Introduction
Recent decades have witnessed unprecedented environmental deterioration, with climate change and extreme weather events, such as floods and droughts, posing significant challenges. The scientific consensus points to mankind as the main culprit, as well as the sole cause capable of moral agency. The unprecedented increase in human population alongside a variety of polluting enterprises – industry, technology, and urban development – harm wilderness areas, contributing to the extinction of biological species and threatening their present and future generations.
Of all human activities, however, warfare has a particularly significant and enduring effect on the natural environment, with militaries generating exceptionally large carbon footprints, both in war and in peacetime.Footnote 1 According to one authority, ‘collectively the world’s militaries are estimated to be the largest single polluter on Earth, accounting for as much as 20 percent of all global environmental degradation’.Footnote 2
Training and preparing for war, as well as fighting and recovering from it, inevitably have negative effects on natural systems. Maintaining, exercising, and mobilizing standing armies contribute to carbon emissions. Military industries cause extensive pollution; warfare disrupts ecosystems, harms wilderness areas, and jeopardizes biodiversity.Footnote 3 As for the instigation of war, conflict over natural resources (scarce or abundant) is a common cause of civil wars; and their conduct, often within biodiversity hotspots, is particularly damaging to the natural environment and its inhabitants.Footnote 4 Moreover, studies indicate that environmental degradation may well increase the incidence of armed conflict, particularly of the non-international variety.Footnote 5
Undeniably, in atypical cases conflicts or their aftermath may have beneficial effects on the environment, such as removing people from an entire area, leaving nature to bloom, and wildlife to roam freely. This is, however, the rare exception that proves the rule.Footnote 6 Overwhelmingly, warfare is very bad for our natural environment, and modern warfare is especially so.
The adverse effects of military activity are evident even before hostilities break out, and often endure in their aftermath. Most notably perhaps, in light of timely concerns, is the potential of environmental harm caused by war to increase worldwide refugee crises and widespread epidemics post bellum (after war), alongside the large-scale economic disruptions that accompany both.Footnote 7 The Spanish influenza pandemic that followed World War I is a case in point. Moreover, as with environmental concerns more generally, some wartime damage will also have multi-generational effects.
Bearing in mind the climate crisis along with the ecological footprint of military enterprises, environmental concerns must now be incorporated into the moral evaluation of violent conflict. To this end, this Element integrates two branches of applied ethics rarely studied in tandem – namely environmental ethics and the ethics of war, as well as law and general moral philosophies – and considers their combined impact on environmental wartime issues. It suggests that considerations arising from environmental ethics should inform contemporary just war theory and its agenda, introducing and addressing the uncharted territory of the environmental ethics of armed conflict.
Several themes are developed in the Element. First, the concept of an environmental morality of war breaks new ground and, as such, ought to build carefully on the wide range of relevant theories in ethics of war, environmental ethics, law, and moral philosophy. International law already contains some prohibitions and restrictions on militaries for protecting nature during armed conflict, supplying the primary building blocks for thinking about environmental obligations in wartime. Ethics is different from law, however, in depth and scope – less technical and unhindered by practical considerations of implementation, international ramifications, and compromises – and should step in to develop the wartime protection of nature.Footnote 8
Beyond military ethics, planetary changes suggest that grave environmental harm may generate a new ‘just cause’ for war, contra existing international law. The relative frequency of civil conflicts and their common location in bio-sensitive regions is a further source of environmental concern.Footnote 9 Finally, ‘environmental terrorism’ is a new and ambiguous label, requiring classification and moral evaluation. Wartime proportionality and sincere intention to protect nature suggest countering ‘environmental aggression’, terroristic or otherwise, via measures short of full-scale conflict, avoiding excessively ruinous consequences not only to humans and other animals but also to their natural surroundings.
Historically, war has always been destructive for the environment. Nevertheless, the issue of protecting nature per se from the deleterious effects of warfare surfaced only in the late twentieth century, due mostly to the unprecedented environmental devastation caused by the Vietnam and Gulf wars.Footnote 10 Since that time, increasing evidence of environmental damage caused by armed conflict has attracted academic attention, much of which remains empirical and dispersed among different disciplines, ranging from political science and international relations to ecology, law, and military history.Footnote 11
In contrast to lawyers and empirical researchers, just war theorists and philosophers of war have yet to step up to the plate. Their voluminous philosophical accounts of the morality of war in recent decades have paid virtually no attention to the ethical issues raised by damage to the natural environment whether before, during, or after armed conflict.Footnote 12 On the whole, the military ethics, or ‘morality of war’, perspective on the environmental damage inflicted by armed forces is glaringly absent, as is any discussion of the environmental causes of war.
Building on the exceptional literature in the field, this Element takes one small step towards remedying the deficiency. The four sections offer initial methods and content in promoting the incorporation of environmental considerations in contemporary scholarship on the morality of war. This is an absolute necessity for any twenty-first-century ethics of war and its regulations, with implications for both jus ad bellum (the legitimacy of engaging in war) and jus in bello (just conduct in war), as well as any future discussion of jus para bellum (the just preparation for war, in which, for example, military training might damage the environment) and jus post bellum (justice after war).Footnote 13
Section 1 lays the groundwork for some of the overarching proposals expressed throughout the Element. I begin by briefly surveying the existing philosophical literature on environmental justice in wartime (environmental jus in bello). Combining environmental ethics with the ethics of war, the Element asks how the environmental crisis should challenge and change the rules of engagement in war, stressing the need for ethical guidelines in this field. What would a ‘greener’ ethics of war look like?
My point of departure is the International Law of Armed Conflict (ILOAC), identifying the most directly relevant existing environmental regulations in wartime applicable to international armed conflict. Unlike moral philosophers, lawyers have of necessity already paid notable normative attention to environmental regulation in wartime, ‘jump-starting’ moral philosophy, as it were. Humanitarian law, legal commentary, academic analysis, and critique of existing environmental regulations in armed conflict should supply moral philosophers with the initial material that stimulates further elaboration. Perhaps counter-intuitively, I argue that environmental protection in war is an issue in which ethics must take its cue from the law rather than vice versa.Footnote 14
Beyond law, a good place to begin a new moral inquiry is the point of convergence of the various philosophies and world-views that pertain to this issue. This principal suggestion, as developed in Section 1, does not look to the law as a mechanism for settling disagreements, and is distinct from compromise between opposing world-views. Instead, it suggests something like an ‘overlapping consensus’, a moment of agreement (as opposed to compromise) between vastly different perspectives.Footnote 15
Thinking comprehensively about environmental protection in wartime requires consideration of contesting viewpoints within environmental ethics (human versus non-human perspectives), various moral philosophies, and competing just war traditions. When these very different roads all lead to the same moral conclusion, Section 1 suggests that this conclusion is most likely to be correct. Attaining mutual moral ground also serves to prevent extremism or unrealistic idealism in any one perspective, advancing practical ethics.
Finally, with these foundations in hand, the section raises and critiques the proposal to grant nature civilian status in wartime. Rejecting as untenable the extreme attribution of absolute non-combatant immunity for the non-human world, it supports a more moderate proposal to weigh harm to the natural environment on the cost side of wartime proportionality calculations, beyond damage to purely human resources and surroundings.Footnote 16 This would mean that foreseeably excessive harm to nature might place the legitimacy of an attack into question. This proposal is not far from emerging international norms, particularly international criminal law, and is, arguably, in keeping with overlapping consensus.Footnote 17
While the wartime status of nature and environmental wartime regulation during armed conflict (environmental jus in bello) have been addressed only rarely by just war theorists and moral philosophers, the environmental conditions under which states may legitimately resort to war or armed force (environmental jus ad bellum) have hardly been tackled at all. Moreover, because the law focuses invariably on rules mitigating the conduct of hostilities rather than on objective justice of cause, environmental jus ad bellum has been explored even less extensively than environmental jus in bello, in law as well as morality.
Can environmental harm trigger a new justification for war? What would be a proportionate response to ‘environmental aggression’? Section 2 takes on these emerging challenges. Setting out with the presumption against the use of force and its exceptions, this section considers whether environmental harm can generate a new casus belli, a just cause or occasion for war, and what might be a proportionate response to aggressive or negligent harm to nature. Force is clearly justified against military attacks. Where environmental harm is not caused by military aggression, Section 2 argues, proportionality points towards counter-measures short of war. Responding in ways that minimize harm to nature also helps demonstrate a ‘right intention’ to combat environmental wrongs.
Section 3 suggests focusing any new ‘environmental ethics of war’ initially on Non-International Armed Conflict (NIAC), which has mostly been neglected by the just war tradition in all its aspects. This neglect overlaps with just war theory’s neglect of the environment. Crucially, for our purposes, regions prone to civil conflict often contain the greatest biodiversity. Moreover, NIAC has also been the most common type of warfare since World War II. Consequently, fruitful inquiry into the new environmental ethics of war requires not only understanding the links between war and the natural environment but also paying special attention to the contexts and locations in which the majority of conflicts occur.
As in the previous sections, in Section 3 the law is both lacking and at the same time our best shot. Article 3 common to the Geneva Conventions (1949) and Additional Protocol II to the Geneva Conventions (1977) apply minimal humanitarian provisions to NIAC.Footnote 18 Notwithstanding, lawyers note that most laws of armed conflict (LOAC) do not apply to NIAC; and when it comes to the environment, restrictions are virtually non-existent.Footnote 19 This is particularly troublesome, as noted, in view of the relative frequency of internal conflicts as well as their prevalence in biodiversity hotspots.Footnote 20 Nonetheless, Section 3 re-emphasizes that a new ethical aspect of armed conflict – in this case the virtually non-existent environmental regulation of NIAC – is best built on pre-existing legal understandings, even if these are not, strictly speaking, directly applicable to NIAC from a LOAC perspective.
Morally, Section 3 argues for the existence of special obligations on the part of both governments and rebels in all civil conflicts – fiduciary duties of care – towards the populations whom they purport to represent and propose to govern, including their natural surroundings. From a non-cosmopolitan perspective, both insurgents and soldiers have special obligations stemming from national affiliations and partiality towards fellow citizens and their homeland terrain. Finally, universal obligations require everyone to pay special attention to biodiversity conservation in armed conflict, particularly in biologically rich regions. The reality of civil conflict is, of course, very different.
Last, Section 4 examines the relatively new label ‘environmental terrorism’. In keeping with the theme of this Element, this conceptual analysis combines theoretical insights from both terrorism scholarship and environmental politics and ethics. Arson attacks launched from Gaza to Israel, burning fields and forests (2018–23), present the primary contemporary example; the section also contains some references to the October 7 massacre that followed. Relatedly, terrorism usually denotes the murder of civilians. Notwithstanding, I argue that the severity of attacks against the natural environment should not be underestimated, and may sometimes go far enough towards threatening non-combatants to constitute bona fide terrorism.
Completing and complementing the discussion on environmental aggression in Section 2, this final section considers appropriate responses to direct and intentional attacks on the non-human world. Even in the face of outright armed aggression against the natural environment, Section 4 concludes that proportionality prescribes a first resort to softer tactics, such as economic sanctions, followed by limited force short of war – jus ad vim – against primary culprits and their infrastructure, reserving full-scale armed conflict to combat graver invasions and assaults on human life and limb.
One final preliminary note on scope and range: this is a very short introductory work that throws a wide and global net in both its topic and its content. The cases addressed in this Element range all the way from civil wars in Africa to fires in the Amazon rainforest and incendiary kites and balloons sent from the Gaza Strip to southern Israel. In a century of great environmental concern and urgency, with global degradation and climate change right around the corner, this Element raises some of the most pressing practical issues of ethics in our times.
1 Protecting the Natural Environment during Armed Conflict: Environmental Jus in Bello
Warfare is among the greatest threats to natural systems, nearly always involving environmental destruction alongside human carnage.Footnote 21 Despite this, relatively little attention has been focused on environmental wartime issues either by advocates of the traditional ethics of war – ‘just war theory’ – or by contemporary moral philosophers.
However, there is a veritable gold mine of legal literature on environmental regulation during armed conflict and its aftermath. ‘International law has not been silent on the environmental effects of military activity’,Footnote 22 and neither have legal scholars.Footnote 23 In contrast to the litany of legal sources on emerging environmental standards in international law of armed conflict, the environmental ethics of war is extremely limited, with extraordinary exceptions reviewed in Subsection 1.2. In the sphere of wartime environmental protection, the law appears to have preceded moral scholarship and may serve to advance it.
1.1 Environmental Laws of War
The most directly relevant environmental restrictions in wartime, applicable to international armed conflicts, appear in the following legal documents, all of which remain primarily human-centred and utilitarian in their perspective.
The 1959 Antarctic Treaty bans military tests and nuclear activity in the region, partly for ecological reasons.Footnote 24
The 1977 Environmental Modification Techniques Convention (ENMOD) bars using the environment itself (i.e., changing or manipulating natural processes) as a weapon.Footnote 25
Protocol I, Addition to the Geneva Convention (GPI) 1977 – Article 35(3), proscribes ‘methods and means of warfare intended or expected to cause widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the natural environment’. Article 55(1) repeats this and adds a further prohibition against damage to the natural environment that ‘prejudice[s] the health or survival of the [human] population’.Footnote 26
1980 Protocol III to the UN Convention, Article 2(4), prohibits targeting forests and other plant cover with incendiary weapons, except when such natural elements are used to hide or camouflage combatants or are themselves otherwise military targets.Footnote 27
Finally, the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, following the language of Protocol I, brands as a war crime: ‘widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the natural environment which would be clearly excessive in relation to the direct overall military advantage anticipated’.Footnote 28
Environmental legal protections also have multifarious sources and modes of application. International Environmental Law (IEL), such as the aforementioned 1959 Antarctic Treaty (and the 1982 UN Law of the Sea Convention),Footnote 29 offers direct protection to the environment, as does International Humanitarian Law (IHL) in Article 35(3) and Article 55(1) of Additional Protocol I. In addition, IHL offers indirect protection to the natural environment as in Protocol I, Article 54(2), whereby ‘it is prohibited to attack, destroy, remove or render useless objects indispensable to the survival of the civilian population, such as foodstuffs, agricultural areas for the production of foodstuffs, crops, livestock, drinking water installations and supplies and irrigation works, for the specific purpose of denying them for their sustenance value to the civilian population’.Footnote 30 International Criminal Law (ICL) – Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the 1998 Rome Statute – makes various kinds of damage to, and destruction of, the natural environment a war crime.
