Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T19:00:54.056Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Structuring unleashed expression: Developmental foundations of human communication

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 February 2023

Wiktor Rorot
Affiliation:
Human Interactivity and Language Lab, Faculty of Psychology, University of Warsaw, 00-183 Warszawa, Poland. [email protected]; [email protected] https://wiktor.rorot.pl; https://hill.psych.uw.edu.pl
Katarzyna Skowrońska
Affiliation:
Human Interactivity and Language Lab, Faculty of Psychology, University of Warsaw, 00-183 Warszawa, Poland. [email protected]; [email protected] https://wiktor.rorot.pl; https://hill.psych.uw.edu.pl
Ewa Nagórska
Affiliation:
Human Interactivity and Language Lab, Faculty of Psychology, University of Warsaw, 00-183 Warszawa, Poland. [email protected]; [email protected] https://wiktor.rorot.pl; https://hill.psych.uw.edu.pl
Konrad Zieliński
Affiliation:
Human Interactivity and Language Lab, Faculty of Psychology, University of Warsaw, 00-183 Warszawa, Poland. [email protected]; [email protected] https://wiktor.rorot.pl; https://hill.psych.uw.edu.pl
Julian Zubek
Affiliation:
Human Interactivity and Language Lab, Faculty of Psychology, University of Warsaw, 00-183 Warszawa, Poland. [email protected]; [email protected] https://wiktor.rorot.pl; https://hill.psych.uw.edu.pl
Joanna Rączaszek-Leonardi
Affiliation:
Human Interactivity and Language Lab, Faculty of Psychology, University of Warsaw, 00-183 Warszawa, Poland. [email protected]; [email protected] https://wiktor.rorot.pl; https://hill.psych.uw.edu.pl

Abstract

The target article highlights the sources of open-endedness of human communication. However, the authors' perspective does not account for the structure of particular communication systems. To this end, we extend the authors' perspective, in the spirit of evolutionary extended synthesis, with a detailed account of the sources of constraints imposed upon expression in the course of child development.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Heintz & Scott-Phillips strongly argue that the cognitive capacities required for unleashed communication are adaptations to a “partner choice” social ecology. This emphasis on adaptation and ecology puts them roughly within the purview of modern evolutionary synthesis (Huxley, Reference Huxley2010). However, arguments against both the adaptationist paradigm and the program of modern synthesis have been accruing systematically for a long time (e.g., Gould & Lewontin, Reference Gould and Lewontin1979; Sober, Reference Sober1982; Walsh & Huneman, Reference Walsh, Huneman, Huneman and Walsh2017) and resulted in several alternative proposals, out of which the extended evolutionary synthesis is one of the most prolific (Laland et al., Reference Laland, Uller, Feldman, Sterelny, Müller, Moczek and Odling-Smee2015; Pigliucci & Müller, Reference Pigliucci and Müller2010). Evolutionary extended synthesis positions at its center the study of development (developmental bias and plasticity) and niche construction. These are precisely the elements that we argue that the authors overlooked in their proposal, and which can provide important details not only about how expression becomes “unleashed,” but also how it can become highly structured to enable the emergence of symbolic communication systems, such as language.

The target article draws the continuity between different forms of human expression, moving the search for foundations of the unleashed communication, that is, the generativity of communication systems, outside the properties of language itself. This opens up new avenues for asking more adequate questions about systems of communication. Here we want to ask, what makes language in particular a suitable tool for such an open-ended expression. While various means of human expression – art, dance, or improvised gestures – can convey meaning, language seems to be the only system effectively allowing for communication both unlimited and precise. We argue that the authors' framework cannot account for the emergence of the structure of unleashed communication visible in language. Here we focus on the inclusion of a crucial factor: External sources of linguistic structure present in development that go beyond the authors' focus on social ecology on an evolutionary scale.

Human infants are born into a social world. Interactions with caretakers are the primary source of experiences for a newborn, as well as the context for their agency. These include language utterances of particular structure, crucially – closely tied to action (Rączaszek-Leonardi, Nomikou, Rohlfing, & Deacon, Reference Rączaszek-Leonardi, Nomikou, Rohlfing and Deacon2018). In fact, children learn basic linguistic structures much earlier than they are able to use them for communication in the same way as adults do (Bruner, Reference Bruner and Forgas1985). Importantly, the caretakers' actions themselves also often exhibit a communicative structure. As evidenced in research on early semantic development, infants' behaviors, such as reaching and pointing, are treated as ostensive by caregivers to build sensible “events” or “narrations” around them. This way, action first, children learn about possibilities of expression that can be effective in social situations. “Events” rather than being entirely created on the fly are culturally sanctioned routines, adapted to a situation (Bates, Camaioni, & Volterra, Reference Bates, Camaioni and Volterra1975). It is within such interactions that experiences of being expressive and effects of this expression on partners appear and are progressively shaped toward communicative and linguistic modes. Yet the child may be perfectly unaware of this and treat pointing gestures just as a reliable way of getting what they want. It is only when pointing becomes unreliable and produces different results depending on the context (most importantly, receiver's attention and knowledge; Liszkowski, Carpenter, Henning, Striano, & Tomasello, Reference Liszkowski, Carpenter, Henning, Striano and Tomasello2004) that the child starts to become aware of the intricacies of communication. Thus two kinds of cultural enactments scaffold the developmental progression: interactive routines leading to various expressions being integrated for purposive co-action (Rączaszek-Leonardi, Nomikou, & Rohlfing, Reference Rączaszek-Leonardi, Nomikou and Rohlfing2013; Rossmanith, Costall, Reichelt, López, & Reddy, Reference Rossmanith, Costall, Reichelt, López and Reddy2014) and using a highly structured language by a parent, in concert with the routines, which scaffolds skillful linguistic participation. In both cases, it is shareable structures, historically shaped by culture, that are central for developmental language emergence in interaction (Bruner, Reference Bruner1983).

