a finite nilpotent class 2 group and K is a subgroup with $G'\leq K\leq Z(G)$ , then the central product of $\aleph _0$ copies of G, amalgamated over K, is $\omega $ -categorical.

We give a short proof in Section 2 of the following result, an easy consequence of known results on $\omega $ -categorical groups.

Proposition 1.3. Every $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite group is nilpotent-by-finite.

We then show that Conjecture 1.1 holds for many of the $\omega $ -categorical class 2 groups that we know of, in particular (for odd primes p) for the model companion of the theory of exponent p class 2 p-groups described by Saracino and Wood in [Reference Saracino and Wood35], and various generaliations; namely the comprehensive groups of Apps [Reference Apps2] (see Theorems 2.10 and 2.11) and higher nilpotency class generaliations of the Saracino-Wood groups, considered in [Reference Maier31], [Reference Baudisch5], [Reference Baudisch8], and [Reference d’Elbée, Müller, Ramsey and Siniora17]. In particular, we prove the following result (Corollary 2.8 below).

Theorem 1.4.

  1. (i) For p an odd prime, the unique countable existentially closed nilpotent class 2 group of exponent p is not pseudofinite.

  2. (ii) The $\omega $ -categorical groups $D(n)$ with supersimple rank 1 theory considered by Baudisch in [Reference Baudisch8] are not pseudofinite for $n\geq 2$ .

We remark that Baudisch [Reference Baudisch8] showed that the group in (i) has TP ${}_2$ theory. More recently, d’Elbée, Müller, Ramsey and Siniora [Reference d’Elbée, Müller, Ramsey and Siniora17, Corollary 3.7] have shown it to have an NSOP ${}_1$ theory. Part (ii) above shows that not every $\omega $ -categorical finite-by-abelian group is pseudofinite, i.e., the converse to our conjecture is false: the groups $D(n)$ for n finite are all finite-by-abelian.

A theory has the strict order property if it has a model M such that there is a definable preorder on some power $M^n$ with an infinite totally ordered subset, and a model has the strict order property if its theory has. We say the model (or theory) is NSOP otherwise. It is easy to see that an $\omega $ -categorical structure with the strict order property is not pseudofinite (see Lemma 2.1). The obvious ways to show that a structure is not pseudofinite are to define a partial ordering which is dense or has no greatest element, or to define a map $f:X \to X$ which is injective but not surjective, or vice-versa. Such a function cannot be definable in an $\omega $ -categorical structure, since it would lead to pairs from X at arbitrary “distance” with respect to f. We believe Theorem 1.4 may be the first result proving non-pseudofiniteness of an $\omega $ -categorical structure without the strict order property, and that (ii) may be the first example of an $\omega $ -categorical supersimple non-pseudofinite structure. (In the other direction, Kruckman in [Reference Kruckman25, Theorem 4.5] shows that the theory $T_{\mathrm {feq}}^{*}$ of parametrised equivalence relations is $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite but not supersimple.) Of course, pseudofiniteness is unknown for many $\omega $ -categorical structures – for example it is a well-known open problem posed by Cherlin for the universal homogeneous triangle-free graph (see [Reference Cherlin10, Problem A’], or [Reference Cherlin11]).

Some background on $\omega $ -categorical groups. The structure of $\omega $ -categorical groups has been revisited since the early 1970s by many authors, and some substantial literature appears to be little known. We summarize some aspects here, focussing on themes related to Conjecture 1.1.

First, there are several results recovering our intended conclusion, i.e., showing that $\omega $ -categorical groups satisfying certain model-theoretic hypotheses are FAF. For example, by [Reference Baur, Cherlin and Macintyre9] every $\omega $ -categorical superstable group is abelian-by-finite (but under stability only virtual nilpotency is known [Reference Baur, Cherlin and Macintyre9, Reference Felgner20]). This is generalized in [Reference Evans and Wagner18], where it is shown that every $\omega $ -categorical group with supersimple theory is FAF. The latter also generalizes Proposition 6.2.4 from [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14] where the same conclusion is obtained for groups interpretable in a smoothly approximable structure; such structures are known to be supersimple. (In [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14, Proposition 6.2.4], there are assumptions of finite rank, type amalgamation and modularity—these are shown to hold for smoothly approximable structures in Corollary 2.2.11, Proposition 5.1.15, and Corollary 5.6.4 respectively—note that smooth approximation is equivalent to Lie coordinatisability by [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14, Theorem 2].) Finally, by [Reference Dobrowolski and Wagner16], every $\omega $ -categorical group of finite burden is FAF. In each case, there is some notion of rank, and the arguments often proceed by identifying minimal abelian groups and working with definable isogenies. Some of these results have ring-theoretic analogs, and as noted at the end of this paper, Conjecture 1.1 has a ring-theoretic equivalent, namely Conjecture 3.5.

An important construction technique for $\omega $ -categorical algebraic objects is that of boolean powers. For groups, one takes an $\omega $ -categorical or finite group G equipped with the discrete topology, the Stone space S of a countable $\omega $ -categorical Boolean algebra B (for example the countable atomless Boolean algebra, in which case S is a Cantor space), and forms the group $B[G]$ consisting of all continuous maps $S\to G$ , with coordinatewise multiplication as the group operation. There is an analogous construction (see Section 2 of [Reference Apps3], or [Reference Wilson, Campbell and Robertson39, Section 2]) when B is an $\omega $ -categorical Boolean ring without a 1: in the case above corresponding to the Cantor set, one obtains the group $B^-(G)$ consisting of all $f:S \to G$ with $f(x_0)=1_G$ , where $x_0\in S$ is specified. It is easily seen that if G is an $\omega $ -categorical group which is nilpotent of class 2 but not abelian, and B is infinite, then $B[G]$ and $B^-[G]$ are $\omega $ -categorical nilpotent class 2 and not FAF (see for example the paragraph before Proposition 4.1 in [Reference Apps2]). By the easy Lemma 3.1 below, such groups are not pseudofinite. For more on Boolean powers of groups, see also [Reference Apps1]. In particular, since any $\omega $ -categorical group has a maximally refined chain of characteristic subgroups with characteristically simple and $\omega $ -categorical or finite successive quotients, [Reference Apps3, Theorem A] gives an approach to structural questions about $\omega $ -categorical groups.