In their 2000 article ‘Protecting the Natural Environment in Wartime: Ethical Considerations from the Just War Tradition’, one of the few ethical treatments of the subject, Gregory Reichberg and Henrik Syse point out that environmental protections in international law enjoy nothing like the absolute status that is attached to civilian immunity or the prohibition on torture, and (Protocol I and ENMOD notwithstanding) are couched largely in terms of necessity and proportionality.Footnote 31
It is also noteworthy that the standard of the Rome Statute is manifestly weaker than that required in Additional Protocol I. In order to be prosecutable as a war crime, damage to the natural environment has to be not only ‘widespread, long-term, and severe’ but also ‘clearly excessive in relation to the direct overall military advantage anticipated’.Footnote 32 This is a clear and typical example of environmental interdictions falling back on proportionality.Footnote 33 Nevertheless, as David Luban points out more generally, the discrepancies between Protocol I and the Rome Statute should not be read as lowering the standard of rightful conduct required of military organizations under the laws of war. Instead, they represent the difference between rightful conduct and a criminal offence: ‘the drafters apparently thought that fairness to the accused requires a less stringent standard. It follows, however, that the Rome Statute’s standard should not be taken to represent the standard of rightful conduct.’Footnote 34
Furthermore, principles and provisions of the law of war that do not specifically refer to the ‘environment’, such as the aforementioned necessity and proportionality requirements as well as peacetime environmental law, may also add to its protection.Footnote 35 Legal protection afforded to ‘cultural property’ and ‘World Heritage Sites’ might contribute towards safeguarding the environment in specific areas.Footnote 36 Conventions such as the aforementioned 1982 UN Law of the Sea Convention, obliging states to protect and preserve the marine environment (Article 192) and to prevent and reduce its pollution (Article 194), are (arguably) applicable to military commanders at sea.Footnote 37 Finally, leading militaries and international organizations now pay at least cursory attention to environmental issues in their handbooks and directives.Footnote 38
Law is by no means an unusual starting point for ethical analysis of war. Current scholarship on the ethics of war is, however, deeply philosophical, largely concerned with the underlying principles of morality rather than with concrete practicable rules. Notwithstanding, the just war tradition has always been intertwined with legal thinking (‘natural law’) and the subsequent emergence of international laws of war.Footnote 39 Contemporary environmental concerns should be no exception.
Moreover, where law imposes normative regulation in the face of practical necessity before deep moral reflection has developed, ‘law is a school of moral philosophy’.Footnote 40 Discussing civilian immunity, Jeremy Waldron makes this point:
law often colonizes an area of normative inquiry first, before serious moral inquiry, as we know it begins. Often, we learn how to moralize by learning how to ask and answer legalistic questions: I strongly believe that law is a school of moral philosophy. Historically, this has been particularly true of the laws and customs of armed conflict.Footnote 41
Referring to the law as a guide to ethics is especially noteworthy in the case of wartime environmental protection because law and legal experts have already paid systematic attention to this issue, whereas moral philosophers, for the most part, have not. Commentary and critique of environmental regulations in armed conflict should supply philosophers with normative food for thought, but they also leave much work to do. Ethics is wider and more inclusive than law, especially international law, which often represents a minimal compromise between states rather than deep moral reflections about war.Footnote 42 Moreover, law and lawyers concentrate on jus in bello, the rules of engagement in international armed conflict, discussed in this section. They have less to say about further environmental aspects of war addressed in the remainder of the Element. Law has a necessary practical focus. Considerations of technicalities and implementation may restrain and limit legal sources, in contrast with deep moral theory or comprehensive philosophical evaluation of environmental ethics in wartime that is sorely lacking.Footnote 43 In the case in hand, as we have seen, law is necessarily and exclusively human centred, and its environmental provisions are non-absolute;Footnote 44 environmental ethics incorporates other perspectives as well. Here it is clear that ethical inquiry should deepen, explain, and widen the scope of environmental wartime issues raised in the surrounding legal literature.Footnote 45
1.2 Environmental Military Ethics
Falling far behind their legal counterparts, moral philosophers have paid scant attention to environmental ramifications of military activity, rendering ‘environmental considerations … peripheral in analyses of the ethics of war’.Footnote 46 Notable philosophical exceptions reviewed here are few and far between, and their authors may well be regarded as pioneers in their field. Some of these contributions adopt a highly specific approach, while others offer a more general ethical analysis. Merrit Drucker (Reference Drucker1989) discusses a military commander’s professional responsibility for the natural environment in both peacetime and wartime, arguing from environmental ethics that military necessity cannot justify any extent of environmental devastation. Most interestingly, Drucker aspires to attribute non-combatant status to the environment itself and its non-human natural inhabitants. Focusing on environmental protection, such as immunity for nature in wartime, however, risks losing sight of humanitarian concern for the lives of soldiers and civilians.Footnote 47
Drawing on Drucker’s analysis, Reichberg and Syse (Reference Reichberg and Syse2000) are the first contemporary just war theorists to explicitly suggest incorporating environmental considerations in the moral assessment of war and its conduct. Focusing specifically on Thomas Aquinas’s influential formulation of the just war requirements and natural law, along with his conception of the relationship between humanity and nature in terms of responsibility and stewardship, the authors suggest that the just war tradition ‘provides an ethical vocabulary for assessing the impact of war on our natural environment’.Footnote 48
Combining some of these previous insights, Mark Woods (Reference Woods, Brough, Lango and van der Linden2007) recommends introducing environmental ethics into the just war tradition and considers how this might be done.Footnote 49 Like Drucker, Woods denies that military necessity always trumps environmental considerations and poses a vital practical ethics question: to what extent, if any, can we require armies and military commanders to put their mission and men at risk in order to avoid environmental harm?Footnote 50 Rejecting the traditionally stark distinction between jus ad bellum–jus in bello and the independence of the rules of conduct from just cause, Woods’s environmental standards suggest that a war likely to involve significant attacks on nature would be ipso facto unjust, regardless of cause, and would necessarily fail ad bellum criteria such as proportionality and competent authority.Footnote 51
Next, Marcus Hedahl, Scott Clark, and Michael Beggins (Reference Gross and Meisels2017), of the US Navy, argue that environmental change must affect the theoretical framework of the just war tradition at its very core, explicating this at both its ad bellum and in bello levels, as well as justice prior to and post bellum.Footnote 52 (I return to their discussion of jus ad bellum in Subsection 1.3.) Meanwhile, Laurie Johnston (Reference Johnston, Winright and Johnston2015) offers a religious account, based on the Christian virtues of humility and solidarity.Footnote 53
Reflecting on the classics, Adrien Estève (Reference Estève2020) cites consequentialist–utilitarian arguments within the just war tradition for protecting the natural environment in times of war, complementing them with reasoning from virtue ethics.Footnote 54 Most recently, Josh Milburn and Sara Van Goozen (Reference Milburn and Van Goozen2021, Reference Milburn and Van Goozen2023) focus exclusively on animal rights, partly in connection with the wartime requirements of necessity and proportionality, arguing plausibly that we ought to take into account wartime harm to individual animals when assessing the justice of military action.Footnote 55
This invaluable collection of original analyses constitutes the latest ethical–philosophical discussion about war and the environment, leaving room for further thought on environmental jus in bello.
Pushing forward, ethical inquiry in this new area ought to set out from solid beginnings, those that generate the strongest consensus between competing moral theories and ethical standpoints. John Rawls famously coined the term ‘overlapping consensus’ to denote widespread agreement among free and equal citizens who espouse conflicting comprehensive doctrines on the principles of justice. This means that similar normative conclusions can be derived from different, even contrasting, philosophical and moral creeds, generating wide agreement from vastly different viewpoints.Footnote 56
The idea of attaining overlapping consensus on environmental protection in wartime was first introduced by Reichberg and Syse in an attempt to reach beyond their specifically Thomist argument: ‘Even if one discards the way of viewing man and nature outlined here, one may nonetheless accept it as one way of grounding a moral view of the environment and warfare.’Footnote 57
This possibility of finding common moral ground, distinct from compromise, sustaining and supporting similar prescriptions from very different doctrines and perspectives – highly relevant to Reichberg and Syse’s arguments from Thomas Aquinas – is wholly essential to the argument presented here. Thinking comprehensively about environmental protection in wartime requires contending with contesting points of view within environmental ethics, moral philosophy, and the just war tradition. There are, to date, at least three different perspectives in environmental ethics (anthropocentric, biocentric, and ecocentric), three relevant moral philosophies (utilitarian, deontological, and virtue ethics), and two prominent reigning theories of just war (‘traditionalist’ and ‘revisionist’). It is impossible to explicate all these theories here, or to take sides in these divides, but it is important to note them. In the remainder of this section, I introduce traditional just war theory and its revisionist alternative, as well as very basic environmental ethics. Readers familiar with standard ethical theories on war and the environment (and the overlapping consensus strategy) may wish to skip ahead to Subsection 1.3.
Beginning in the medieval writings of Augustine and later of Thomas Aquinas, the definitive account of the just war tradition, or ‘Just War Theory’ (JWT), in modern times appears in Michael Walzer’s classic Just and Unjust Wars and is closely aligned with the International Law of Armed Conflict (ILOAC). Within this tradition, the rules and customs of war divide sharply into two distinct categories: jus ad bellum governs the initial resort to war, and is the responsibility of state leaders, while jus in bello regulates the conduct of war by the military. Armies are required to distinguish civilians from combatants and to refrain from targeting the former. Combatants may fight and kill, regardless of the justness of their cause, and are legitimate targets of attack by virtue of their threatening nature. Non-combatants remain immune from direct attack. Necessity precludes wanton violence. Proportionality in bello requires the military to minimize incidental harm to civilians and civilian objects.Footnote 58 These rules apply equally to all parties, independently of their respective causes and the overall justness of their war or any personal blame.Footnote 59
Originating in the work of Jeff McMahan, the ‘revisionist’ morality of war takes issue with blanket civilian immunity, combatant equality, and the overarching independence of jus in bello from jus ad bellum. With its roots in the writings of Renaissance philosophers such as Francisco de Vitoria and Francisco Suarez in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, revisionist (neo-classical) theory denies that the existing rules and customs of war reflect deep morality. Ultimately, the reasons for fighting a war (whether just or unjust, defensive or aggressive) are inseparable from the very licence to fight and kill. Accordingly, just and unjust combatants cannot be morally equal. If killing in war is justified as self-defence, then only soldiers on the defensive side can possess this license. Moreover, combatants who fight an unjust war can rarely fulfill the jus in bello requirements of necessity and proportionality. (If their war is aggressive, futile, and injurious, how can any of its measures be necessary and proportionate?) Consequently, unjust wars also defy the laws that govern conduct in battle. Finally, not all civilians are innocent or non-threatening, so there can be no deep moral justification for their automatic immunity as a group. Liability to harm and immunity from harm, McMahan argues, should be determined on the basis of individual contribution to and responsibility for injustice, as in civilian life.Footnote 60
The result is a well-known split within JWT and the emergence of two camps.Footnote 61 Much of the current scholarship on the ethics of war is of the critical–revisionist variety, while the remainder is mostly traditionalist, as are the laws and military handbooks.Footnote 62 Environmental issues are typically absent from any of this philosophical work on war.Footnote 63
Environmental ethicists, for their part, are mostly uninvolved in this JWT debate. As for their own traditional divisions, broadly described, anthropocentrism regards the value of nature and its non-human components as solely instrumental in furthering human objectives. All living organisms, ecological compilations, and inanimate elements within nature are devoid of independent moral standing and are valuable solely for the benefit of mankind. Biocentric and ecocentric theories dispute this, and attribute intrinsic value and moral standing to non-human living individuals or ecological collectives, respectively. Biocentrism, literally signifying a ‘life-centred’ approach, grounds obligations for environmental protection in the moral value of other-than-human living individuals. By contrast, ecocentrism shifts the moral focus from individual creatures to ecological wholes, namely biological species, biomes, and entire ecosystems, and sanctions attaching intrinsic value to inanimate elements of the natural environment such as rivers, lakes, landscapes, and mountains.Footnote 64
Beyond the anthropocentric versus non-anthropocentric (bio/ecocentric) divide, the three perspectives draw, in profoundly different ways, on general theories of normative ethics to establish humanity’s moral obligation towards nature. Anthropocentric thinkers establish only indirect duties to protect the environment, based on the purely human interests of both current and future generations.Footnote 65 Such human-centred justifications for environmental protection, or combined approaches, rely on either virtue ethics, or utilitarianism, or deontology.Footnote 66
Similarly, biocentric and ecocentric ethicists apply either utilitarian or deontological morality to make the case for the protection of non-human entities, grounding direct duties towards non-human moral subjects. Biocentric environmental ethics intersects with different general moral theories at various junctions, such as ‘sentientism’ – closely associated with Peter Singer’s utilitarian approach to animal rightsFootnote 67 – or ‘biocentric consequentialism’Footnote 68 versus a deontological approach to animal rights.Footnote 69 Ecocentrism, ecological ethics or the ethics of deep ecology, is also morally varied.Footnote 70 Biocentrism, sentientism, and ecocentrism may or may not be egalitarian in the sense of attributing equal moral value to all living things (biocentric egalitarianism) or even, beyond living things, to natural objects and ecosystems, adding to the multifariousness of perspectives.Footnote 71
For all the theoretical diversity and moral pluralism within environmental ethics and JWT, the duty to protect the natural environment during wartime is the subject of an overlapping consensus on which moral theories are likely to converge, though they will differ in their reasoning and in the extent of protection they afford (e.g. the cross-cutting conclusion that military use of herbicides is wrong).Footnote 72 One very basic example of this is the fundamental question of establishing the moral and legal status of the natural environment in bello.
1.3 Environmental Non-combatant Immunity
Drucker’s early suggestion of extending non-combatant immunity to the environment rests on nature’s unquestionably great value, inherently and/or for the well-being of humankind, establishing a moral reason to preserve it. Consequently, Drucker argues, the same arguments that support wartime civilian immunity and the protection of cultural artifacts apply to the environment, to wit: nature is non-threatening (echoing Walzer’s explanation of civilian immunity), nor is it in the business of war;Footnote 73 it did not choose to be involved; moreover, it provides sustenance and nurture, rendering it akin to medical and religious personnel.Footnote 74
Affording full-fledged non-combatant immunity to the environment, with all the rights that designation implies, is, however, difficult to maintain. One problem with this approach, Michael Deiderich points out, ‘is that wars are fought largely in the natural environment, and that a commander would not be expected to sacrifice a soldier to save a tree’.Footnote 75 Another concern raised by Hedahl et al. is that wartime civilians have absolute rights against direct attack and military use:
It would appear to strain credulity to believe that the environment has a right against ever being used as a means to an end. One should not be forced to conclude that digging trenches and thereby using the environment as a means would be wrong, even though using a competent adult who is not involved in hostilities in a similar way might well be.Footnote 76
Notwithstanding, Drucker’s basic reasoning is compelling because it encompasses all perspectives and attempts to avoid radical conclusions. Although environmental noncombatant immunity is fully sustainable only on the basis of a deontological morality that attributes inherent worth to the environment, it is, more modestly, analogous to the protection accorded by existing IHL – anthropocentric–utilitarian ‘humanitarian’ law – to works of art and other cultural assets.Footnote 77
Rejecting the analysis of nature as a genuine ‘non-combatant’, Hedahl et al. point out that the environment is nonetheless not a combatant, thereby retaining a prima facie presumption against violent attack. Reminding us that the moral default, even in wartime, is against the use of force, the authors argue more plausibly that military violence against nature should require robust justification. They propose that ‘impacts to the environment must be appropriately considered in any double-effect calculation’, emphasizing their significance in determining proportionality in bello.Footnote 78
One advantageous feature of this last proposal to incorporate nature in the proportionality calculus is that it represents a moment of union between conflicting perspectives on human–nature relations. The aforementioned debate within environmental ethics revolves around whether to approach the natural environment as having intrinsic or merely instrumental value for human beings, though, to the extent that we are part of nature, this may be something of a false dichotomy.Footnote 79 The environmentally devastating effects of the Russian war in Ukraine, for example, indicate that much of what is bad for nature is harmful to human beings as well. Looking to include animals in the ethics of war, considering the harmful impact on animals within its proportionality calculations, Milburn and Van Goozen point out a similar overlap: ‘the JWT requirement of discrimination already rules out many of the forms of warfare that are most impactful on animals. For example, as chemical and nuclear warfare or booby traps are likely to devastate humans as well as animals, JWT already rules these out as indiscriminate.’Footnote 80
In the case in hand, a human-centred approach (anthropocentrism) as well as various non-anthropocentric approaches to environmental ethics (notably biocentrism and ecocentrism) would endorse attributing weighty consideration to environmental damage within wartime proportionality, but the former would not endorse the less tenable proposal to equate the status of nature with the absoluteness attached to civilian human rights. Accommodating a range of ethical perspectives – anthropocentric/non-anthropocentric – identifies points of overlapping consensus that enable wide agreement on realistically sustainable advances in protecting the environment at war.