Finally, these public, physical structures are crucially replicable. The authors are certainly correct in highlighting that one of the purposes of conventionalization is to turn attention to the communicative intention of a particular action (target article, sect. 8.5, para. 3). As importantly, however, conventionalization ensures the replicability of expressions and serves as one of the key sources of constraints on unleashed expression. Over the course of development, via overimitation (target article, sect. 7, para. 8) and co-action, utterances (spoken or signed) are nudged toward these culturally sanctioned forms stabilizing their functions, which make up a language. In turn, all this depends on the physical, public, and shareable nature of the signs that can be abstracted away from a particular situation in which they are produced and repeated under nearly any circumstances.

A fully unleashed expression would prevent successful message transmission because of the multiplicity of possible meanings. Introducing structure and constraints that ensure replicability, a “leashing” of expression of sorts, restricts informative intentions of communicators that cannot be “about anything at all” (target article, sect. 5, para. 2). Open-endedness of some elements of a communication system needs to become suspended, so that they are produced and interpreted as natural signs (Bar-On, Reference Bar-On2021, p. 15), for the system to remain unleashed. This is possible via the developmental pressures described above. The evolutionary perspective of the authors needs a complementary account of the developmental and environmental structures that enable and stabilize communicative abilities. While the roots of expressive communication could be observed in the open-ended improvised expressions, identifying the key processes from other timescales at the level of individual and language development allow for an adequate, interaction-specific balance of “leashed” and “unleashed” parts of communication. We argue that this contribution may serve as a valuable extension for the proposed framework.

The processes described above indicate that the focus on the ecological interactions and on the evolutionary timescale may lead to averaging out crucial processes that accompany the unleashing of expression. On the other hand, taking care to analyze the developmental processes substantiates the authors' claims about the appearance of relevant cognitive capacities at “reliable and predictable stages of ontogeny” (target article, sect. 6, para. 11) and highlights that this results from a network of dynamic processes supported by other individuals and the cognitive niche that humans have constructed in order to master language use.

Acknowledgment

The authors wish to thank Borys Jastrzębski for discussion of the target article.

Financial support

The work on this commentary has been funded by the NCN Opus 15 Grant 2018/29/B/HS1/00884 to Joanna Rączaszek-Leonardi.

Conflict of interest

None.

References

Bar-On, D. (2021). How to do things with nonwords: Pragmatics, biosemantics, and origins of language in animal communication. Biology & Philosophy, 36(6), 50. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-021-09824-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bates, E., Camaioni, L., & Volterra, V. (1975). The acquisition of performatives prior to speech. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 21, 205226.Google Scholar
Bruner, J. (1983). Child's talk: Learning to use language. Norton.Google Scholar
Bruner, J. (1985). The role of interaction formats in language acquisition. In Forgas, J. P. (Ed.), Language and social situations (pp. 3146). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-5074-6_2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B. Biological Sciences, 205(1161), 581598. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.1979.0086Google Scholar
Huxley, J. (2010). Evolution: The modern synthesis. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Laland, K. N., Uller, T., Feldman, M. W., Sterelny, K., Müller, G. B., Moczek, A., … Odling-Smee, J. (2015). The extended evolutionary synthesis: Its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 282(1813), 20151019. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2015.1019Google ScholarPubMed
Liszkowski, U., Carpenter, M., Henning, A., Striano, T., & Tomasello, M. (2004). Twelve-month-olds point to share attention and interest. Developmental Science, 7, 297307.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pigliucci, M., & Müller, G. (Eds.). (2010). Evolution, the extended synthesis. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rączaszek-Leonardi, J., Nomikou, I., & Rohlfing, K. J. (2013). Young children's dialogical actions: The beginnings of purposeful intersubjectivity. IEEE Transactions on Autonomous Mental Development, 5(3), 210221. https://doi.org/10.1109/TAMD.2013.2273258CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rączaszek-Leonardi, J., Nomikou, I., Rohlfing, K. J., & Deacon, T. W. (2018). Language development from an ecological perspective: Ecologically valid ways to abstract symbols. Ecological Psychology, 30(1), 3973. https://doi.org/10.1080/10407413.2017.1410387CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rossmanith, N., Costall, A., Reichelt, A. F., López, B., & Reddy, V. (2014). Jointly structuring triadic spaces of meaning and action: Book sharing from 3 months on. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 122. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01390CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sober, E. R. (1982). The modern synthesis: Its scope and limits. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 314321. https://www.jstor.org/stable/192427Google Scholar
Walsh, D. M., & Huneman, P. (2017). Introduction: Challenging the modern synthesis. In Huneman, P. & Walsh, D. M. (Eds.), Challenging the modern synthesis: Adaptation, development, and inheritance (pp. 134). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199377176.003.0012Google Scholar