A number of authors have revisited the subject of $\omega $ -categorical nilpotent groups, from the viewpoints of Fraïssé limits, existentially closed groups in certain classes, and model companions. We summarize briefly what is known.

Saracino and Wood [Reference Saracino and Wood35, Theorem 3.9], among other results, show that for every finite $m\geq 2$ the collection of nilpotent class 2 groups of exponent m has a model companion, and this model companion is $\omega $ -categorical. The proof is essentially by identifying appropriate axioms (of the form generalised by Apps, see below). A related thread of work explores groups whose theory has quantifier-elimination. Work of Cherlin and Felgner [Reference Cherlin and Felgner12] reduces the classification to that of QE nilpotent class 2 groups of exponent 4. In [Reference Saracino and Wood36], constructions are given of $2^{\aleph _0}$ non-isomorphic countable $\omega $ -categorical such groups. The construction is analogous to that of Henson [Reference Henson21] of homogeneous digraphs: the authors find a family $\mathcal {F}$ of mutually non-embeddable finite class 2 groups of exponent 4, for each $S\subset \mathcal {F}$ consider the class of finite class 2 groups of exponent at most 4 not embedding a member of S, and show this class has the amalgamation property; distinct sets S yield non-isomorphic Fraïssé limits. This approach is developed further in [Reference Cherlin, Saracino and Wood15] with a view also to constructions of homogeneous rings.

Apps [Reference Apps2], generalizing the Saracino–Wood construction of model companions for the theory of class 2 p-groups with a given bound on the exponent (not necessarily prime), gives the construction of comprehensive groups described in Section 2 below. The key point is that the centre $Z(G)$ is specified in advance, together with the exponents of $Z(G)$ , $G/Z(G)$ , and G. For given data satisfying certain conditions, the model companion of such a class is described in [Reference Apps2, Theorem D].

Maier in the late 1980s wrote a series of papers on constructions of existentially closed nilpotent groups in various classes. The proofs are based on an intricate adaptation, using Lazard series, of Higman’s amalgamation results for nilpotent groups (see [Reference Higman23]), where the groups are equipped with a common central series. In particular, in [Reference Maier31, Theorem 3.5], Maier shows that for p an odd prime and $c<p$ the class of groups of nilpotency class c and exponent p has a unique existentially closed member, its model companion, which is $\omega $ -categorical. The main focus of Maier’s paper is elsewhere, and he notes that in the case $c=2$ , Saracino and Wood had already constructed this model companion in [Reference Saracino and Wood35, Theorem 3.9].

Baudisch [Reference Baudisch5] shows that for an odd prime p the class of finite groups of exponent p and class at most 2, equipped with a predicate for a central subgroup, has the amalgamation property. Its Fraïssé limit will as a group be isomorphic to the model companion of the collection of class 2 exponent p groups. It follows that the latter group has quantifier-elimination once a predicate is added for its centre, and Baudisch also shows that this group does not have simple theory, since there is an infinite descending chain of centralisers of finite sets, each with infinite index in its predecessor. In more recent work Baudisch also shows in [Reference Baudisch8] that its theory is TP ${}_2$ . He explores in [Reference Baudisch6, Reference Baudisch7] generalizations of the construction in [Reference Baudisch5] to arbitrary nilpotency class $c<p$ . The approach to amalgamation is analogous to that of Maier, and there is a precursor (for $c=2$ ) in [Reference Saracino37].

Very recently, d’Elbée, Müller, Ramsey and Siniora [Reference d’Elbée, Müller, Ramsey and Siniora17] have revisited the results of Baudisch and Maier. They give a careful description of the amalgamation in the context of Lie algebras L equipped with a “Lazard series”, that is, a series $L=L_0\geq L_1 \geq \ldots \geq L_{c+1}=0$ , with $[L_i,L_j]\leq L_{i+j}$ for all $i,j$ (where $L_k=0$ for all $k>c$ ). They transfer the amalgamation from such “Lazard Lie algebras” to the corresponding class of finite groups (exponent p, class at most c, where $c<p$ , equipped with a Lazard series). This yields a Fraïssé limit $\mathbf {G}_{c,p}$ , which is $\omega $ -categorical, and exactly the model companion of the class of exponent p groups of class at most c constructed by Maier in [Reference Maier31, Theorem 3.5]. They show that the groups $\mathbf {G}_{2,p}$ are NSOP ${}_1$ —it was already known from Baudisch’s work that they do not have supersimple theory. Strikingly, they also show that for $c\geq 3$ the group $G_{c,p}$ is SOP ${}_3$ and NSOP ${}_4$ , and is c-dependent and $(c-1)$ -independent (i.e., strictly NSOP ${}_4$ and strictly NIP ${}_c$ ).

Structure of the paper. Propositions 1.2 and 1.3, along with Theorem 1.4, are proved in Section 2. We also show in Theorem 2.11 that Apps’s comprehensive groups are not pseudofinite provided they have non-cyclic centre. The section includes a discussion of pseudofiniteness for $\omega $ -categorical FAF groups. In Section 3 we note that the Boolean power construction does not yield counterexamples to our conjecture, that a counterexample will not arise from an ultraproduct of finite p-groups with large automorphism groups, and present the ring-theoretic analogue of the conjecture.

2 Saracino–Wood groups and variants

In this section we reduce our conjecture to the case of nilpotent class 2 groups, and then show that several variants of the Saracino–Wood existentially closed nilpotent class 2 exponent p group (for p an odd prime) are not pseudofinite. We do not consider the case $p=2$ (where there are analogs of exponent 4). Since it is short and central to the paper, we first include a proof of the following easy result. See also [Reference Kruckman25, Proposition 1.3], where the result is described as folklore.