The traditionalist versus revisionist divide within the ethics of war suggests similar benefits of value agnosticism and attaining overlapping consensus between different world-views on environmental protection. Drucker argued for environmental noncombatant immunity because the environment is non-threatening, echoing Walzer’s explanation of civilian immunity.Footnote 81 Considering the revisionist perspective adds an extra layer of wartime environmental protection to the Walzerian reasoning that regards those who are non-threatening as immune from attack. Revisionist philosophers of war notoriously reject the traditional distinction between threatening combatants and (ostensibly) non-threatening civilians, arguing that the correct criterion of liability to attack in war is not posing a direct threat but rather being morally responsible for an objectively unjustified, wrongful threat.Footnote 82 Needless to say, nature is not responsible for wartime injustice any more than it poses a threat, nor is it an agent capable of full moral standing. The environment is innocent in the deep moral sense, and not to blame for war.Footnote 83 Moreover, the necessarily continuous range of potential duties towards the environment – before, during, and after armed conflict – should come naturally to revisionist philosophers of war, who reject ‘the idea that a different morality comes into effect in conditions of war’.Footnote 84 The revisionist ‘reductivist’ approach to war, which ‘treats warfare as morally continuous with all other activities’, accords with the realities of protecting the natural environment over time.Footnote 85
Incorporating the revised criterion of liability serves once again to strengthen our presumption against aggression towards entities that are not combatants, but not the far-reaching proposition that would grant the environment full non-combatant status and immunities, on a par with human rights. A morality of war that describes itself as ‘individualist’ might be hard-pressed to stretch much further away from humanitarianism.Footnote 86
Both theories of the just war are complemented by acknowledging that civilian immunity rests on a basic principle of just combat that proscribes attacking the defenceless.Footnote 87 This justification for civilian immunity is particularly applicable to the environment, which is patently defenceless and vulnerable, as are its individual non-human inhabitants.Footnote 88 The vulnerability-based justification for protecting sentient beings in wartime crosses animal rights and environmental ethics, with both traditional JWT and revisionism lending the argument greater credence. Maintaining consensus with anthropocentrism, in both environmental and military ethics, reminds us to weigh the welfare of nature and its non-human inhabitants against military goals and human life, and to avoid untenable wartime conclusions that would result from attributing equality to all life forms or absolute non-combatant immunity to the environment.
1.4 Concluding Remarks
The conduct of hostilities is very bad for nature, yet relatively little attention has been focused on environmental military ethics within the voluminous writing by just war theorists and revisionist philosophers of war. Lawyers have done better.
Taking our first steps towards an environmental ethic of war suggests that the strongest moments of moral truth – at least its minimal core content – are present at those points of convergence and consensus between all perspectives. Points of agreement between conflicting ethical camps, notably utilitarianism and Kantian moral philosophies, anthropocentric and non-anthropocentric environmental ethics, and traditional and revisionist moralities of war, indicate moments of moral truth. Unless all our normative thinking is askew, it is unlikely that all approaches would be wrong on a particular issue. When in uncharted moral territory, this is probably the most solid ground from which to set out.
On a practical note, despite contemporary public attention on environmental deterioration (Greta Thunberg notwithstanding), the idea of protecting nature during wartime does not come easily. At least at first blush, wartime concern for human life and well-being appears far too pressing to allow for consideration of wildlife, far less to protect it at the expense of human beings.Footnote 89 It is difficult enough to persuade warring parties to respect the lives of enemy civilians at the expense of their own military advantage, let alone value a species of animal or their natural habitats.Footnote 90
Accommodating different perspectives and focusing on points of consensus should prevent unrealistic extremes from either environmentalism or militarism and help avoid conclusions that are well-argued and morally attractive in theory (on paper) but are realistically impractical. Coming at this from environmental ethics or deep moral philosophy risks over-zealous environmentalism, placing unduly demanding restrictions on war-making, verging on pacifism, as well as on its individual participants, whose lives are already at risk. At the other end of the equation, militarism, pure anthropocentrism, or raison d’état alone will likely overemphasize ‘necessity’ and downplay environmental harms in relation to immediate military advantage.
The status of the environment in wartime is a clear case study for overlapping consensus: affording absolute civilian immunity to the natural environment is unjustified from a humanist perspective, and untenable from a military standpoint; but the lesser analogy with cultural artifacts can be supported by a full host of relevant moral theories. Referring to existing law as a benchmark, this equilibrium is well reflected in the Red Cross’s articulation of the aforementioned relevant legal rules in Protocol I: ‘Except in rare cases when it has become a military objective, it is against the law to attack the natural environment.’Footnote 91
2 Environmental Just Wars: Jus ad Bellum and the Natural Environment
War is bad for the environment. As discussed in Section 1, contemporary ecological concerns pose significant challenges to jus in bello, or military ethics.Footnote 92 Nevertheless, despite growing awareness of environmental issues, just war theorists and moral philosophers of war have paid insufficient attention to the military’s carbon footprint, notwithstanding notable exceptions reviewed in the previous section.Footnote 93 The law and legal scholars have paid more attention to protecting nature during armed conflict. In this area, the law, by virtue of necessity, precedes moral scholarship and may serve to advance it. But, because the International Law of Armed Conflict focuses primarily on the rules of engagement regulating the conduct of hostilities, issues concerning environmentally just and unjust wars have received even less normative attention than environmental protection in war.Footnote 94
The current jus ad bellum legal regime does not recognize any environmental injuries that fall short of ‘armed attack’ as just causes for war, and the dangers of legalizing additional occasions for war go without saying. Because of the different nature and functions of morality and law, even the most practical ethics may not translate directly into legal proposals; law must account for a multitude of practicalities that may elude moral philosophers of war.Footnote 95 This does not settle the issue at hand or render futile the consideration of future environmental causes for war. As new dangers emerge, ethical deliberation should eventually guide and influence the jus ad bellum regime. Ethical reflection on timely concerns should ultimately help inform and shape a legal regime that takes emerging environmental concerns more seriously.
Empirically, the natural environment plays a very significant role in the resort to war. Natural wealth (such as oil) funds and encourages participants in civil wars; greed for the riches of the earth – diamonds, oil, and other natural resources – may partly explain the onset, duration, and ferocity of these wars.Footnote 96 Links between climate change and conflicts have been debated within the academic literature, indicating that an increasing number of wars are being driven by environmental destruction, by climate change, and by resource scarcity.Footnote 97 As global climate change progresses and areas of the world become uninhabitable, conflicts over living space and scarce natural resources are likely to increase, placing pressure on the current jus ad bellum regime.Footnote 98
The following two subsections focus on potential ecological justifications for war as well as on the proportionality of any such recourse to arms on behalf of the environment. Setting out with the presumption against the use of force, Subsection 2.1 considers whether environmental harm can form a new justification for war, presumably in the context of war’s prima facie unjustifiability. Subsection 2.2 asks how the environment figures into the proportionality of war itself (as distinct from the jus in bello requirement to minimize collateral damage).Footnote 99 Subsection 2.3 asks who the ‘right authority’ would be to declare war for environmental reasons.
My answers are not definitive. The use of force is clearly justified in response to military aggression, whether against the natural environment or otherwise. Where harm to nature or its inhabitants is not caused by military attack, JWT criteria point in favour of responding via measures short of war. Combating harm to nature by military means always runs a high risk of causing more environmental harm than good. Non-military measures – international pressures, protests, and sanctions – do not require satisfying the jus ad bellum proportionality (or ‘just authority’) requirement, but any resort to arms does require meeting these conditions. Resorting to limited force short of all out war – e.g. pinpointed drone strikes and cyber-attacks – mitigates the risk of disproportionality. Finally, I suggest that resorting to soft power and possibly limited force – less harmful to the environment than full-scale armed conflict – as well as international cooperation, also helps satisfy the ‘just authority’ condition and serves to indicate ‘right intention’, deflecting suspicions about the use of force to advance state interests on the pretext of environmental protection.
2.1 Environmental Just Cause
To start with, on all accounts, wars must have a just cause, typically that of resisting aggression (national self-defence). Traditionally, aggression is ‘the crime of war’.Footnote 100 In the post-World War II era, the prohibition against the use of force among states, as well as the exceptions to it (self-defence and UN Security Council authorization), are well-established within the UN Charter system.Footnote 101 Effectively, contemporary international law and JWT now recognize only one just cause for waging war unilaterally: self- or other defence against aggression understood as the occurrence of an armed attackFootnote 102 ‘(with the possible exception of the prevention of large-scale violations of human rights, such as genocide)’.Footnote 103 Reichberg and Syse explain:
Since war is prima facie an evil, participation in it requires moral and legal justification. Thus, according to the moral logic of ‘just cause’, war-making will be deemed rightful or just solely when it arises as a response to grave wrongdoing committed by the other side.Footnote 104
On a revisionist–individualist version of JWT, ‘a just cause for war is a wrong that is of a type that can make those responsible for it morally liable to military attack as a means of preventing or rectifying it’.Footnote 105 On both versions of JWT – revisionist and traditionalist – as well as international law, the ultimate objective of war is protecting basic human rights, whether via national self-defence or, more reductively, individual self-defence.Footnote 106
Environmental destruction is often part and parcel of an ongoing aggressive attack on a state’s sovereignty and its members’ basic rights. Russian aggression towards Ukraine supplies ample examples of assaults on the natural environment that also threaten life and liberty.Footnote 107 This is aggression simpliciter. Airborne incendiary devices launched from the Gaza Strip into Southern Israel between 2018 and 2023 – setting forests and fields alight, wreaking long-term ecological damage – present far lower-intensity cases of contemporary environmental aggression, discussed in Section 4.Footnote 108 As no Israelis were killed or injured in these attacks, the level of aggression and the appropriate response remain debatable issues. In hindsight, they pale in comparison with the murderous October 7 invasion. Nonetheless, kites and balloons were military incursions that crossed borders and caused widespread environmental harm on Israeli territory, straightforwardly violating sovereignty and individual rights to personal safety and private property.Footnote 109 In both the Israeli and the Ukrainian cases, attacks against land and property, whatever their degree, fit comfortably within traditional JWT; the crime of aggression is not limited to bodily harm or killing.Footnote 110
Suggesting a rich history of attributing significance to environmental impacts within just war deliberations, Hedahl et al. point out that Vitoria included damaging the environment (e.g. by burning vineyards or olive gardens) among the just causes for war,Footnote 111 though notably vineyards and olive gardens are human-made. Grotius compared the severity of poisoning the land to poisoning a person, both warranting the right to defend, recover, and punish, within or between political communities respectively.Footnote 112 As with Vitoria, attributing care for the natural environment per se to Hugo Grotius is a bit of a stretch: poisoning the land is a wrong to humans, who will not be able to use the land, rather than a wrong to the land itself. Nonetheless, as ‘the father of international law’ it is noteworthy that he regarded violence towards land as a casus belli.
Setting out with this tradition, it is not unthinkable to argue, as does Robyn Eckersley, that major environmental emergencies with transboundary spillover effects that threaten public safety; for example, ‘Chernobyl-style’ threats of nuclear explosion, would morally and legally justify military action. This is the strongest and most minimalist argument for ecological intervention because ‘incursions of pollution or hazardous substances into the territory of neighboring states are analogous to an “armed attack” with chemical, biological, or nuclear weapons; they enter or threaten to enter the territory of the victim state without its consent and with equally grave consequences.’Footnote 113 This first set of cases would count as threats to territorial integrity, rendering an environmental just cause, per se, redundant as justification for war, because just cause could be captured by the right to defend sovereignty.
A second case is where severe ecological harm, or ‘ecocide’, accompanies grave human rights violations, on a par with genocide or crimes against humanity. Here, Eckersley continues, justifying military action rides on the back of humanitarian intervention – ‘eco-humanitarian intervention’ – and is subject to all the controversies and challenges surrounding the emerging norm of responsibility to protect, and then some.Footnote 114 Legally, there is no such ‘eco-humanitarian’ basis for war in current international law, and even humanitarian intervention does not yet constitute a clear exception to the prohibition on the use of force.
The most interesting question remains whether environmental concerns could ever constitute a wrong that gives rise to ‘just cause’, even if a state’s territory has not been invaded and where no basic human rights have been directly infringed.Footnote 115 Territorial invasions and genocide that involve harm to the natural environment do not stray far from conventional justifications for war. Responding to environmental harms that do not involve territorial incursion or violation of human rights would rest entirely on ecological grounds.Footnote 116
Eckersley considers extending the idea of responsibility to protect (R2P) to non-human species and biodiversity, that is, military intervention to prevent ‘ecocide’ or ‘crimes against nature’ in themselves, even where consequences are confined to the culprit state causing harm to its own environment. If we view relations between humans and nature in trustor–trustee, or custodianship, terms, it follows that the destruction of species and ecosystems is a dereliction of duty.Footnote 117 On this account, deliberate and wilful acts that cause grave environmental damage (e.g. Iraq setting fire to Kuwait’s oil fields) or extermination of species (e.g. the threat of poachers annihilating mountain gorillas) might then be regarded as war crimes in the first instance, or comparable to conscience-shocking ‘crimes against humanity’ in the second, possibly triggering ‘just cause’ for international military intervention (subject to the remaining just war requirements).Footnote 118
For present purposes, I set aside the question of justifying military action solely on behalf of other species or nature per se without resorting to any human interests. Establishing a purely ecological just cause for war would require settling the most basic divides within environmental ethics – anthropocentric versus non-anthropocentric – in all its variety.Footnote 119 Justifying intervention to protect a local environment – its ecosystems, species, and habitats – as being on a par with the ideal of humanitarian intervention to protect human life might require a doctrine of conditional sovereignty whereby the right against interference is contingent upon meeting minimal environmental moral standards.Footnote 120 Legally, such a basis for war does not even remotely exist in international law. Military rescue of non-human species, extending R2P to biological diversity, is unlikely and doubtfully desirable, considering the high costs of war. Moreover, in most real-world cases, the extreme type of environmental harm that could even potentially justify war would likely be bad for humans as well, at least indirectly, and exceed national boundaries.Footnote 121
Discussing World Heritage Sites that lie within the territorial boundaries of sovereign states, Cecile Fabre supplies a timely example recalling the 2019 fires in the Amazon rainforest.