Lemma 2.1. Let M be an $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite structure. Then M does not have the strict order property.

Proof. Suppose that M is $\omega $ -categorical with the strict order property. Then (possibly naming parameters by constants) there is a 0-definable preorder $<$ on some power $M^d$ of M, with an infinite chain. By $\omega $ -categoricity there are finitely many 2-types, so by Ramsey’s theorem there is a formula $\phi (x,y)$ isolating a complete 2-type and implying the formula $x<y$ , and $\{a_i:i\in \omega \}\in M^d$ such that $\phi (a_i,a_j)$ holds whenever $i<j$ . In particular, some sentence $\sigma $ of ${\mathrm {Th}}(M)$ expresses that $<$ is a preorder, that $\phi (x,y)$ implies $x<y$ , that $\exists x\exists y\phi (x,y)$ , and that $\forall x\forall y\big (\phi (x,y) \to \exists z(\phi (x,z)\wedge \phi (z,y))\big )$ ; the last implication holds since $M\models \phi (a_1,a_3) \wedge \exists z(\phi (a_1,z)\wedge \phi (z,a_3))$ , and because $\phi $ isolates a complete type. Such a sentence clearly has no finite model.

We thus obtain a first step (Proposition 1.3 of the introduction) towards proving Conjecture 1.1.

Corollary 2.2. Let G be an $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite group. Then G has a nilpotent 0-definable normal subgroup of finite index.

Proof. By Lemma 2.1, G does not have the strict order property. The result now follows immediately from [Reference Macpherson28, Theorem 1.2].

For any nilpotent group G of class c we write

$$ \begin{align*}G=\gamma_1G>\gamma_2G>\ldots >\gamma_{c+1}G=1\end{align*} $$

for the lower central series of G.

Remark 2.3. In arguments below we shall use that if H is a nilpotent group of class 2 and $x,y\in H$ then for any $n\geq 1$ we have $[x,y]^n=[x^n,y]$ . This is proved easily by induction. In particular, the exponent of $\gamma _2H$ divides that of $\gamma _1H/\gamma _2H$ . We also use the identities $[xz,y]=[x,y]^z[z,y]$ and $[x,y]^{-1}=[y,x]$ , the latter giving $[H,G]=[G,H]$ whenever H is a subgroup of G.

We aim next for Corollary 2.5, which is just Proposition 1.2 from the Introduction. First, we give a lemma, for which we are very grateful to Laurent Bartholdi for supplying the proof.

Lemma 2.4. Let G be a p-group of class 3, and let $|\gamma _2G/\gamma _3G|=p^m$ . Then $|\gamma _3G|\leq p^{2m^3}$ . In particular G is finite-by-abelian.

Proof. First observe that $\gamma _2G/\gamma _3G$ has exponent at most $p^m$ , and every irredundant generating set has size at most m. Thus $\gamma _2G$ can be generated by $\gamma _3 G$ and a set of m commutators $[a,b]$ in G. Let S be the set of these $a,b$ , so S has size at most $2m$ . Let H be the subgroup of G generated by S and $\gamma _3G$ . Then $\gamma _2G\leq H$ , so H is normal in G. Furthermore,

$$ \begin{align*}\gamma_2G\geq [H,G]\gamma_3G\geq [H,H]\gamma_3G\geq\gamma_2G.\end{align*} $$

so

$$ \begin{align*}[H,H]\gamma_3G=\gamma_2G=[H,G]\gamma_3G=[G,G].\end{align*} $$

For $x,y\in H$ and $z\in G$ , the Hall–Witt identity

$$ \begin{align*}{\displaystyle [[x,y^{-1}],z]^{y}\cdot [[y,z^{-1}],x]^{z}\cdot [[z,x^{-1}],y]^{x}=1}\end{align*} $$

and the fact that H is normal in G, it now follows that

$$ \begin{align*}[[H,H],G] \leq [[H,G],H]\cdot [[G,H],H]=[[G,H],H].\end{align*} $$

Since $\gamma _3G\leq Z(G)$ we now have

$$ \begin{align*} \gamma_3G &= [\gamma_2G,G] = [[H,H]\gamma_3G,G]=[[H,H],G]\leq [[G,H],H]\\ & =[[G,H]\gamma_3G,H]=[[H,H],H]. \end{align*} $$

Note that since $\gamma _3G\leq Z(G)$ , for $x,z\in S$ and $y\in \gamma _2G$ we have $[x,y]\in Z(G)$ and so $[xz,y]=[x,y]^z[z,y]=[x,y][z,y]$ . Hence $\gamma _3G$ is generated by a set of commutators $[x,y]$ where $x\in S$ and $y\in \gamma _2G$ is from a set (of size at most m) which gives a generating set of $\gamma _2G/\gamma _3G$ . So $\gamma _3G$ is generated by a set of size at most $2m^2$ . By Remark 2.3 (applied to the class 2 group $\gamma _2G$ ), $\gamma _3G$ has exponent at most $p^m$ . Thus $|\gamma _3G|\leq p^{f(m)}$ where $f(m)=2m^3$ .

Corollary 2.5. Suppose (A) every $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite p-group of class at most 2 is FAF.

Then the same conclusion holds for all $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite groups.

Proof. In the argument below, we may assume that normal subgroups witnessing the FAF condition are characteristic and hence 0-definable; see the discussion of FAF groups after Conjecture 1.1.

Let G be an $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite group. By Corollary 2.2 and the last paragraph we may suppose that G is nilpotent. As any periodic nilpotent group is a direct product of its Sylow subgroups, we may further suppose that G is a p-group for some prime p.

Observe that under (A), any pseudofinite $\omega $ -categorical p-group with a class 2 definable normal subgroup of finite index, or with a finite normal subgoup with class 2 quotient, is FAF. For by (A), the class 2 piece is FAF, and absorbs the finite piece at the top or bottom.

Since there are only finitely many characteristic subgroups, we may suppose by the previous paragraph that G has no proper characteristic subgroup of finite index. Likewise, we may suppose that G has no non-trivial finite characteristic subgroup. Hence we aim to show that G is abelian.

We now use induction on the nilpotency class of G and let $1\neq \gamma _kG\leq Z(G)$ be the smallest non-trivial term of the lower central series. We need to show $k=1$ . By assumption (A) and our reduction of G we know that $k\neq 2$ . So suppose towards a contradiction that $k\geq 3$ . By induction and since G has no proper characteristic subgroup of finite index, $\bar {G}=G/\gamma _kG$ has finite commutator group $\bar {G}'$ and $\bar {G}= C_{\bar {G}}(\bar {G}')$ . Thus G has nilpotency class 3. Consider the lower central series $G=\gamma _1G>\gamma _2G>\gamma _3G>1$ and note that $\gamma _2G/\gamma _3G\cong \bar {G}'$ is finite. By Lemma 2.4, G is finite-by-abelian, with a non-trivial finite characteristic subgroup, contradicting our assumption. Hence $k=1$ and G is abelian.

Our next goal is to show that certain constructions of $\omega $ -categorical p-groups discussed in the papers [Reference Apps2, Reference Baudisch4Reference Baudisch6, Reference Cherlin, Saracino and Wood15, Reference Maier31, Reference Saracino and Wood35] are not pseudofinite. In order to make the idea as explicit as possible in the simplest case, we first consider existentially closed class 2 p-groups of exponent p.

Let p be an odd prime. By [Reference Saracino and Wood35, Theorem 3.9], the theory $T_{{\mathrm {nil2}},p}$ of existentially closed nilpotent class 2 exponent p groups is complete, and is axiomatized by a sentence $\rho $ expressing that a model G is a nilpotent, class 2 exponent p group and that the centre is the set of commutators, an axiom scheme expressing that the centre is infinite, and the following axiom scheme $\Sigma _n:=\{\sigma _n:n>0\}$ . Here $\sigma _n$ expresses:

$$ \begin{align*}(\forall \mbox{~linearly independent~} g_1,\ldots,g_n\in G\setminus Z(G))( \forall h_1,\ldots,h_n\in Z(G))(\exists k\in G)\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\left(\bigwedge_{i=1}^n [g_i,k]=h_i\right).\end{align*} $$

Here linear independence is interpreted in the sense of the $\mathbb {F}_p$ -vector space $G/Z(G)$ . As noted in [Reference Saracino and Wood35, Theorem 3.9], $T_{{\mathrm {nil2}},p}$ is $\omega $ -categorical. However, the following lemma yields that $\rho \wedge \sigma _1\wedge \sigma _2\wedge \tau $ has no finite model, where $\tau $ expresses that the centre has order at least $p^2$ .

Lemma 2.6. Let p be an odd prime, and let $(V,W,\beta )$ be a 2-sorted structure where $V,W$ are vector spaces over $\mathbb {F}_p$ (each sort viewed in the usual language of $\mathbb {F}_p$ -modules) of dimension at least 2 and $\beta :V\times V \to W$ is bilinear. Let $\chi $ be a sentence expressing this information, and $\psi $ be the sentence

$$ \begin{align*}(\forall \mbox{~linearly independent~}v_1,v_2\in V) (\forall w_1,w_2\in W)\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}(\exists z\in V)(\beta(v_1,z)=w_1\wedge \beta(v_2,z)=w_2).\end{align*} $$

Then $\chi \wedge \psi $ has no finite model.

Proof. Suppose for a contradiction that $(V',W',\beta )$ is a finite model of $\chi \wedge \psi $ , with $\dim (V')=n>1$ and $\dim (W')=d>1$ . For each $v\in V'$ , the map $\beta _v:V'\to W'$ given by $\beta _v(x)=\beta (v,x)$ is linear, and is surjective as $(V',W',\beta )\models \psi $ . Thus the kernel $K_v$ of $\beta _v$ has index $p^d$ . Furthermore, $\psi $ ensures that if $v_1,v_2\in V'$ are linearly independent then any two cosets $K_{v_1}+a_1$ and $K_{v_2}+a_2$ intersect: indeed, if $w_i=\beta (v_i,a_i)$ for $i=1,2$ then because $(V',W',\beta )\models \psi $ there is $z\in V'$ with $\beta (v_1,z)=w_1\wedge \beta (v_2,z)=w_2$ , and we have $z\in (K_{v_1}+a_1) \cap (K_{v_2}+a_2)$ . Thus $K_{v_1}+K_{v_2}=V'$ , for if $z\in V'$ there is $u_1\in K_{v_1}\cap (K_{v_2}+z)$ , so $u_1=u_2+z$ for some $u_2\in K_{v_2}$ , and $z=u_1-u_2\in K_{v_1}+K_{v_2}$ . Thus, we have a collection consisting of $ \frac {p^n-1}{p-1}$ such kernels $K_v$ , each of codimension d in $V'$ , such that any two span $V'$ . By moving to the dual space $(V')^*$ and taking annihilators, we find a family consisting of $\frac {p^n-1}{p-1}$ subspaces of $(V')^*$ each of dimension d, with pairwise intersection $\{0\}$ . Since $d>1$ , this is clearly impossible by counting vectors in $(V')^{*}$ .

Corollary 2.7. Suppose that G is an $\omega $ -categorical nilpotent group of class 2 and exponent p (where p is an odd prime) with both the centre Z and the group $G/Z$ elementary abelian of rank at least 2, and such that $G\models \sigma _1\wedge \sigma _2$ . Then G is not pseudofinite.

Proof. This follows immediately from Lemma 2.6. Indeed, if such G were pseudofinite, then there would be a finite group H satisfying the corresponding conditions. Put $V=H/Z(H)$ and $W=Z(H)$ – these are elementary abelian p-groups and so vector spaces over $\mathbb {F}_p$ . Let $\beta $ be the commutator map $V\times V \to W$ given by $[gZ(H),hZ(H)]=[g,h]$ . The axioms $\rho \wedge \sigma _1\wedge \sigma _2$ yield that $(V,W,\beta )\models \chi \wedge \psi $ , contrary to Lemma 2.6.