These are regular occurrences, which inflict untold damage on homes, animal species, and the planet’s ecosystems. Anger at what many regard as the Brazilian authorities’ unconscionably reckless approach to deforestation has focused on its environmental impact for present and future generations.Footnote 122
In such cases, Fabre suggests, outsiders have a claim to the preservation and, if necessary, restoration of ‘humankind’s common heritage’.Footnote 123 Following UNESCO’s World Heritage List, these include not only universally valuable man-made landmarks, such as Notre Dame de Paris, but also natural landscapes, rivers, mountains, and lakes, like the Smokey Mountains in the US or Lake Baikal in Russia, noting that some landmarks are valuable not only as heritage but also for instrumental reasons.Footnote 124
The Amazon rainforest is (arguably) said to produce 20 per cent of the Earth’s atmospheric oxygen. Clearly, beyond UNESCO’s World Heritage List well-noted by Fabre, the Amazon is a global systematic resource – ‘global public commons’ – required for the balance of the earth’s systems. Its burning caused severe harm to the ecosystem, vital to the planet, and warrants its protection. Consequently, the fires became something of an international crisis, with Brazil’s lax policy prompting the aforementioned anger of, and fierce response from, world leaders (memorably, French President Emmanuel Macron) culminating in a threat by G7 countries to withdraw from trade negotiations with Brazil.
In response, President Jair Bolsonaro accused the G7 leaders of intervening in Brazil’s internal affairs. Despite repeated pleas from the international community and non-governmental organizations, Brazil refused to revise its environmental policies, with possible dire ramifications in terms of deforestation and climate change. This is of course just one example of the international community’s persistent failure to guarantee compliance on environmental issues (e.g. climate change mitigation, ecological protection, biodiversity conservation, etc.).Footnote 125
Whether or not one accepts the argument for ‘Humankind’s Common Heritage’ in toto, the example of wildfires in the Brazilian Amazon rainforest and resultant deforestation presents a uniquely good case study for reflecting on the permissibility of resorting to force to avert grave ecological destruction, when all else has failed.Footnote 126
In keeping with the G7 threat, Fabre maintains that the protection of outsiders’ interests in such sites of ecological or cultural significance is an enforceable duty of justice, suggesting the appropriateness of economic sanctions, expulsion from international organizations, reduction in foreign aid, and so on, in cases like this one.Footnote 127 Could extreme dereliction of duty to maintain vital ecological sites also justify force as a last resort?
Not unrelated to the notion of common heritage or global resources (albeit in regard to jus in bello), Reichberg and Syse allude to the natural law tradition whereby all property is originally and ultimately common to humankind, while private property is fully justified as expedient.
Thus, the destruction of, say, farmland, rain forests, or oil resources constitutes not only a violation of the property rights of those who live in or own that area now; it is also a way of destroying property which in a sense is common to all of mankind, including future generations … This entails a moral prohibition against large-scale devastation of territory, even within one’s own national jurisdiction.Footnote 128
Considering the gravity of contemporary environmental concerns, the idea of an ecological just cause arising from such devastation even in one’s own territory, or of resisting ‘environmental aggression’, is far from fanciful. In the Amazonian case and most others, environmental destruction is manifestly bad for human beings, not only nature per se – at least in the long run – perhaps violating our common property or resources, as well as harmful to animals and inanimate components of nature. Climate change is a case in point.
Appealing to the just war framework, Marcus Hedahl and Kyle Fruh suggest that carbon-emitting activities perpetuating global warming constitute aggression towards the most vulnerable to its effects, to wit, low-lying lands such as Tuvalu, which will soon face existential threat as a result.Footnote 129 ‘In perpetrating climate change, we are, in fact, waging war against the most vulnerable.’Footnote 130 Climate change, they argue, is an unjust war justifying self-defence on behalf of the injured party.Footnote 131 Subsequently, they defend retaliation by these nations via geoengineering, specifically solar radiation management (SRM), which is equally construed as an act of war but justified in these cases.Footnote 132 Ultimately, they concede their argument also suggests that in principle ‘In the right circumstances, low-lying nations would possess the normative authority to engage in kinetic attacks on GHG-producing facilities.’Footnote 133
The threat to be averted notwithstanding, establishing a ‘green just cause’, even from a purely anthropocentric stance, would not at present fit easily with any known version of JWT, and would require considerable (perhaps desirable) adjustment of existing tenets in either its traditional or its revisionist account, as well as international law. As Hedahl and Fruh recognize, paradigmatic aggression consists in the intentional and deliberate use of force by an identifiable party against territorial integrity or political sovereignty.Footnote 134 Causing environmental damage does not necessarily entail the use of military means of the type that would ordinarily generate just cause for war in response to an armed attack. In the Brazilian example, ‘just cause’ would be distinct from self-defence on both traditionalist and revisionist versions of JWT because outsiders’ basic rights are not necessarily undermined or impaired by failure to preserve a site such as the Amazon – at least not directly or immediately – nor was any nation-state invaded by an act constituting outright ‘aggression’ in any traditional or legal sense.Footnote 135
All the same, bearing in mind increasing anthropogenic destruction and climate change, it is not impossible to envision continuous and future transgression that would violate the human right to a safe environment, both individually and communally, hampering another nation’s ability to ‘determine their own levels of environmental quality’ as well as individual health and well-being.Footnote 136 This might indeed constitute ‘aggression’ even if no border is crossed, potentially justifying recourse to force in response if and when all else fails. In revisionist terms, grave ecological negligence or harm to the non-human world could constitute a wrong of sufficient severity to render responsible individuals in the perpetrator state liable to defensive attack, if attacking them could correct, or considerably mitigate, the environmental wrong in question.Footnote 137
It is difficult to specify exhaustively the wide variety of possibilities that might potentially trigger a future ‘just cause’. As global environmental degradation continues to unfold, urgency will have a bearing on these issues. Once again, the easiest cases are those in which harm to nature involves conventional invasion of territory, as with the environmental damage due to the war in Ukraine, or inflammatory airborne devices entering Israel. Next, following Eckersley, emitting harmful substances directly into another state is arguably analogous to territorial invasion.Footnote 138 Large emissions of greenhouse gases, however, are unfortunately still the norm, and therefore it would be very difficult for anything resembling the present understanding to justify an exceptional resort to force, despite the far-reaching and long-term consequences of rising temperatures.Footnote 139 Clear breaches of existing international law (e.g. blowing up Antarctica), on the other hand, would be better candidates for intervention. The weakest cases for intervention, straying furthest from existing law, are those of states destroying only their local environment, where the devastation is entirely contained within their own national jurisdiction, though arguably any environmental harm affects us all at least indirectly and destroys property common to mankind, including future generations.Footnote 140
Acknowledging a non-comprehensive range stretching from old-fashioned violation of sovereignty at one end, and local harm to one’s own territory or national resources at the other, Bolsonaro’s Brazil supplied a timely example of a state destroying its own environment and at the same time damaging its population and the world at large. Nonetheless, where no actual or imminent armed attack is present, justifying war to combat environmental harm is unlikely to fulfil the jus ad bellum principle of proportionality.
2.2 What Is a Proportionate Response?
Even if ‘just cause’ could be adjusted to accommodate non-military environmental wrongs, the further ad bellum criterion of proportionality would still be difficult to satisfy in cases of purely ecological harm. As for armed environmental aggression, military attacks on the environment would count as a threat to territorial integrity (which, along with political independence, constitutes sovereignty). Such cases would not require an environmental just cause per se, because they could be captured by the right to defend sovereignty, responding to ‘armed attack’. Even so, military response may harm the environment to an extent that dwarfs its benefit. In keeping with proportionality, what unilateral military measures, if any, might states employ to fend off environmental harm?
The relevant international legal documents – the UN CharterFootnote 141 and UN Security Council Resolutions – do not contain positive references to proportionality ad bellum as a limitation on self-defence in response to an armed attack. Nevertheless, such a restriction is recognized as part of customary international law.Footnote 142 Originally derived from the 1837 Caroline incident,Footnote 143 and reinforced more recently by several opinions of the International Court of Justice (ICJ),Footnote 144 it is widely acknowledged that a military operation should not exceed the goal of restoring the status quo that predated the armed attack to which it is responding – self-defence should not be retaliatory or punitive and reprisals are generally agreed to be unlawful – though this does not tell us much about the legitimate extent of response.Footnote 145
As opposed to proportionality in bello regulated by International Humanitarian Law, ad bellum proportionality applies to the legitimacy of the forceful action in total, rather than its specific tactics.Footnote 146 It throws a wide net rather than focusing narrowly on collateral damage to civilians, applying instead to the general overall level of devastation anticipated as a result of the proposed military action. This would include the harm of violating territorial integrity, damage to infrastructure, effects on third parties, and so on,Footnote 147 and presumably all damage to the natural environment. Nonetheless, the indeterminacies of this requirement far exceed its discernable limits; and the specific content of any legal ad bellum proportionality test remains extremely vague and controversial, as it does within the JWT that underlies it.
As for the just war tradition, all versions include an ad bellum proportionality condition that applies to the war as a whole, requiring that its destructiveness must not be excessive in relation to the relevant good it will achieve.Footnote 148 This was Vitoria’s understanding, echoed in countless contemporary discussions of proportionality.Footnote 149 Thomas Hurka explains that ad bellum proportionality requires balancing the good that the war is designed to bring about – the wrong it is intended to avert – against the harm that the war causes.Footnote 150 It involves weighing the costs and benefits of war overall, though how exactly these are to be estimated or compared remains very vague.Footnote 151
What seems clear and pertinent is that proportionality in jus ad bellum is inevitably tied to just cause: an aggressive war cannot have any relevant benefits to balance against the harm it inflicts. Without just cause, there are no sufficient harms that warrant armed resistance. Only a war fought for a good cause, typically wars of self-defence, can pass the ad bellum proportionality test.Footnote 152 When wars are fought for the right reasons, the benefits side of the proportionality calculus includes their initial just cause – resisting aggression.
Just war theory also acknowledges several legitimate ‘conditional’ goals that the military is entitled to pursue, such as disarming a threatening enemy and deterring further aggression. Additional wartime goals are conditional in that they would not in themselves justify the resort to war. Nonetheless, when they accompany an initially sufficient just cause for war, specifically self-defence, these additional goals count as potential benefits that weigh against the harms of the war and contribute to its proportionality.Footnote 153
This invariable link between justice of cause and proportionality comes to the fore when considering a new casus belli, namely environmental harm. First, the distinction between ‘sufficient’ and ‘contributing’ (conditional) just causes is particularly pertinent to the environmental benefits of war and their contribution to its proportionality calculations. While it may not be permissible at present to fight wars for purely environmental reasons, morally valuable ends such as promoting environmental justice might serve to add legitimacy to a war that already has a lawful just cause. Recognizing a ‘conditional’ environmental goal would increase the benefits side of proportionality calculations, presumably licensing greater use of force or allowing more destruction/harms, because of the ‘additional’ justice.
On the other hand, ecological justifications for war pose a special type of complication for the proportionality calculus. While environmental concerns may broaden the scope of just cause, the inevitable devastation caused by warfare makes proportionality more difficult to satisfy. Irrespective of whether the ecological harm was inflicted via armed attack or not, warfare undertaken for environmental protection will foreseeably cause further damage to the natural environment, which may well outweigh its gains.Footnote 154 Moreover, full-scale military responses to non-military harm, or even to armed attacks that are largely non-lethal to humans, would likely be viewed as excessive by both public and legal opinion.
One practical way to meet these challenges is by resorting to limited belligerency in response to environmental wrongs without incurring the extent of devastation that would outweigh the benefits of military action. This includes tactics covered by jus ad vim – the just use of force short of war – that fall below the breadth and intensity of traditional warfare, notably pinpointed air strikes with drones as well as non-kinetic (unarmed) tactics.Footnote 155
Like most contemporary just war thinking, the discussion of jus ad vim begins with Michael Walzer’s Just and Unjust Wars, specifically with the preface to its fourth edition. There, Walzer distinguishes traditional jus ad bellum, governing the resort to actual war (full-scale attacks, invasions), from the moral principles that govern the resort to force short of war, dubbed jus ad vim. As Walzer explains, the measures governed by jus ad vim involve the use (or threat) of force – embargos or the enforcement of no-fly zones, limited airstrikes with drones, etc. – and consequently count as acts of war under international law. Nonetheless, it is common sense to recognize that they are very different from war.Footnote 156
Full-scale conflict always involves grave risks and hazards, unpredictable and all too often catastrophic consequences, and the full-fledged ‘hellishness of war’ described throughout Just and Unjust Wars and enhanced if we count non-human casualties alongside harm to the natural surroundings. Bearing in mind the link between just cause and proportionality as well as the high environmental costs of military action, resorting to full-scale war to fend off ecological hazards, even if they give rise to ‘just cause’, is unlikely to satisfy the ad bellum proportionality requirement to cause more benefit than harm.Footnote 157
By contrast, jus ad vim measures are limited in their scope and intensity, requiring far less force and harm to their surroundings, as well as less risk to their perpetrators. This is certainly the case with embargos and no-fly zones.Footnote 158 As for drones, as Laurie Johnston points out, they ‘have less of a carbon footprint because they are less resource intensive. They use less fuel than manned aircraft.’Footnote 159 Moreover, echoing McMahan’s criterion of liability, Adam Betz points out in connection with targeted killing, ‘A major advantage of these tactics … is the fact that they can be more readily directed at liable parties’.Footnote 160
Opposing any relaxation of the prohibition on the use of force to accommodate ‘atmospheric intervention’ against egregious climate change offenders (e.g. Brazil), Martin nonetheless recognizes that the type of force potentially relevant in such cases would be ‘limited surgical strikes against precisely the infrastructure related to the noncompliant conduct … pertinent historical examples would be the Israeli surgical air strikes against the Iraqi nuclear facility at Osirak in 1981, or again its strike against the Syrian nuclear facility in 2007.’Footnote 161
One risk with air strikes is that they could degenerate into all out international armed conflict.Footnote 162 A further disadvantage concerns the jus in bello core principle of distinction and civilian immunity. As opposed to targeting nuclear munition plants:
the entire premise of atmospheric intervention is that the use of force would be targeted at infrastructure or facilities directly related to the contribution of GHGs [greenhouse gases], it is highly unlikely that such targets could be legitimately characterized as anything other than civilian objects.Footnote 163
Legally, as well as in traditional JWT, air strikes may be deployed only against military targets. When dealing with environmental harms, as in the Amazon example, aiming at combatants may not be relevant. Hedahl and Fruh entertain the possibility of low-lying nations justifiably launching tactical kinetic attacks at GHG-emitting facilities, if this could facilitate their battle against climate change.Footnote 164 A revisionist account of the ethics of war might conceivably justify targeting culpable civilians responsible for grave environmental negligence, if killing them (or destroying related civilian infrastructure) were likely to halt, or seriously diminish, ongoing ecological harm.Footnote 165 More palatable to traditionalists and lawyers, alternative measures short of war also include non-kinetic, ‘soft war’ tactics – ‘softer’ alternatives to kinetic power, such as media and propaganda warfare, economic restrictions, and even cyber-attacks – to halt or repel environmental harms without targeting non-combatants and civilian objects or falling foul of any proportionality requirement.Footnote 166
Tactics covered by jus ad vim are, by definition, forceful measures albeit short of large-scale war, often involving kinetic force, notably the use of drones for targeted killing or pinpointed attacks on relevant facilities. Legally, there is no gradation in the use of force or ‘armed conflict’. Consequently, as Walzer notes, jus ad vim acts are clearly governed by international laws of war and appropriate for combatting military targets and objectives.Footnote 167 The concept of soft war, by contrast, encompasses non-kinetic tactics – e.g. economic and media/information warfare, individual boycotts, and ‘lawfare’ – that do not involve a resort to arms and therefore, apart from intense cyber-attacks, mostly do not count legally as acts of war at all.Footnote 168 Consequently, directing these tactics at non-compliant civilians does not violate non-combatant immunity, on any account of JWT or international law. Pinpointed strikes against military targets respect civilian immunity; measures short of attack are not bound by its requirements.Footnote 169
Resorting to a mixture of jus ad vim and/or soft war tactics to combat environmental injustice is probably our best shot in terms of efficacy and proportionality, from both human- and non-human-centred ethical perspectives. From a traditional and legal standpoint, non-kinetic alternatives and soft power will be more appropriate against civilians and civilian infrastructure, however culpable they may be for the environmental wrongs in question.Footnote 170 Moreover, soft war tactics do not run the risk of counter-productiveness in terms of causing further environmental harm. Last resort and proportionality, as well as common sense, also require exhausting measures such as punitive economic sanctions of increasing severity and collective diplomatic pressures before contemplating force, particularly where no prior belligerent attack has taken place.Footnote 171
When outright environmental aggression is perpetrated by an attacking army (as in the Russian case) or terrorist organizations (as in the case of Hamas), kinetic jus ad vim tactics against combatants and other military targets are legitimate, assuming reasonable chance of success, at a low cost to their operatives and to the natural surroundings they purport to protect. For revisionist philosophers of war, this conclusion holds also for targeting culpable civilian aggressors and applicable infrastructure, if attacking them is likely to reduce the injustice they cause while avoiding excessive costs to nature as well as to non-liable combatants and civilians on the just side.