This yields almost immediately the following result, and hence gives Theorem 1.4. The groups $D(n)$ (for n finite) are $\omega $ -categorical nilpotent class 2 and exponent p, with centre elementary abelian of rank n. By [Reference Baudisch8, Theorem 3], they are supersimple of SU-rank 1. Note that for $n=1$ the group is extraspecial, so pseudofinite.

Corollary 2.8. Let p be an odd prime.

  1. (i) The theory $T_{{\mathrm {nil2}},p}$ is not pseudofinite.

  2. (ii) For $n\geq 2$ the group $D(n)$ discussed by Baudisch in [Reference Baudisch8] is not pseudofinite.

Proof. Case (i) follows immediately from the corollary by the above axiomatisation of $T_{{\mathrm {nil2}},p}$ . The groups $D(n)$ in (ii) are built by an amalgamation argument, working with the class of finite nilpotent class 2 exponent p groups G expanded by linearly independent constants $c_1,\ldots ,c_n$ such that $G'\leq \langle c_1,\ldots ,c_n\rangle \leq Z(G)$ . These also satisfy $\sigma _1\wedge \sigma _2$ ; this is perhaps most easily verified by working in the category $\mathbb {B}^P$ with objects $(V,W,\beta )$ where $V,W$ are vector spaces over $\mathbb {F}_p$ and $\beta :V\times V \to W$ is an alternating bilinear map, as described in [Reference Baudisch8, Section 3]; we may take $W=\langle c_1,\ldots ,c_n\rangle $ .

Remark 2.9. The counting argument in Lemma 2.6 is quite extravagant, and does not seem to require the full strength of $\psi $ . This suggests a conceivable route to a counterexample to our conjecture, by building a group with sparse satisfaction of $\sigma _2$ , possibly exploiting the Shelah–Spencer zero-one laws from [Reference Shelah and Spencer38].

We now turn to Apps’s more general class of comprehensive groups, which we briefly summarize. First recall that if A is an abelian p-group and $g\in A$ , then the height ${\mathrm {ht}}_A(g)$ is defined to be ${\mathrm {sup}}\{n\geq 0:g=h^{p^n} \mbox {~for some~}h\in A\}$ . A subgroup B of A is pure in A if ${\mathrm {ht}}_B(g)={\mathrm {ht}}_A(g)$ for all $g\in B$ . For a group A of finite exponent, write ${\mathrm {exp}}(A)$ for the exponent of A. Building on work in [Reference Saracino and Wood35], for p a prime Apps [Reference Apps2] defines a nilpotent class 2 p-group G with centre Z to be comprehensive if it satisfies the following condition, where $|g|$ denotes the order of a group element g, $G^*=G/Z$ , and for $g\in G$ , $g^*$ denotes its image in $G^*$ :

( $*$ ) Let A be a finite pure subgroup of $G^*$ , let $\alpha \in {\mathrm {Hom}}(A,Z)$ , let $w\in Z$ and $r\in \mathbb {N}$ , and suppose ${\mathrm {exp}}(\alpha (A))\leq p^r\leq {\mathrm {exp}}(G^*)$ and $p^r|w|\leq {\mathrm {exp}}(G)$ . Then there is $g\in G$ such that $\langle A,g^*\rangle =A\oplus \langle g^*\rangle $ is pure in $G^*$ , $|g^*|=p^r, g^{p^r}=w$ , and $[a, g^*]=\alpha (a)$ for all $a\in A$ . (Here, the natural map $G^*\times G^*\to Z$ induced by commutation in G is also denoted by $[-,-]$ .)

Given an abelian p-group Z and $t,u\in \mathbb {N}$ , Apps defines $\mathcal {N}_2(p^u,p^t/Z)$ to be the class of groups G of exponent $p^u$ with centre Z such that ${\mathrm {exp}}(G^*)=p^t$ . He proves the following (restricted below to finite exponent, the area of our interest).

Theorem 2.10 [Reference Apps2, Theorem C].

Let p be prime, Z a countable abelian group of finite exponent $p^s$ and suppose $t,u\in \mathbb {N}$ with $s+t\geq u\geq s\geq t$ , with also $u> t$ if $p=2$ . Then there is a unique countable comprehensive group G in $\mathcal {N}_2(p^u,p^t/Z)$ , and G is $\omega $ -categorical.

It can be checked that for p an odd prime, $s=t=u=1$ , and Z an elementary abelian p-group of rank n, the corresponding comprehensive group is exactly Baudisch’s group $D(n)$ .

Theorem 2.11. Let $Z,p, s,t,u$ and the comprehensive group G be as in Theorem 2.10, with p odd. Assume Z contains an elementary abelian p-group of rank 2 (i.e., Z is not cyclic). Then G is not pseudofinite.

Proof. Suppose for a contradiction that G is pseudofinite. Let $G_0^*$ be the subgroup of $G^*$ consisting of elements of height 0 and order p, together with the identity. By [Reference Apps2, Lemma 3.2(a)], the group $G_0^*$ is infinite. Let $G_0$ be the preimage of $G_0^*$ under the map $G \to G^*$ . Clearly $G_0$ is characteristic in G, so is $\emptyset $ -definable and so is $\omega $ -categorical and also pseudofinite. Let $Z_0$ be the subgroup of Z consisting of elements of order at most p. Then $Z_0$ is an elementary abelian p-group of rank at least 2. Since $[x,y]^p=[x^p,y]$ for any $x,y\in G_0$ by Remark 2.3, the commutator map $G_0 \times G_0 \to Z$ induces a bilinear map $\beta :G_0^* \times G_0^* \to Z_0$ , and the structure $(G_0^*, Z_0, \beta )$ is definable, and so $\omega $ -categorical and pseudofinite. Furthermore, it follows from ( $*$ ) that for any linearly independent $g_1,g_2\in G_0^*$ and $h_1,h_2\in Z_0$ , there is $k\in G_0^*$ with $\beta (g_i,k)=h_i$ for $i=1,2$ . This however is impossible by Lemma 2.6.