2.3 Legitimate Authority and Right Intention
In conventional wars, the jus ad bellum condition of ‘legitimate authority’ appears virtually procedural, established automatically when war is declared by heads of state.Footnote 172 On whose authority would warfare or kinetic force short of war be waged on behalf of the environment, or humanity’s interest in it? Few states are themselves environmentally compliant and therefore lack the moral standing to coerce (potentially by means of kinetic force) environmental bad actors, suggesting the appropriateness of forceful measures only in the most egregious cases.
Even in extremis, forceful measures to protect global resources or ‘common heritage’ should probably not be undertaken as lone ventures. Optimally, any military response to environmental wrongdoing would be an international endeavour rather than a vigilante job, subject to suspicions of ulterior motives. Possibly, as Craig Martin predicts in connection with climate change, combating environmental rogues would begin with demands on the UN Security Council to authorize military action in advance under a widened understanding of its role in maintaining international peace and security before generating new ‘just causes’ for unilateral action, though how likely or desirable any of this is remains extremely questionable.Footnote 173 Martin argues persuasively that we ought to resist any such readjustments that would be counterproductive in terms of climate change and the international rule of law.Footnote 174 He also notes that ‘The five permanent members of the U.N. Security Council are all among the most responsible for climate change’.Footnote 175
Notwithstanding, counterproductivity may be mitigated by resorting to jus ad vim – drone strikes and targeted killing, cyber-attacks – which is less detrimental to the environment than large-scale warfare. Rule of law would still require, inter alia, satisfying the ‘right authority’ condition for any use of force. Acknowledging the dangers of opening a new cause for jus ad bellum (or jus ad vim), the UN Security Council, albeit nonideal, nonetheless seems the most ‘legitimate authority’ for protecting global resources – ‘our common heritage’ – from severe harm, when this is necessary at the bar of last resort.
Crucially, various soft war tactics can respond to ‘environmental just cause’ without opening the can of worms involved in authorizing military action on new pretexts. Affirming the protection of ecologically (as well as culturally) significant sites as ‘a duty of justice’, Fabre proposes a mixture of economic and international pressures, designed to combat defiant states.Footnote 176 While economic sanctions and expulsions from international organizations require authoritative decisions, they do not involve sanctioning war, lending these unarmed tactics an additional layer of justification that does not apply to jus ad vim. Moreover, some soft war pressure tactics are not subject to any formal political or legal constraints: individual boycotts, publicity and information warfare, nonviolent protest, and lawsuits may all be undertaken without appealing to any higher authority.
One further point regarding authorization is noteworthy. As with jus ad vim, soft war tactics have the additional advantage of carrying less risk for their agents, making them more likely candidates for approval by states and their international institutions. Militaries are naturally reluctant to risk their soldiers even to protect foreign civilians, let alone animals and ecosystems. Jus ad vim (targeted killing, drones, cyber-attacks) and soft war (conditional sales/purchases, boycotts, public protest, etc.) do not imperil soldiers and are relatively economical, freeing resources for other needs; they are therefore far more likely to be authorized for environmental protection, at a lower moral cost to young lives and other assets.
Finally, beyond legitimate authority, warfare must also be undertaken with the right intentions, that is, those embedded in the war’s just cause. Environmental war, not unlike humanitarian intervention, runs the risk of being used as a pretext for furthering other interests. International authorization mitigates this danger. Moreover, soft war and jus ad vim tactics that respect proportionality go a long way towards satisfying the rightful intention condition. In the event of an environmental wrong triggering the just cause requirement, it is incumbent on those combating it to demonstrate their sincerity by fighting in ways that avoid causing more environmental devastation than they prevent. Otherwise, they risk becoming aggressors themselves.Footnote 177
2.4 Concluding Remarks
The laws of war focus on rules mitigating the conduct of hostilities rather than the reasons and nature of armed conflict, or justice of its cause. Consequently, within this sub-field – environmental ethics of war – pioneered primarily by lawyers, jus ad bellum has received even less consideration than the environmental ethics in war discussed in the previous section.
War’s prima facie evil requires paying critical attention to any new justifications for armed conflict. Notwithstanding, ecological harm may sometimes constitute a just cause, at the intersection between human and non-human interests, even in the absence of bodily harm. The simplest cases of ‘environmental aggression’ that sit comfortably within the just war tradition are those in which borders are crossed, and environmental devastation involves territorial invasion and the destruction of property. At times, combatting environmental harms may accompany conventional defensive casus belli, enhancing the war’s benefits and contributing to proportionality.
More controversially, in view of the ongoing environmental crisis, it is conceivable that a future just cause may arise from deliberate or negligent harm to the natural environment, even if no direct violence towards land or people has been perpetrated. This is where the fires in the Amazon rainforest came in. Examples like this also raise questions of legitimate authority, notably UN Security Council authorization.
Regarding proportionality ad bellum, where military response is apt and necessary, counter-measures must not wreak more environmental havoc than they purport to combat. I argued that both jus ad vim and soft war offer a better alternative for combating environmental wrongs than outright warfare. Both forceful measures short of war and soft war tactics are more likely to fulfil the requirement of ad bellum proportionality than large-scale armed conflict.Footnote 178
Soft war begins with non-violent action – boycotts and ‘media warfare’, publicity and information, public pressure, as well as ‘lawfare’, i.e. international legal action against perpetrators of environmental harm.Footnote 179 Harsher unarmed measures include political–diplomatic pressure, possibly ‘ecological peacekeeping’, followed closely by economic restrictions and trade sanctions, such as ‘green conditions’ attached to loans, aid, and sales, and rising to cyber-warfare.Footnote 180 Most of these tactics may legitimately be employed against civilians as well as combatants, on all accounts of the just war tradition and international law. ‘Just authority’ is also irrelevant to most soft war tactics (with the likely exception of cyber-war), lending them an additional layer of justification.
Once non-kinetic measures have been exhausted, both environmental and humanitarian concerns about proportionality point towards resorting to limited force short of conventional war – jus ad vim – against military culprits and their infrastructure, preferably as a multinational task undertaken by an international authority.
Finally, satisfying proportionality in the case of an environmental just cause also goes towards fulfilling the further jus ad bellum criterion of ‘right intention’ by displaying sincere care for nature, rather than waging war for ulterior motives on an environmental pretext.
3 Environmental Ethics in Civil Wars
Most wars since 1945 have been intra-state conflicts, often occurring in areas containing the greatest biodiversity, and most wartime casualties since that time have occurred within them. The environment is no exception. By stark contrast, the prolific writing in JWT over the past few decades has concentrated almost exclusively on international conflicts, while notoriously neglecting the natural environment.Footnote 181 These two theoretical shortcomings coincide, as civil wars take place more often than their transnational counterparts on territories rich in natural resources.Footnote 182 ‘Particularly troubling for conservationists is the fact that conflict zones very frequently coincide with so-called biodiversity hotspots’,Footnote 183 Thor Hanson explains:
For biodiversity conservation, the relevance of armed conflicts is confirmed by their prevalence in ‘biodiversity hotspots,’ regions that hold more than half the world’s plant and animal species in only 2.3% of its land area. Between 1950 and 2000, over 90% of major armed conflicts took place within countries containing biodiversity hotspots, and more than 80% included fighting directly within hotspot areas.Footnote 184
Moreover, human-induced environmental pressures and changes, often resulting in resource scarcity, may cause or enhance acute conflict, markedly in the developing world.Footnote 185 Anthropogenic climate change has been described as a ‘threat multiplier’ for political instability; the drought and subsequent migration preceding civil war in Syria is a controversial example.Footnote 186 Civil wars in Chad and Darfur are further cases in point.Footnote 187 Other scholars identify natural riches (especially oil), which are a source of funding and reward for rebels, as a partial cause of internal conflict.Footnote 188
Combat itself adversely affects wildlife through the use of mines, bombs, and chemicals, often in already bio-sensitive habitats ‘as were Rwanda’s gorillas and Angola’s elephants during and in the wake of these countries’ respective civil wars’; ‘mine triggers do not differentiate between humans and nontarget species of sufficient mass to activate them.’Footnote 189 The impact of the Rwandan civil war of 1994 on wildlife, accompanying the infamous human tragedy, is paradigmatic: bombs naturally killed all life forms indiscriminately, while mines reportedly placed along trails in Rwanda’s Parc National des Volcans killed many gorillas.Footnote 190
Years of civil war in Mozambique (1977–92) led to catastrophic die-offs of large mammal herbivores (elephants, zebras, buffalo, hippos, etc.), greatly decreasing their populations in African savannas, in turn affecting savanna habitats and resulting in biodiversity loss.Footnote 191 ‘The elephants of Angola and Mozambique were widely hunted and killed during civil wars in those countries – the elephant population in Mozambique’s Gorongosa National Park declined by 90% during the country’s civil war.’Footnote 192 Trade in wildlife and animal products has served to fund many conflicts, particularly parties to civil wars.Footnote 193 Overall, ‘A study of African protected areas found that the occurrence of armed conflict was the strongest predictor of a drop in large-mammal population sizes between 1946 and 2010’.Footnote 194
As things stand, the most common and frequent environmental harms in sensitive regions – those caused by Non-International Armed Conflict (NIAC) specifically – receive only cursory ethical notice, or none at all, in the vast philosophical literature on the morality of war.Footnote 195 To date, no comprehensive ethics of war inquiry has been undertaken into the harsh effects of this predominant type of warfare on the natural environment.
Accordingly, this section focuses the ‘environmental ethics of war’ on civil conflict. Subsection 3.1 surveys the limited extent of international law of armed conflict applicable to civil strife, which is mostly lacking in its protection of the natural environment during NIAC. Subsection 3.2 elaborates on the overlap between conflict and biodiverse regions, as well as on the environmental hazards arising specifically from civil conflicts and in their aftermath. Subsection 3.3 sketches initial ethical guidelines for environmental protection in civil war and compares them with existing legal restrictions in international armed conflict.
Two caveats: first, for present purposes, ‘civil war’ refers loosely to all forms of domestic warfare – NIAC – occurring within a single state and among its members, with or without foreign intervention. In this sense, the common term ‘civil war’ is something of a misnomer, shorthand for the more encompassing but cumbersome technical term ‘intrastate armed conflict’. Second, admittedly, beyond pure theory, any ‘environmental philosophy of war’, particularly for civil conflicts, is likely to inform international forces and institutions and influence guidelines for intervening armies, long before it applies directly to internal warring parties.
3.1 Environmental Law Applicable to NIAC
Only a small part of humanitarian law applies to NIAC. The laws that apply to NIAC – those laid down in Article 3 common to the Geneva Conventions (1949) and, more recently, Protocol II (1977) – aim to uphold civilian immunity and the rights of the sick and wounded, as well as to prohibit torture and further excesses in wartime.Footnote 196 They do not apply the full set of laws in bello applicable within international armed conflicts to non-international strife.