Remark 2.12. Let p be an odd prime and $m=p^u$ for some $u\geq 1$ . It is shown at the end of Section 3 of [Reference Apps2] that any countable group satisfying the model companion of the theory of class 2 groups of exponent m is a comprehensive group with respect to $\mathcal {N}_2(p^u,p^u/Z)$ , where $Z=(C_{p^u})^\omega $ . Since such Z contains an infinite elementary abelian p-group, the model companion is not pseudofinite.

As mentioned in the introduction, for any odd prime p and $c<p$ , Maier [Reference Maier31] constructs an $\omega $ -categorical model companion of the class of exponent p groups of nilpotency class at most c. The construction is described in detail in [Reference d’Elbée, Müller, Ramsey and Siniora17], via an intricate amalgamation of “Lazard” Lie algebras which yields additional information on the model theory of the groups. The countable model of the model companion is denoted $\mathbf {G}_{c,p}$ . It turns out (personal communication of Christian d’Elbée) that if $c\geq 4$ then $\mathbf {G}_{c,p}$ interprets $\mathbf {G}_{2,p}$ , which is the countable model of $T_{{\mathop{\mathrm {nil2}}},p}$ ; the argument provided by d’Elbée does not handle the case $c=3$ . In particular, by Corollary 2.8, we have

Proposition 2.13. Let p be an odd prime and $3<c<p$ . Then $\mathbf {G}_{c,p}$ is not pseudofinite.

We have not tried systematically to show that all known groups of this flavour (i.e., $\omega $ -categorical model companions, Fraïssé limits in various languages) satisfy Conjecture 1.1. In particular, we only work with odd primes, so for example do not consider the QE nilpotent class 2 groups of exponent 4 mentioned in the introduction.

We finish this section with a brief discussion of which FAF groups are pseudofinite.

Examples 2.14. First, by [Reference Baur, Cherlin and Macintyre9, Theorem 63], every $\omega $ -categorical abelian-by-finite group has $\omega $ -stable theory, and hence is smoothly approximable (see e.g., [Reference Cherlin, Harrington and Lachlan13, Corollary 7.4]) and so pseudofinite. As noted in Section 1, extraspecial p-groups of odd exponent p are pseudofinite, whereas by Theorem 2.11 for finite $n\geq 2$ Baudisch’s groups $D(n)$ are not; the groups in both of these classes are finite-by-abelian. At the other extreme to the groups $D(n)$ , consider (for an odd prime p and any finite $n\geq 1$ ) a vector space V over $\mathbb {F}_{p^n}$ equipped with a non-degenerate symplectic form $\beta : V\times V \to \mathbb {F}_{p^n}$ . Define the group $H(p,n)$ to have universe $V\times \mathbb {F}_{p^n}$ , with group operation $(v_1,x_1)*(v_2,x_2)=(v_1+v_2, x_1+x_2+\beta (v_1,v_2))$ . Then $H(p,n)$ is bi-interpretable with a smoothly approximable structure and so is smoothly approximable and hence pseudofinite (unlike $D(n)$ ). However, like $D(n)$ , $H(p,n)$ is nilpotent class 2 of exponent p with centre elementary abelian of rank n, and is supersimple of SU-rank 1. If $n=1$ then $H(p,n)$ is extraspecial (so is isomorphic to $D(1)$ ).

The groups $H(p,n)$ are a special case of a more general class of $\omega $ -categorical nilpotent class 2 groups discussed by Apps in [Reference Apps2, Section 2]. Namely, given a finite nilpotent class 2 group G, and subgroup K of G with $G'\leq K\leq Z(G)$ , let $G(\omega ;K)$ denote the (restricted) central product of $\aleph _0$ copies of G, amalgamated over K, and for $n\in \mathbb {N}$ with $n>1$ let $G(n;K)$ be the central product of n copies of G amalgamated over K. Apps shows in [Reference Apps2, Theorem A] that $G(\omega ;K)$ is $\omega $ -categorical.

Question 2.15. Is it true that for any $G,K$ as above, the group $G(\omega ,K)$ is pseudofinite and satisfies the limit theory of the groups $G(n,K)$ ? Are all such groups smoothly approximated by the $G(n,K)$ (and hence supersimple of finite rank)?

Observe that if G is a finite non-abelian group, then the restricted direct power $H:=G^\omega $ is not pseudofinite. For define a preorder $x<y$ on H by putting $x<y$ if and only if $C_H(x)>C_H(y)$ . Then $H\models (\forall x\in H\setminus Z(H)) (\exists y\in H\setminus Z(H))(x<y)$ ; indeed, we could choose y to agree with x on its support, and have a non-central element of G in another entry. Such a sentence could not hold in any finite non-abelian group. In fact, such a group H is also not $\omega $ -categorical—see e.g., [Reference Rosenstein34, Theorem 3].

Question 2.16. Does every $\omega $ -categorical FAF group have supersimple theory?

3 Further observations

We begin by noting that the Boolean power construction mentioned in the introduction does not seem to give counterexamples to Conjecture 1.1. Note that in the lemma below, if G is nilpotent of class 2 then so are $B[G]$ and $B^-[G]$ .

Lemma 3.1. Let G be an $\omega $ -categorical non-abelian group and let $B[G]$ or $B^-[G]$ be an $\omega $ -categorical Boolean power of G. Then $B[G]$ (respectively $B^-[G]$ ) has the strict order property so is not pseudofinite.