Lawyers note the limitations of the law applicable to NIAC, both with reference to overall deficiencies in Protocol IIFootnote 197 and regarding environmental preservation specifically.Footnote 198 Designed for irregular forces or for regular forces fighting irregulars inside their own country, Protocol II sets up only minimal guarantees that do not include environmental provisions comparable to Additional Protocol I, while the 1977 Environmental Modification Techniques Convention (ENMOD) applies without prejudice to all types of conflict but is extremely narrow in scope, applying only to manipulation (‘modification’) of the environment.Footnote 199 The only indirectly relevant Protocol II provisions are Article 14 – protecting objects indispensable for the survival of the civilian population (agricultural areas, crops, livestock, drinking water installations, and irrigation works) – and possibly Article 15, which protects works and installations containing dangerous forces.Footnote 200
Nonetheless, there is an emerging readiness on the part of major states and international forces to factor environmental concerns into the calculus of the military, and to apply the higher standards of international armed conflict, including their environmental aspects, to NIAC as well.Footnote 201 It is not always easy to clearly distinguish international from NIAC, particularly where international and foreign forces are involved; this is an additional reason to apply the same legal regime to all cases.Footnote 202 Here, again, the general law of war principles and standards, necessity and proportionality, may have a further bearing on environmental protection in all types of armed conflict.Footnote 203 The continuing relevance of domestic environmental law is particularly pertinent in the case of internal strife, where the distinction between armed conflict and civil disturbances is less stark.Footnote 204
Lawyers concerned with protecting the environment during NIAC concentrate on arguments and mechanisms for extending environmental protection in international wars (as well as peacetime regulation) to internal armed conflicts.Footnote 205 Advocating criminal liability for environmental damage in civil wars, Carl Bruch notes that ‘While not directly applicable to internal conflicts, the norms applicable to international armed conflict constitute the most developed framework for constraining environmental damage from armed conflict’.Footnote 206 The virtually non-existent environmental regulation of NIAC prompts us to build on existing understandings, in ethics as well as law. The penultimate part of this section asks whether civil conflicts and insurgencies are morally subject to different environmental burdens or permissions at the bar of jus in bello from those that apply (or ought to apply) in traditional interstate wars.Footnote 207
3.2 Civil Wars
To recap: civil wars are under-regulated – both generally and regarding the natural environment in particular – and their level of adherence to existing law is inferior. Armed conflict in the post-World War II era has been mostly intra-national, with over 80 per cent of such warfare between 1950 and 2000 occurring within biodiversity hotspots.Footnote 208 Both these features of contemporary conflict as well as their overlap have been largely overlooked by just war theorists, though less so in empirical studies. While hotspots represent less than 2 per cent of the earth’s land, they support about half of the world’s plants and many rare species.Footnote 209
Internal conflict and its aftermath are a major cause of deforestation, with considerable impact on biodiversity. Northern and Central Ethiopia, for example, have lost most of their tree cover through civil war.Footnote 210 Other prominent examples include the Great War of Africa in the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC), where over a five-year period civil war caused as much as a 1.61 per cent loss of forests (in both battle and non-battle zones), more than the entire territory of Belgium and nearly half that of Sierra Leone.Footnote 211
Counter-insurgency, for its part, may require deforestation in conflict areas in order to eliminate insurgent hideouts (e.g. Turkish forces deliberately set fire to forests to reduce cover for Kurdish forces in their ongoing conflict with the PKK).Footnote 212 All warring parties have an incentive to mobilize resources such as timber, cutting down trees alongside exploitation of other natural supplies.Footnote 213 Abundant examples include ‘rampant trade in “conflict” timber and diamonds during civil wars in Liberia, Sierra Leone, and elsewhere’.Footnote 214
Displaced populations require resources for their survival during and after hostilities by ‘living off the land’ – poaching, foraging, looting, etc. – as do guerrilla forces.Footnote 215 In the DRC, conflict wiped out 95 per cent of hippos, as their habitats were destroyed and the animals could not be protected from poachers.Footnote 216 Nature reserves and national parks have been used for grazing, house-building, and hunting.Footnote 217 By the mid–late 1990s, ‘An estimated 850,000 refugees from the Rwandan civil war were living in or around Virunga National Park’ – Africa’s most biodiverse protected area (in Zaire/DRC) – cutting down trees for wood, leading to massive environmental degradation, specifically deforestation.Footnote 218 After a decade of war and civil unrest, aerial surveys of the park ‘found 629 hippopotami from a population that once exceeded 30,000 animals’.Footnote 219 Demand for firewood, charcoal, and building materials has led to similar land degradation and losses of forest and woodland around settlements of internally displaced Darfuris in Sudan, Somali refugees in Kenya, and Afghan refugees in Pakistan.Footnote 220
War-related forest loss in Nicaragua, Columbia, as well as DRC and along the South Sudan–Uganda border, is attributed primarily to such changes in human settlement and activity patterns.Footnote 221 In Rwanda, the south-eastern portion of the Nyungwe montane forest – dominated by bamboo and home to the owl-faced monkey – as well as other biodiverse mountain forests were largely cleared for agriculture.Footnote 222 While depopulation of conflict zones may have beneficial environmental effects, such as an increase in wildlife and reforestation, it is often counterbalanced by increased activity elsewhere, so that the overall consequences of armed conflict for biodiversity remain overwhelmingly negative.Footnote 223 Moreover, ‘Some post war biodiversity impacts represent a straightforward continuation of effects begun during wartime, such as persistent deforestation near long-term refugee camps’.Footnote 224
In all cases, the anthropogenic perspective, military necessity, and immediate human needs overshadow environmental considerations. Lack of environmental concern in the face of military imperatives and the importance of winning is particularly crucial in less-developed countries, particularly in Africa, where people are more dependent on natural resources,Footnote 225 and where losing may entail unforgiving repercussions. Developing nations are also more likely to experience internal conflict, as has been the case in Mozambique, Angola, Somalia, DRC, Sierra Leone, and Rwanda, conducted more frequently and less lawlessly than international wars, as well as more often within environmentally sensitive regions.Footnote 226
In Rwanda specifically, as well as Darfur, Cambodia, and Sierra Leone, humanitarian tragedy not only takes priority over environmental issues but renders their mention slightly obscene. Notwithstanding, there is a growing realization that preserving the natural environment is also an urgent human interest, albeit in the longer term.Footnote 227 Moreover, as we have seen, often human and non-human concerns go hand in hand as the humanitarian crises accompanying and succeeding wars, including those involving refugees and displaced persons, can also have devastating impacts on wildlife and natural resources.Footnote 228
Any practicable moral rules for protecting the natural environment in armed conflict – international and internal – require a delicate balance between multiple in bello and post bellum perspectives, recommending once again a moderate, conservative, all-encompassing approach. NIAC specifically raises unique challenges for balancing human and non-human interests and vulnerabilities, generating special responsibilities towards civilians and their natural surroundings.
3.3 Protecting the Natural Environment in Civil Conflict
Several distinct features of civil conflict suggest special moral obligations on the part of the warring parties towards the natural environment, as well as more general universal responsibilities on the part of combatants generally, including local and intervening forces.
First and foremost, as noted repeatedly, is their location: most civil wars take place within a tiny portion of the earth’s land surface, typically rich in vertebrate life, containing rare species and (according to the Red CrossFootnote 229) approximately 50 per cent of the world’s plant life. In other words, they overlap to a very large extent with biodiversity hotspots. Moreover, civil wars often take place on territories rich in useful natural resources.
Moving on to participants, internal wars are fought between two or more parties within a state, all of whom bear special responsibilities towards that state’s inhabitants, territory, and territorial resources. It is widely accepted that governments have protective duties towards their own population, whom they are sworn to protect. Writing of civil war, Vattel pointed out that
we must, in the first place, recollect that all the sovereign’s rights are derived from those of the state or of civil society, from the trust reposed in him, from the obligation he lies under of watching over the welfare of the nation, of procuring her greatest happiness, of maintaining order, justice, and peace within her boundaries.Footnote 230
Rebels and freedom fighters also have special obligations towards members of the population they profess to be fighting for, as well as for their own homeland terrain, beyond general duties to refrain from harming civilians and their environment. Like governments, rebels derive any legitimacy they may have from the welfare of their people. Regardless of national partiality, rebels are responsible for their civilian co-nationals because they claim to act for them and in their name. This presumably includes due care for their natural surroundings and the resources necessary for their survival and well-being.
In reality, civilians caught up in local conflict are often abandoned by both rebels and sovereigns, remaining utterly defenceless, as well as emotionally forsaken by friends and relatives who find themselves in opposing camps. Whereas governments engaged in international wars aim to protect their civilian population and distance the fighting from the home front, civil wars, by stark contrast, take place mostly among civilians within their environment, by parties concerned primarily with victory at all costs.
As for deleterious consequences, civil conflict typically lasts longer than interstate wars, with a higher level of devastation to civilians and their natural surroundings.Footnote 231 Fought typically to the bitter end rather than concluding in negotiated settlement,Footnote 232 local wars and their harmful effects are also likely to recur within the first decade after their conclusion.Footnote 233 Crucially, rebellions, revolutions, and insurgencies are fought mostly unconventionally,Footnote 234 adding costs to civilian environments, with guerrillas typically living amidst civilians and subsisting off the land.Footnote 235
Civil wars, we have seen, are fought mostly outside any structure of rules, let alone any concern for the natural surroundings in which they are conducted. As noted, the extremely basic anthropocentric guidelines for protecting the environment set out in Protocol I do not apply to civil conflict, and even the humanitarian rudiments of Common Article 3 and Protocol II are largely ignored. Nonetheless, accounting for special relationships as well as location, a traditional military ethics perspective with an eye to the future suggests that civil wars ought to be subject to standards of environmental protection that are at least similar to, if not higher than, those of international armed conflict.
Conversely, Cecile Fabre argues that in the case of a just insurgency local civilians may be particularly liable to collateral harm because they are the potential beneficiaries of the war.Footnote 236 This would presumably include incidental damage to their natural environment. Moreover, rebels are typically disadvantaged in terms of weaponry and military resources, possibly justifying greater liberties on the part of the weaker side.Footnote 237
At least from a revisionist perspective, when insurgents have a just cause they may conceivably be subject to a lower standard of jus in bello regulations, giving them a fighting chance against injustice.Footnote 238 Philosophically, revisionist theorists might argue that bona fide resistance movements can justify unavoidable harm to the environment by reference to the objective justness of their cause combined with the military asymmetry of the conflict and the potential benefit of victory to local inhabitants. Fending off genocide, to take the extreme example, would clearly generate such extra licence on all existing accounts of (anthropocentric) JWT.Footnote 239 Any other conclusion, favouring nature over human life, would far exceed overlapping consensus as advocated in Section 1.
In many other cases, however, difficulties in establishing objective and absolute justice on one side or another, particularly in complex multi-party internal conflicts, as well as the prospect of enforcing it on the warring factions, may preclude the possibility of deriving any useful rules of conduct from such deep moral insight.
Intrastate wars being what and where they are, any environmental requirements will, at most, set standards and command respect from international organizations and intervening forces and guide oversight and post-war accountability, rather than effectively enforcing first-order rules on the warring parties themselves, whether just or unjust. This is, nonetheless, no small achievement. Advocating the conduct towards the environment displayed by intervening forces in former Yugoslavia as a future model, US Colonel James Burger argues for equal application of environmental rules to all situations.Footnote 240 The presence of international peacekeeping forces challenges the distinction between intranational and international conflict, as well as between wartime and peacetime environmental rules. Moreover, intervening forces are out there to protect, and therefore bear a particularly heavy burden of obligation to refrain from making matters worse. At the same time, they often face considerable challenges, which brought on their intervention to begin with, in protecting human life, even at a cost to the environment.
Overall, the variety of exceptional circumstances listed above imply that combatants engaged in civil conflict – both local and foreign – albeit facing unique hardships, nonetheless shoulder a particularly high level of environmental responsibility. This holds not only for non-anthropocentric environmental ethics that attach intrinsic value to the environment (its life forms or ecology) but also from a human-centred perspective, attributing instrumental value to the environment in terms of utility. The law of war protects the natural environment not only because of its intrinsic value but because it sustains human life.Footnote 241
Locals, both governments and rebels, have fiduciary duties of care towards the population whom they purport to represent and propose to govern, which must include their natural surroundings and resources – present and future – and natural objects for their survival and well-being. From a non-cosmopolitan perspective, both insurgents and soldiers also have special obligations stemming from national affiliation and partiality towards fellow citizens and their homeland terrain.
Universal obligations command everyone to pay special attention to biodiversity conservation in armed conflict, particularly in biologically rich regions. Intervening parties are better informed and equipped to recognize and follow environmental rules.Footnote 242 Their very presence calls into question the distinction between NIAC and international wars, suggesting the applicability of Protocol I standards. Peacekeeping forces, as well as the necessarily continuous demands of care for the natural environment, blur the distinction between wartime and peacetime rules. Revisionist philosophers of war reject such distinctions in any event.Footnote 243
3.4 Concluding Remarks
Just war theory and the morality of war have been applied far less to internal armed conflict than to conventional wars between states, as well as devoting very little attention to the environmental aspect of armed conflict. The two deficiencies overlap. Non-international armed conflict has long become the norm for warfare rather than the exception, with considerable consequences for the natural environment, for example in Angola, Cambodia, and Colombia.Footnote 244 These concerns are brought together in the geographical overlap between internal armed conflict and areas with high biological richness and limited extent.Footnote 245 At the same time, existing international law provides only a few environmental protections during internal armed conflicts.Footnote 246
The more developed law of international armed conflict is morally instructive but not definitive. Civil wars are different in several respects from international conflicts, and these differences may have a moral bearing on their regulation. Considering the demands of justice regarding the environment specifically in intrastate as opposed to interstate wars suggests an equal, if not higher, responsibility to protect in the case of NIAC.
On a practical note, given the nature of civil conflicts and their participants, it is hard enough to impose minimal humanitarian standards, let alone enforce environmental regulations. Any emerging guidelines and rules of engagement in this field are more likely to inform intervening forces and instruct international institutions – both common to NIAC – than to apply directly as first-order rules to warring factions, at least for the foreseeable future.Footnote 247
4 Environmental Terrorism
Environmental disruption and degradation are old features of war, but the term ‘environmental terrorism’ is relatively new, dating back to the Persian Gulf War oil spills and subsequent fires in Kuwaiti oil fields.Footnote 248 Academic interest in terrorism surfaced mostly after 9/11, with notable late twentieth-century exceptions.Footnote 249 The increase in environmental awareness is more recent still.
This section examines the relatively novel and ambiguous term ‘environmental terrorism’, combining insights from both terrorism scholarship and environmental politics, ultimately drawing lessons for the here and now. Subsection 4.1 considers the definitions of terrorism more generally and argues that a useful characterization will indicate why terrorism is wrong. Following Michael Walzer, I suggest that terrorism is the intentional murder of random civilians for political purposes.Footnote 250 Subsection 4.2 considers various distinct meanings of ‘environmental terrorism’ in particular. Subsequently, Subsection 4.3 asks whether the natural world can fully qualify as a victim of terrorism. In keeping with the rejection of ‘environmental non-combatant immunity’ in Subsection 1.3, this subsection argues that, absent human targets, deliberately destroying nature does not in itself meet the requirements of ‘terrorism’. Finally, Subsection 4.4 asks what would constitute an appropriate and proportionate response to ‘environmental terrorism’.
One timely example comes from the Gaza Strip. On 30 March 2018, protesters in Gaza instigated a civil resistance campaign along the border with Israel. Following these border disturbances, Gazans launched countless kites, and (as of May 2018) party balloons and inflated latex condoms bearing flammable materials and explosives – grenades, Molotov cocktails, etc. – into Israeli territory. Though these attacks never resulted in Israeli fatalities, they sparked fires burning thousands of acres of farmland, parks, forests, and nature reserves, killing animals, destroying beehives, wildlife and natural habitats, and wreaking ecological devastation in the Western Negev with long-term environmental ramifications.Footnote 251 On one occasion, a burning falcon outfitted with a harness carrying flaming material was propelled from Gaza into Israel.Footnote 252 In June 2018, kites from Gaza destroyed vast parts of the Carmia nature reserve inside Israel, causing massive damage.Footnote 253
Continuing seasonally into 2021, and recurring in Fall 2023 (a mere two weeks before the October 7 massacre), airborne arson attacks caused economic and psychological harm, spread fear, and disrupted daily life.Footnote 254 Many of the incendiary devices found inside Israel were coloured as party balloons with cartoon decorations, apparently aimed at attracting children;Footnote 255 some fell in residential areas and within family homes.Footnote 256 Israel dubbed these attacks ‘balloon terrorism’, ‘terror kites’ and ‘arson terror’, exploring the legality and expediency of various counter-terrorism measures in response.Footnote 257
Terrorism is a contested concept, associated primarily with the murder and maiming of civilians; its applicability to environmental destruction is far from obvious. The following subsection argues that the term ‘terrorism’ is partly rhetorical in environmental contexts. Acts of hostility directed exclusively at non-human elements of the natural world may not in and of themselves constitute terrorism. In principle, this section suggests, the moral condemnation of terrorism ought rightly to be reserved for the indiscriminate targeting of human non-combatants. At the same time, the severity of environmental harm should not be understated. Attacking the natural environment during armed conflict is arguably a war crime. Moreover, in reality, hostile acts against nature may go so far towards threatening civilians as to constitute bona fide terrorism, as well as going hand in glove with attacking non-combatants more directly.
4.1 What Is Terrorism and What Is Wrong with It?
Terrorism has countless definitions, each with its own objective and agenda. There are by now equally numerous remarks to this effect, especially since 9/11. There is to date no canonical, universally agreed definition of terrorism, whether legally, philosophically, or in ordinary usage. It has become almost commonplace to suggest that definition is impossible and redundant – ‘we know it when we see it’ – or sectarian – ‘one man’s terrorist is another’s freedom fighter’ – or meaningful only within specific fields (law, finance, sociology) for specific purposes.Footnote 258 Others propose ‘neutral objective’ all-encompassing definitions that include various forms of political violence and a mixture of historical cases, concluding effectively that terrorism is in the eye of the beholder.Footnote 259
Various features are typically listed in association with terrorism, notably its theatrical–media element and audience,Footnote 260 illegality, targeting civilians, ‘weapon of the weak’,Footnote 261 political goals, causing fear and panic. But terrorism scholars differ, and often remain undecided, regarding any necessary and sufficient conditions. The broadest ‘non-biased’ definitions of terrorism include various forms of illegal political violence that fall short of war,Footnote 262 the terrorizing acts of states in war, as well as ‘state terrorism’ towards the states’ own citizenryFootnote 263 or enemy civilians. Others add institutional ‘structural violence’, often associated with capitalism and globalization.Footnote 264
These inclusive definitions do not necessarily condemn ‘terrorism’ as such, encompassing a wide mixture of historical cases – ranging from American and French revolutionaries to the Maquis, Irgun and Stern Gang, the atomic bombs on Japan, structural inequality, Bush and Blair, Hamas, and ISIS. Such theorists take pride in objectivity, criticizing stricter definitions for building ‘a judgment of immorality, or non-justifiability into the definition of terrorism, making it impossible even to question whether given acts of terrorism might be justified’.Footnote 265
Evaluating the changing character of war and terrorism, as well as appropriate counter-measures, requires clearer insight. It is, Aristotle teaches, our capacity to distinguish and define which enables us to make ethical judgments.Footnote 266 As Tony Coady puts it: ‘There are two central philosophical questions about terrorism: What is it? And what, if anything, is wrong with it? Here I propose to deal with the first question, but I do so because of the importance of the second.’Footnote 267
Terrorism is a pejorative term. In keeping with common usage, a good definition will indicate what is wrong with terrorism, and strictly specify which new incidents fall within this derogatory category and which do not. ‘Environmental terrorism’ is a paradigm case in point. While the broadest definitions may charitably include harm to the environment under the rubric of terrorism, they will not necessarily attach any negative judgement to this label and cannot teach us much about its normative implications.
Michael Walzer’s critical understanding of terrorism in his seminal Just and Unjust Wars provides the classic definition, which has become the term of reference for practically every discussion on terrorism. According to Walzer, ‘terrorism’ is the random killing of innocent people, generating pervasive fear for a variety of political purposes.Footnote 268 Killing non-combatants at random is a crucial element, referring both to the violation of civilian immunity and to the total disregard for the identity of the victim.Footnote 269 Randomness sets terrorism apart from milder forms of political violence – guerrilla warfare directed at armies and political assassination aimed at state officials.Footnote 270 Attacking anyone within a political community, rather than selected individuals, Walzer explains, not only increases fear but also delivers a devaluating, uncompromising message of rejection to an entire group: ‘We don’t want you here’.Footnote 271 Hamas’s indiscriminate onslaught on October 7, conveying the message ‘from the river to the sea’, is a gruesomely clear example.
Walzer’s censorious depiction of terrorism as the terrifying random murder of innocent civilians for political gain is echoed in countless modern works.Footnote 272 Most authors also include fear – literal terrorization – in their definitions of terrorism. Tied at the philological level to the term itself, this basic feature – intended and resulting fear – cuts across political lines and is included in the widest variety of discussions on terrorism.Footnote 273 Moreover, Jurgan Habermas noted after 9/11, terrorism (as opposed to paramilitary guerrilla tactics) ‘revolves around murder, around the indiscriminate annihilation of enemies, women and children – life against life’, and can never be legitimized.Footnote 274
No doubt, Walzer acknowledges, ‘the use of the term is contested; that’s true of many political terms. The use of “democracy” is contested, but we still have, I think, a pretty good idea of what democracy is. … The case is the same with terrorism.’Footnote 275 Terrorism is essentially about targeting random non-combatants, along with anyone else, instilling pervasive fear in civilians as a means to political ends. This basic understanding allows for variation and has some fuzzy edges, but it is, at the very least, its core content.
It remains to be seen whether environmental destruction can qualify as terrorism in this sense: under what conditions, and to what degree, it shares the normative shortcomings of terror, as well as how to respond. I begin with what is wrong with terrorism in the narrow sense defined in this subsection .
Terrorism, Walzer and Habermas maintain, devalues entire nations or classes, and attacks the defenceless among them, violating the most basic rule of the just war tradition.Footnote 276 Beyond conventions of war, terrorism defies a key standard of liberal humanist morality, at least from Kant through Rawls, which fundamentally forbids the use of human beings as means only, and prescribes their treatment as ends in themselves.Footnote 277 It also violates an older cross-cultural commitment to protect the defenceless and vulnerable, those who are not trained to fight or cannot fight, namely women, children, clergymen, and elderly people, who are disengaged from military activity.Footnote 278
Terrorism is also a form of free riding. ‘Terrorism of the weak’ relies on conventional armies observing traditional rules of war, while the terrorists themselves thwart them. If their stronger adversaries were to match the terrorists’ nihilism by denying civilian immunity, choosing to terrorize the latter with their superior force, they would once again have the upper hand, rendering ineffective the smaller-scale terrorism of the ‘underdog’. Terrorism wholly depends upon its opponents upholding a moral code that the terrorists themselves reject. Terrorists also rely on a set of civil liberties, which they often hold in contempt, but which enables them to operate more freely than they could in their absence. Terrorism’s very effectiveness depends on a reversal of the Kantian imperative to ‘act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law’.Footnote 279
Regardless of its professed cause, terrorism in the strict sense – murdering random civilians as a political strategy – is diametrically opposed to the requirements of liberal morality and is defensible only at the cost of relinquishing the most basic of liberal commitments. None of this condemnation applies to attacks on natural resources and environmental destruction for political gain.
4.2 Environmental Terrorism: Assorted Meanings
The most obvious difference between traditional terrorism and ‘environmental terrorism’ specifically is that the former is aimed directly at human beings, whereas the latter targets other inhabitants of the natural world, addressing and affecting humans only indirectly and with varying degrees of severity. Typical examples include the destruction of forests and agricultural sites by fire. ‘Dry weather conditions can make forests, fields, and grasslands more susceptible to fire’ and hence make them a prime target with potentially devastating economic and environmental consequences.Footnote 280 The fires sparked by Hamas’s arson attacks in the Israeli South between 2018 and 2023 are cases in point. Attacks aimed specifically at the agricultural sector are often classified as ‘agro-terrorism’, alongside the use of biological agents against domestic animals and crops.Footnote 281
In contrast to the post-9/11 surge in terrorism scholarship, the relevant literature on its environmental brand is relatively scant and scattered across various academic fields, from law to political science, geopolitics, and environmental ethics. Several clarifications are in order, regardless of discipline.
First, environmental terrorism is distinct from ‘eco-terrorism’ – violence carried out to further ecological causes – though the labels are occasionally used interchangeably.Footnote 282 For eco-terrorists advancing an environmentalist agenda, the environment is an objective (e.g. saving the planet) rather than a target.Footnote 283 Examples include militant environmental groups such as the Earth Liberation Front (ELF) and its sister organization the Animal Liberation Front (ALF), believed to be responsible for some 600 criminal acts between 1996 and 2002.Footnote 284 Illegal violence notwithstanding, much ‘eco-terrorism’ does not maim or kill, often aiming instead at property considered ecologically detrimental; its classification as ‘terrorism’ rather than sabotage (or ‘ecotage’) is therefore debatable.Footnote 285
As opposed to ‘eco-terrorism’, ‘environmental terrorism’ more often refers to the deliberate destruction or manipulation of the natural environment in the name of political or ideological zealotry.Footnote 286 Like environmental warfare, environmental terrorism involves attacking or utilizing the forces of nature for hostile purposes.Footnote 287 This includes targeting natural resources directly, such as by incendiary means, as well as harnessing elements of the environment itself as tools of war or terror.Footnote 288 An example of the latter is the means and methods of warfare prohibited by the 1977 Environmental Modification Techniques Convention (ENMOD), which bars using the environment itself (changing or manipulating natural processes, such as the weather) as a weapon. Biological and chemical warfare is another example of harnessing elements of the environment for hostile purposes.Footnote 289
Similarly, the environment can be, and has been, harnessed as a conduit of attack – a delivery vehicle carrying destruction to a human population – such as the poisoning of water supplies.Footnote 290 Other times, ‘the environment or resources themselves are targeted for destruction or compromise, with the collateral damage being felt by the population the terrorists wish to impact’.Footnote 291 In the former we might say the environment is a casualty, whereas in the latter the casualty is the directly targeted victim.Footnote 292
Offering an eight-pronged taxonomy of environmental destruction, Daniel Schwartz suggests we reserve the term ‘environmental terrorism’ only for those acts of violence in which the deliberate manipulation of the environment is intended to instil trepidation in the larger population, specifically from the ecological consequences of the act.Footnote 293 This excludes unintended environmental damage and wanton vandalism, but also the most deliberate harnessing of natural resources for terroristic purposes. On this account, terroristic manipulation of nuclear, biological, or chemical materials (e.g. the use of nerve gas in the Tokyo subway) would not count as environmental terrorism because the perpetrators do not primarily intend to instil fear of the specifically ecological consequences of their act. In these cases, Schwartz argues, the environment is merely a casualty rather than a victim. The same goes for the purposeful wartime destruction of resources, such as scorched-earth policies, and even ‘ecocide’ – substantially damaging/destroying ecosystems – where the environmental destruction is strategic rather than symbolic, as the perpetrator is not attempting to create fear of the environmental consequences of the act, but is rather using the environment strategically to further other political ends.Footnote 294 On this account, Saddam Hussein’s ecological destruction during the Persian Gulf War would not, contra President Bush’s labelling, count as state terrorism because ‘the Iraqi leader never issued an ecological threat and never “held the environment hostage’’’.Footnote 295
Quite narrowly construed, Schwartz’s single example of ‘environmental terrorism’ is a 1995 incident in which a group of disgruntled fishermen on the Galapagos Islands – unhappy about an imposed limit on the lucrative trade of sea cucumber harvesting – threatened, tortured, and killed 81 of the islands’ rare tortoises.Footnote 296 Only this type of unlawfulness, Schwartz concludes, in war/peacetime, constitutes environmental terrorism stricto sensu ‘because it is only in these scenarios that a perpetrator attempts to instil fear in the larger population over the ecological consequences of their destruction. In such cases the environment is the primary symbol, and ecology is a victim rather than a casualty.’Footnote 297
More commonly, the label ‘environmental terrorism’ refers to all military or paramilitary violence that intentionally utilizes or targets natural resources to attain any political ends. This includes deliberate environmental destruction employed as a tactic to pressure governments or their citizenry to make political concessions, to seek retaliation for propaganda purposes, to attract attention to a political cause, or to convey a ‘theatrical’ message to one’s enemy, fellow nationals, or the world at large. In environmental attacks, elements of the non-human world – be they forests, fields, rivers, or whatever form they take – are the direct victims of hostilities, though the ultimate political target remains humans. Whether such acts destroy resources or use them as a channel of attack, they may serve to symbolize the perpetrator’s grievance, to instil fear in a civilian population, to intimidate the enemy into capitulation, to raise awareness to the assailants’ political agenda, or to enlist supporters and activists to their cause. Groups such as ISIS in Syria and Iraq, for example, have ‘shown their capacity to leverage the environment, by targeting water resources as tools to manipulate the population’.Footnote 298
Several scholars suggest that existing legal doctrines ‘fail to adequately respond to the specific threat of environmental terrorism’.Footnote 299 In the context of armed conflict, existing Geneva conventions prohibit intentionally targeting natural resources unless there is a direct military advantage to doing so.Footnote 300 As noted in Section 1, this is clearly far weaker than the absolute prohibition of intentionally attacking civilians, which holds regardless of military advantage.Footnote 301 Nevertheless, terrorism is by definition indiscriminate violence, and ‘because it is directed at a symbolic target, does not create an immediate military advantage for the attacker’.Footnote 302 Absent a direct military advantage, does targeting natural resources for indirect or symbolic purposes – such as to intimidate, coerce, or convey a political message – constitute terrorism?
Sometimes this question lacks practical significance, as when hostilities target civilians and their environment or destroy valuable or scarce resources, or when environmental damage severely prejudices civilian well-being and livelihood in violation of Additional Protocol I, Article 55.Footnote 303 These cases violate human civilian immunities rather than purely environmental interests. Consider resource destruction that also leads quite directly to loss of human life,Footnote 304 deliberately targets civilians within their environment, or causes arguably disproportionate long-term harm. In Kuwait, for example, ‘The oil fires also signified a more menacing threat: their lasting impact on the environment and population of the region’.Footnote 305
In the case of Gaza, Israel’s resort to terrorism discourse to describe the fires emanating from the Strip is largely justified. Though there were no human casualties in the incendiary attacks, the aerial explosives from Gaza were equally designed to target random civilians, and some did in fact land in educational institutions, including the yard of a preschool facility, and in private houses causing property damage.Footnote 306 Dressing airborne explosive devices as children’s toys indicates a clear intent to injure. Gazan activists evidently had no qualms about harming both natural resources and non-combatants within a single operation. When they ignited a field, if a couple of children had turned up to collect a colourful inflammatory kite or pick up an explosive party balloon, terrorists would not view this as a fly in the ointment or unfortunate collateral damage, but rather as a well sought-after added bonus.Footnote 307 Terrorism is indiscriminate in this sense as well: it is indifferent to the nature of its victim.
In principle, however, does targeting natural resources exclusively – to convey a message of fear, gain attention or political objectives, oppose oppression, or rally support – tick all the boxes of ‘terrorism’? As noted in Section 1, the natural environment shares several features frequently associated with the victims of terror, among them the vulnerability of non-combatants and a lack of direct involvement in combat – connecting immunity from attack with military disengagement.
Nature is usually a non-military target, and attacking it often involves the destruction of civilian assets – both private and public. With growing environmental awareness, such attacks have increasing potential to cause fear and panic and attract public media attention to a particular cause.Footnote 308 In terms of ‘violence as communication’Footnote 309 – theatre and conveying a message for political gain – as well as illegality, attacking the natural environment scores highly in its resemblance to hard-core terrorism.Footnote 310 As for potential harm, Timothy Schofield notes that ‘Killing the horticulture of an ecosystem [notably by incendiary means] … can cause substantial damage to that system’s wildlife and topsoil. Recovery from such ecological damage could take decades.’Footnote 311 In terms of range and ‘ongoing-ness’, environmental damage scores higher than most terrorist attacks.