Proof. We consider the case when B is the countable atomless Boolean algebra, but the other cases (where B has finitely many atoms, or is an $\omega $ -categorical Boolean ring without 1) are similar. Let C be the Cantor set. Then $B[G]$ consists of all continuous maps $C\to G$ with finite support. Let $\{U_i:i\in \omega \}$ be clopen subsets of C, with $U_i\subset U_j$ whenever $i<j$ . Also let $g\in G\setminus Z(G)$ and let $\phi _i:C\to G$ be the map taking value g on $U_i$ and $1$ elsewhere. Then for each i we have $\phi _i\in B[G]$ , and $C_{B[G]}(\phi _i)$ consists of elements $\psi $ of $B[G]$ taking any value on $C\setminus U_i$ and taking values in $C_G(g)$ on $U_i$ . Hence if $i>j$ we have $C_G(\phi _i)<C_G(\phi _j)$ . Thus, the formula $\phi (x,y)$ expressing $C_{B[G]}(x)\leq C_{B[G]}(y)$ defines a preorder with an infinite totally ordered subset. Non-pseudofiniteness now follows from Lemma 2.1.

We also pose the following question, aiming to recover a Boolean power structure for a certain class of nilpotent class 2 groups, mimicking the proof of Theorem A of [Reference Apps3] which stems ultimately from an unpublished result of Philip Hall.

Problem 3.2. Find conditions on a locally finite nilpotent class 2 (perhaps $\omega $ -categorical) group G which guarantee that G is a Boolean power. Suggested conditions are (i) there is no non-trivial characteristic subgroup of G which is properly contained in the derived subgroup $G'$ , and (ii) G has a subgroup of finite index not containing $G'$ . Find conditions which ensure that G is a filtered Boolean power in the sense of [Reference Macintyre and Rosenstein30].

Let $f(n)$ be the number of non-isomorphic groups of order n. It is well-known that $f(n)$ grows fast for prime power n, in the sense that for prime p we have $f(p^m)\geq p^{\frac {2}{27}m^2(m-6)}$ (see [Reference Higman22]). Given this ubiquity of finite p-groups, we expect there to be many $\omega $ -categorical class 2 p-groups not of the types described above. Note, though, that the very flexible “Mekler construction” (see [Reference Mekler32]), though it gives examples of nilpotent class 2 exponent p pseudofinite groups (see [Reference Macpherson and Tent29]), does not preserve $\omega $ -categoricity so is not likely to give new examples.

The deep theory in [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14] yields the following consequence.

Proposition 3.3. Suppose that $d\in \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {C}$ is a family of finite groups such that, for all $G\in \mathcal {C}$ , the group ${{\mathrm {Aut}}}(G)$ has at most d orbits on $G^4$ . Then the following hold.

  1. (i) There is $e\in \mathbb {N}$ such that each $G\in \mathcal {C}$ has a normal subgroup N of index at most e, with $N'\leq Z(N)$ and $|N'|\leq e$ .

  2. (ii) Any ultraproduct of members of $\mathcal {C}$ is FAF with $\omega $ -categorical theory.

Proof.

  1. (i) It follows from the structure theory developed in [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14] (see e.g., Theorem 6) that the (sufficiently large) members of $\mathcal {C}$ fall into finitely many families $\mathcal {C}_i$ each associated with an $\omega $ -categorical countably infinite Lie coordinatizable group $G_i$ whose theory is the collection of sentences which hold in all but finitely many groups in $\mathcal {C}_i$ . In particular, by [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14, Theorem 7] such a group is modular with the type amalgamation property and of finite rank (the rank used in [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14] can be taken after the fact to be SU-rank). By [Reference Cherlin and Hrushovski14, Proposition 6.2.4] the group $G_i$ is FAF, and the result follows.

  2. (ii) This is immediate from (i).

Thus, for any construction of an $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite not virtually finite-by-abelian group, the $\omega $ -categoricity will not arise directly from richness of the automorphism groups of a class of finite groups. Such a construction will have to involve some model-theoretic argument to obtain $\omega $ -categoricity (e.g., back-and-forth, Fraïssé amalgamation, or axiomatizing an appropriate class). We cannot envisage such a construction which eludes the argument against pseudofiniteness given in Section 2.

Remark 3.4. We list the $\omega $ -categorical nilpotent groups of which we are aware and for which we have not addressed their pseudofiniteness. First, we have not considered the class 2 groups of exponent 4 with quantifier elimination constructed in [Reference Saracino and Wood36], or indeed the Apps comprehensive groups of Theorem 2.10 with $p=2$ , but would expect similar methods to rule out pseudofiniteness. Likewise, as noted before Proposition 2.13, we do not know if Maier’s group $\mathbf {G}_{3,p}$ is pseudofinite. In the other direction, we do not know if the finite-by-abelian groups $G(\omega ,K)$ considered in Question 2.15 are always pseudofinite.

Finally, we note that the structure theory for $\omega $ -categorical rings (not necessarily commutative) has close parallels to that of $\omega $ -categorical groups. Thus, we have the following conjecture and proposition. Recall that a ring R is nilpotent (of class r) if $x_1\ldots x_r=0$ for any $x_1,\ldots ,x_r\in R$ . We say R is null if $xy=0$ for any $x,y\in R$ .

Conjecture 3.5. If R be an $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite ring, then R has a definable 2-sided ideal I of finite index which is finite-by-null, i.e., I has a finite 2-sided ideal J such that $I/J$ is null.

We remark that every supersimple $\omega $ -categorical ring is in this sense finite-by-null-by-finite (see [Reference Krupinski and Wagner27, Theorem 3.4], and its proof for the definability assertion).

Proposition 3.6. Let R be an $\omega $ -categorical pseudofinite ring. Then R has a definable nilpotent ideal of finite index.

Proof. By [Reference Krupinski26, Theorem 3.1], any $\omega $ -categorical ring whose theory does not have the strict order property has a definable nilpotent ideal of finite index (the definability clause comes from the proof in [Reference Krupinski26], using the corresponding definability in Corollary 2.2). The result now follows from Lemma 2.1.

Acknowledgments

We warmly thank Bettina Eick for very helpful discussions related to the proof of Corollary 2.5, and Laurent Bartholdi, for allowing us to include the proof of Lemma 2.4 which he provided. We also thank Christian d’Elbée for several very helpful discussions.

Funding

The research of the second author was funded through the Cluster of Excellence by the German Research Foundation (DFG) under Germany’s Excellence Strategy EXC 2044–390685587, Mathematics Münster: Dynamics–Geometry–Structure and by CRC 1442 Geometry: Deformations and Rigidity.