The question remains: ‘If a bomb goes off in a forest and there is no one there to lose a view or to suffer collateral damage, is it terrorism? This raises questions of how and by whom the environment is valued, and on what time scale these values are identified.’Footnote 312
4.3 Targeting Nature
Ethical evaluation of ‘environmental terrorism’ invariably intertwines not only with the controversial terrorism scholarship discussed above, but also with the variety in ethics of the environment, as discussed in Section 1. Absent human targets, does an assault on the natural world carry the negative normative baggage associated with ‘terrorism’? This depends not only on our definition of terrorism but again on our classification of the non-human victim as compared with the human non-combatants most often identified as the targets of terror.
Critiquing ‘environmental terrorism’, Shannon O’Lear notes, regarding legal definitions, that targets of terrorism typically consist of non-combatants.Footnote 313 ‘Considering the role the environment might have in this definition of terrorism, environmental areas or resources such as forests, water supplies, national parks, etc. would fall under the category of “noncombatant targets” and could be involved in terrorist activity in ways that would “influence an audience’’.’Footnote 314
Similarly, Elizabeth Chalecki argues ostensibly that ‘Terrorism clearly violates the jus in bello criterion, since targeting non-combatants lies at the very core of its strategy. That the target is environmental and not human does not blur the distinction between warfare and terrorism.’Footnote 315 At the same time, she notes that prohibitions on intentionally attacking the environment are subject to military necessity.Footnote 316 This is patently not the case with jus in bello concerning human civilian immunity, which applies absolutely.
On Chalecki’s account, deliberately burning forests or fields, setting a nature reserve ablaze, killing animals, destroying natural habitats, and so forth for political purposes, all target ‘non-combatants’, violating their immunity, and would ipso facto probably constitute acts of terrorism.
Can the environment count as a non-combatant, warranting its absolute protection on a par with civilian immunity, and labelling its violation as ‘terrorism’? Adopted categorically, environmental non-combatant immunity would preclude not only wanton destruction but also absolutely any direct attacks on, or use of, the environment in wartime. Section 1 argued against extending non-combatant status to the environment as untenable for the law of armed conflict, while emphasizing its prima facie protection from direct attack, subject to military necessity, and the strong significance of environmental damage in determining proportionality.Footnote 317 This, however, remains a far cry from automatically branding purely environmental destruction as a violation of non-combatant immunity or genuine acts of terror.
One danger of the ‘environmental terrorism’ label is the risk of over-zealous environmentalism belittling the value of human life. Regarding acts that target humans within their environment or affect them profoundly, Schwartz warns that ‘To label this act “environmental terrorism” might serve to elevate ecological concerns over concerns of human life. Although the ecological destruction might ultimately threaten human life, there is a danger in elevating the importance of this eventuality over the immediate loss of human life.’Footnote 318 Similarly, classifying purely environmental attacks as ‘terrorism’ runs the same risk of depreciating the value of human individuals, equating them with natural resources. One does not need to be an overly human-centred moral philosopher to note the difference between on the one hand killing or kidnapping children, or dismembering and butchering civilians, and on the other hand attacking a tree or a fossil formation, destroying a beehive, or arguably even abusing and killing a falcon or 81 rare tortoises.
From a liberal perspective, nothing like a Walzerian absolute anti-terrorism stance is applicable to flora and fauna, or even animals. For Kant (and Rawls) certainly, the categorical prohibition on using human beings as means only, prescribing their treatment as ends in themselves, does not extend to non-human inhabitants of the natural world.Footnote 319 Only human individuals are ends in themselves, everything else has its price, as is well reflected in the subjection in international law of environmental interdictions to military necessity. Even utilitarian defenders of animal rights need not attribute equal worth to humans and all other animals.Footnote 320
Of course, all this may just beg the question from an anthropocentric stance, or at least a very inegalitarian bio-centric account. Some non-anthropocentric theorists construct deontological moral arguments that attribute inherent worth (intrinsic value), in whole or part, to non-human elements of the natural worldFootnote 321 – an ‘objective good-of-their-own’Footnote 322 – while many others reject this moral framework altogether, attributing intrinsic value to animals and ecosystems for very different reasons.Footnote 323 Perhaps we have reached a dead end. The concept of terrorism as we know it from Maximillian Robespierre, from 9/11 to October 7, is admittedly human-centred. As is also its categorical condemnation from a liberal ‘humanistic’ perspective and even its defence by Western apologists of terrorism.Footnote 324 In this context, so called ‘environmental terrorism’ runs the risk of abusing the concept of terrorism for rhetorical purposes, discrediting the absoluteness of the liberal prohibition on terror as well as the reasons for it that attach specifically to the value of human life, imago Dei, and the inherent worth of individual human persons.
4.4 Appropriate Response: The Case of Gaza and Beyond
Terrorism or no terrorism, no state can tolerate violent attacks on its territory and natural resources, alongside the property and ecological losses that accompany both. Regarding the natural environment per se, occasionally referred to as war’s ‘forgotten victim’, some lawyers support a Fifth Geneva Convention on the Protection of the Environment in Time of Armed Conflict.Footnote 325 Others propose the criminalization of ‘ecocide’, either domestically – specifically referring to ‘environmental terrorism’Footnote 326 – or more recently as an international war crime.Footnote 327 Any of this might go part way towards remedying current inadequacies of legal protections, and expressly condemn the environmental nature of the crime.Footnote 328 Legal channels are, however, unlikely to offer immediate practical relief to nations suffering environmental assault.
What unilateral military measures might a state legitimately resort to in order to fend off environmental attacks? This question was hotly debated in connection with the inflammatory kites and balloons from Gaza. As with ‘environmental terrorism’ more generally, formulating appropriate and effective responses to this new threat was not easy.Footnote 329 Two key issues applied to the particularities of the Gaza case. The first concerned the overall legal framework of the arson attacks (armed conflict governed by international humanitarian law, or domestic law enforcement). The second questioned the legal status of the incendiary weapons launchers: were they in fact Hamas operatives or independent violent rioters?Footnote 330 Fighting Hamas terrorism from Gaza under the auspices of armed conflict is one thing; shooting at teenagers flying a kite is quite another. Israel steadfastly maintained the former approach, but nonetheless struggled at that time with an appropriate response. ‘Technological non-lethal solutions for thwarting the kites, such as drones deflecting the kites from their trajectory, are not an ultimate solution; and options other than the use of lethal force to thwart the threat, such as talks and warnings, have proved useless.’Footnote 331 One cannot in good faith target children, limiting the level of force against the actual imminent threat to something like a law-enforcement operation or self-defence.Footnote 332
The more permissive hostility model widened legitimate targets to Hamas personnel and assets, rather than merely responding to the immediate threat, namely the incendiary apparatus and its launchers, who were mostly youngsters.Footnote 333 The armed conflict model allowed Israel to target the leaders of Hamas, particularly its military wing, as well as weapons factories and warehouses, in response to the damage wrought upon Israeli territory, in the hope of reducing the risk and deterring future attacks.
Though Hamas may not have initiated the ‘kite-unit’, it quickly endorsed and adopted its fire attacks as an attractive tactic, supported and encouraged them, turning the kite/balloon-based arson into a central operation effort.Footnote 334 While launchers may or may not have received direct orders, Hamas clearly exploited these weaponized kites and balloons for its terroristic purposes.Footnote 335 There is no doubt that between 2018 and Fall 2023 Hamas exercised full effective authority over the Gaza Strip, and at times adopted the fire attacks as its own with threats to keep the kite launch going.Footnote 336 The low-tech weapons not only served the Hamas government’s public image but also enabled it to attack Israel while maintaining deniability and avoiding full-scale kinetic warfare, in which Israel clearly has the upper hand and which both parties appeared to have been avoiding at the time.Footnote 337
The Gaza case study has since been overtaken by events, but it remains a recent and quite singular paradigm of ‘environmental terrorism’ associated with a recognized terrorist group and re-raises the wider issue of combatting environmental aggression. Section 2 argued that limiting counter-measures to the use of force short of full-scale war should avoid the pitfall of generating more environmental damage than protection, outweighing the environmental benefits of the response. Confronting the incendiary objects from Gaza, Israel used a mixture of ‘smart weapons’, such as precision rifles, optical tracking systems, and laser blades to detect and deflate airborne balloons and to grapple and bring down kites, as well as economic sanctions, with only partial success at halting and preventing attacks.Footnote 338 Pre-emptive military measures, such as surgical drone strikes against weapons facilities and targeted killings of those responsible, may be more effective against arson attacks.Footnote 339
Regarding Gaza, in hindsight, all efforts to repel and deter Hamas aggression proved tragically unsuccessful. Notwithstanding and more generally, from both human- and non-human-centred perspectives, resorting to jus ad vim against purely environmental aggression is probably our best shot in terms of efficacy and proportionality. This sets ‘environmental terrorism’ and the appropriate response to it wholly apart from physical invasion and outright terrorism against civilians, even when the two appear in retrospect as points on a single continuum.
4.5 Concluding Remarks
While the underlying phenomenon of environmental destruction during armed conflict is an old story, the deliberate use of this tactic by terrorist organizations, like the scholarly study of ‘environmental terrorism’, remains in its infancy. Early twenty-first-century academia saw a multidisciplinary surge of interest in the study of terrorism. Typical definitions emphasize non-combatant targets, illegality, political motivation, generating fear, and ‘theatre’ influencing an audience. While every element is contestable, all definitions and descriptions assume human targets.
As we face unprecedented environmental degradation on many fronts, the harm done by terroristic attacks to natural resources – deliberately destroying ecosystems and natural habitats – exceeds the immediate damage to property and human well-being. Nonetheless, the use of the term ‘terrorism’ in this context seems mostly a matter of political polemic. Extending absolute civilian immunity to non-human elements of the natural world, condemning any attack on the environment or its use as ‘terrorism’, is rather a stretch. At least from the perspectives of our current political philosophies, this derogatory label applies primarily to human victims.
Attaching the terrorism label to ecological destruction runs the risk of belittling human suffering and the inherent worth of human life, though this argument admittedly prompts the question of anthropocentric ethics. The issue of whether humanity is increasingly progressing towards the recognition of other inhabitants of the earth as equivalent in their intrinsic value exceeds the scope of this essay. Targeting the environment exclusively does not qualify as terrorism by most existing accounts of it and cannot warrant the type of military response or unequivocal condemnation that liberal morality attaches to terrorist strikes, particularly in terms of Kantian interdictions on using human beings as means only and on free riding.
Two caveats: none of the above diminishes or detracts from the severity of attacking the natural environment, the gravity of harm caused, or the need to respond. Moreover, in all likelihood, environmental attacks will often prejudice civilian populations quite directly, as is well reflected in the laws of war. Attacks on the natural environment may not discriminate between human and non-human targets; they may target human non-combatants within the environment; destroy essential resources; ignite, pollute, or contaminate civilian surroundings, and so forth, or represent one link in a terroristic chain of events.
The arson attacks emanating from the Gaza Strip on the Israeli South presented a useful case study of ‘environmental terrorism’ up to Fall 2023. The rest is history. In this case, the applicability of the terrorism label is a moot point. From forests to falcons, incendiary attacks not only impacted but also targeted non-combatants, particularly children. Like Hamas’s inaccurate rockets, their initial lack of success in trying to kill Israelis does not excuse them from the charge of terrorism. The worst was yet to come.
Even where the harm inflicted is purely environmental, no state can indefinitely ignore attacks on their natural resources. Beyond putting out fires, arson attacks require a response. Classifying environmental attacks either as local crimes or as armed conflict, as well as identifying their perpetrators as civilians or irregular combatants directly engaged in hostilities, forms the crux of appropriate reaction. Where non-kinetic tactics have been exhausted and military response is apt and necessary, environmental and humanitarian concerns make a case for limited counter-measures – the use of pinpointed military force, short of war – against primary culprits and their infrastructure, at least as a first call, reserving full-scale armed conflict to combatting invasion and murderous attacks.
Acknowledgements
This book is made up of four relatively new topics, originally researched piecemeal. I am most grateful to Chaim Gans who first suggested I gather the various pieces into one comprehensive manuscript, and for encouraging me to do so.
Some of this material has been published previously in two individual articles: ‘Environmental Ethics of War: Jus ad Bellum, Jus in Bello, and the Natural Environment’, Conatus – Journal of Philosophy, 8(2) (2023), 399–429; and ‘Environmental Just Wars: Jus ad Bellum and the Natural Environment’, Journal of Applied Philosophy (2024). I thank the journals for permission to use these materials here.
All this research was supported by the Israel Science Foundation (Grant no. 217/22).
I am grateful to Kerry Bennett and Avery Kolers, editors of the Journal of Applied Philosophy, for their critical attention and detailed suggestions, which ultimately improved Section 2.
Azar Gat offered sharp insights at the start of this project, which have continued to guide me throughout. Michael Gross has been extremely generous, reading and commenting usefully on articles and sections along the way, as well as on the final manuscript.
Two former students who have since become friends and colleagues were also invaluably helpful. Tamar Caner taught me most of what I know about civil wars. I am indebted to her research on non-international armed conflicts and for her co-authorship of an article that formed Section 3, as well as her permission to use these materials here. Adi Levy graciously shared his expertise on violent and non-violent resistance, improving my work on environmental terrorism. Our collaboration on his paper on armed and unarmed environmental violence, as well as his comments on my own work, have significantly enriched Section 4.
Finally, to the young members of my family – my daughters Abigail and Martha, my nephews Aaron, Avner, and Joel, and my niece Ella – whose generation must contend with war in a deteriorating environment: may God help and keep you.
Series Editors
Jon C. W. Pevehouse
University of Wisconsin–Madison
Jon C. W. Pevehouse is the Mary Herman Rubinstein Professor of Political Science and Public Policy at the University of Wisconsin–Madison. He has published numerous books and articles in IR in the fields of international political economy, international organizations, foreign policy analysis, and political methodology. He is a former editor of the leading IR field journal, International Organization.
Tanja A. Börzel
Freie Universität Berlin
Tanja A. Börzel is the Professor of political science and holds the Chair for European Integration at the Otto-Suhr-Institute for Political Science, Freie Universität Berlin. She holds a PhD from the European University Institute, Florence, Italy. She is coordinator of the Research College “The Transformative Power of Europe,” as well as the FP7-Collaborative Project “Maximizing the Enlargement Capacity of the European Union” and the H2020 Collaborative Project “The EU and Eastern Partnership Countries: An Inside-Out Analysis and Strategic Assessment.” She directs the Jean Monnet Center of Excellence “Europe and its Citizens.”
Edward D. Mansfield
University of Pennsylvania
Edward D. Mansfield is the Hum Rosen Professor of Political Science, University of Pennsylvania. He has published well over 100 books and articles in the area of international political economy, international security, and international organizations. He is Director of the Christopher H. Browne Center for International Politics at the University of Pennsylvania and former program co-chair of the American Political Science Association.
Editorial Team
International Relations Theory
Jeffrey T. Checkel, European University Institute, Florence
International Security
Jon C. W. Pevehouse, University of Wisconsin–Madison
International Political Economy
Edward D. Mansfield, University of Pennsylvania
Stefanie Walter, University of Zurich
International Organisations
Tanja A. Börzel, Freie Universität Berlin
About the Series
The Cambridge Elements Series in International Relations publishes original research on key topics in the field. The series includes manuscripts addressing international security, international political economy, international organizations, and international relations.