References

REFERENCES

Apps, A.B., Boolean powers of groups . Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, vol. 91 (1982), pp. 375395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Apps, A.B., On ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical class two groups . Journal of Algebra, vol. 82 (1983), no. 2, pp. 516538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Apps, A.B., On the structure of ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical groups . Journal of Algebra, vol. 81 (1983), no. 2, pp. 320339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baudisch, A., Closures in ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical bilinear maps . Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 65 (2000), no. 2, pp. 914922.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baudisch, A., A Fraïssé limit of nilpotent groups of finite exponent . Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 33 (2001), no. 5, pp. 513519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baudisch, A., More Fraïssé limits of nilpotent groups of finite exponent . Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 36 (2004), no. 5, pp. 613622.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baudisch, A., Free amalgamation and automorphism groups . Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 81 (2016), no. 3, pp. 936947.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baudisch, A., Neostability-properties of Fraïssé limits of 2-nilpotent groups of exponent $p>2$ . Archive for Mathematical Logic, vol. 55 (2016), no. 3-4, pp. 397403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baur, W., Cherlin, G., and Macintyre, A.J., ‘Totally categorical groups and rings ’. Journal of Algebra, vol. 57 (1979), pp. 407440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cherlin, G., Combinatorial problems connected with finite homogeneity , Contemporary Mathematics 131 (Part 3), American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1992, pp. 330.Google Scholar
Cherlin, G., Two problems on homogeneous structures, revisited , Contemporary Mathematics 558, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2011, pp. 319415.Google Scholar
Cherlin, G., and Felgner, U., Quantifier eliminable groups, Logic Colloquium ’80 (Prague, 1980) , Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 108, North-Holland, Amsterdam-New York, 1982, pp. 6981.Google Scholar
Cherlin, G., Harrington, L., and Lachlan, A.H. ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical, ${\aleph}_0$ -stable structures . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 28 (1985), no. 2, pp. 103135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cherlin, G., and Hrushovski, E., Finite structures with few types, Annals of Mathematics Studies, no. 152, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2003.Google Scholar
Cherlin, G., Saracino, D., and Wood, C., On homogeneous nilpotent groups and rings . Proceedings of American Mathematical Society, vol. 119 (1993), no. 4, pp. 12891306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobrowolski, J., and Wagner, F.O., On $\omega$ -categorical groups and rings of finite burden . Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 236 (2020), no. 2, pp. 801839.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
d’Elbée, C., Müller, I., Ramsey, N., and Siniora, D., ‘Model-theoretic properties of nilpotent groups and Lie algebras’, Journal of Algebra, vol. 662 (2025), 640701.Google Scholar
Evans, D., and Wagner, F., Supersimple $\omega$ -categorical groups and theories . Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 65 (2000), no. 2, pp. 767776.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Felgner, U., On ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical extra-special $p$ -groups . Logique et Analyse. Nouvelle Serie, vol. 18 (1975), no. 71-72, pp. 407428.Google Scholar
Felgner, U. ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical stable groups . Mathematische Zeitschrift, vol. 160 (1978), no. 1, pp. 2749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henson, W., Countable homogeneous relational structures and ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical theories . Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 37 (1972), pp. 494500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Higman, G., Enumerating $p$ -groups. I: inequalities . Proceedings of London Mathematical Society (3), vol. 10 (1960), pp. 2430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Higman, G., Amalgams of $p$ -groups . Journal of Algebra, vol. 1 (1964), pp. 301305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kantor, W.M., Liebeck, M.W., and Macpherson, H.D. ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical structures smoothly approximated by finite substructures . Proceedings of London Mathematical Society (3), vol. 59 (1989), pp. 439463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kruckman, A., Disjoint $n$ -amalgamation and pseudofinite countably categorical theories . Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 60 (2019), no. 1, pp. 139160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krupinski, K., On relationships between algebraic properties of groups and rings in some model-theoretic contexts . Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 76 (2011) no. 4, pp. 14031417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krupinski, K., and Wagner, F., ‘Small profinite groups and rings ’. Journal of Algebra, vol. 306 (2006), pp. 494506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macpherson, H.D., Absolutely ubiquitous structures and  ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical groups . Quarterly Journal of Mathematics, vol. 39 (1988), pp. 483500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macpherson, H.D., and Tent, K., Stable pseudofinite groups . Journal of Algebra, vol. 312 (2007), pp. 550561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macintyre, A.J., and Rosenstein, J.G. ${\aleph}_0$ -categoricity for rings without nilpotent elements and for boolean structures . Journal of Algebra, vol. 43 (1976), pp. 129154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maier, B.J., On nilpotent groups of exponent $p$ . Journal of Algebra, vol. 127 (1989), pp. 279289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mekler, A.H., Stability of nilpotent groups of class 2 and prime exponent . Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 46 (1981), no. 4, pp. 781788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milliet, C., Definable envelopes in groups having a simple theory . Journal of Algebra, vol.492 (2017), pp. 298323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenstein, J.G. ${\aleph}_0$ -categoricity of groups . Journal of Algebra, vol. 25 (1973), pp. 435467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saracino, D., and Wood, C., Periodic existentially closed nilpotent groups . Journal of Algebra, vol. 58 (1979), pp. 189207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saracino, D., and Wood, C., QE nil- $2$ groups of exponent $4$ . Journal of Algebra, vol. 76 (1982), no. 2, pp. 337352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saracino, D., Amalgamation bases for nil-2 groups . Algebra Universalis, vol. 16 (1983) no.1, pp. 4762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., and Spencer, J., Zero-one laws for sparse random graphs . Journal of American Mathematical Society, vol. 1 (1988) no. 1, pp. 97115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, J. S., The algebraic structure of  ${\aleph}_0$ -categorical groups , Groups St. Andrews 1981 (Campbell, C.M. and Robertson, E.F., editors), London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes 71, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge-New York, 1982, pp. 345358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar