COVID-19 conjures the existence of a sacrificial international order. Jean-Hervé Bradol, a former president of Medecins sans Frontieres (MSF), posed that all international orders produce sacrifices.Footnote 1 He was writing in reaction to the “just wars” of the post-Cold War period, when the international community began using force in defense of humanity. According to the defenders of use of force, violence and collateral damage were unfortunate but necessary and legitimate. The benefits would outweigh the costs: more would live than die from the interventions, and those just wars would help defend a liberal international order and create the conditions for a liberal peace. Progress is never cheap or without its sacrifices. All international orders have sacrifices—including those with the best intentions and visions of humanity.
One way to distinguish between different kinds of international orders is the method of selection and the meaning of the sacrifices. For instance, racialized orders select individuals based on skin color and justify their deaths as necessary for a way of life that benefits the so-called superior race.Footnote 2 Religious orders might select nonbelievers and the blasphemous in the pursuit of purity and the sacred.Footnote 3 Sovereign orders have justified the sacrifice of other states in the name of international order. Poland saw itself as the “Christ of Europe” after it was partitioned out of existence by the great powers for the preservation of the European order in the late eighteenth century.Footnote 4
And what of a liberal international order (LIO) defined by principles of equality, humanity, and progress and sustained by international institutions that promote cooperation, peace, and prosperity? Its axioms interfere with entertaining or even conceiving of the possibility of such sacrifice. Internal critiques acknowledge the LIO's failure to live its principles as well as its unintended consequences, such as an economic globalization that produces winners and losers and translates into widening economic inequality. But the liberal forecast is that in the long run the global spread of rights, democracy, and markets, strengthened by the appropriate institutions, will produce a more prosperous and peaceful world. It is possible. Whether on balance the liberal international order has done more good than harm, or is the worst form of international order except for all the alternatives, are not arguments I can or want to settle here. My point is simpler: the LIO, like all orders, has a sacrificial element.
Liberalism's sacrificial dimension begins with the recognition that while equality is a sacrosanct principle, in practice it has always produced forms of inequality. The same can be said for liberalism's kindred spirit of humanity. Humanity has always been a work in progress, and a central narrative of the history of the enlightenment is the slow, uneven, and incomplete process whereby those who were once considered not quite human become humanized. This hierarchy of humanity translates into the relative value of human lives and the determination of whose suffering matters more than others, the effects of which often work through the market and are especially visible during pandemics. Bradol observed that while people are sacrificed during just wars, more people died from HIV/AIDS than from conflict in 2000 because the afflicted were often stigmatized and treated as less than human, and could not afford antiretroviral drugs. These would-be customers of pharmaceutical companies had neither their humanity nor money. And in the spirit of sacrifice, those companies responded by defending their prices, noting that they needed sufficient profits to motivate them to produce life-saving treatments and vaccines. This is a world, observes the South African writer J.M. Coetzee, that easily reduces people to “another brick in the pyramid of sacrifice.”Footnote 5
The relationship between markets and morals is central to scholarship that is critical of neoliberalism and market fundamentalism.Footnote 6 Neoliberalism has two meanings in this argument. There is the neoliberalism associated with the claim that “human well-being can best be advanced by liberating individual entrepreneurial freedoms and skills within an institutional framework characterized by strong private property rights, free markets, and free trade.”Footnote 7 Where states are accused of having overstepped their boundaries, neoliberalism aims to put them back in their appropriate place in order to let markets function properly. Another meaning of neoliberalism refers to how the market both shapes and constitutes values. Liberalism's claim is that markets work best when walled off from normative concerns such as justice, fairness, and morality.Footnote 8 The liberal mistake is to assume that the market is separate from ethics when it is in fact bound up with them. The market can become an ethic in itself and can eventually replace or diminish previously held ethical beliefs. Markets shape what is valued and what counts as fair, just, or equitable. Markets assign value to living and life, and shape whose suffering counts. While all humans are vulnerable to COVID-19, not all are equally vulnerable and not all have equal access to care. These vulnerabilities are not randomly distributed but rather are patterned by class, race, and other enduring hierarchies that are produced and reproduced by markets.
This essay uses COVID-19 to explore the sacrificial element of the liberal international order. I begin with humanitarian governance and the claim that the highest moral principle is the preservation of life. Compassion and an ethics of care are present in all societies, cultures, and religions, but beginning with the enlightenment and liberalism in eighteenth century Europe they became institutionalized and internationalized into a form of governance that contains a diffuse form of power—biopower— that is directed at “making live and letting die.”Footnote 9 Yet the moral principle of preserving life and relieving suffering has been circumscribed and redirected by capitalist expansion and market ideologies. This observation sets up the following three sections: the moral economy, which shapes access to subsistence goods; triage, which concerns the prioritization of treatment during emergencies and situations of scarcity; and sacrifice, which relates to the existing moral order and other categories of dying, including those who can be killed, the abandoned, and the unseen. I conclude by discussing how the concept of sacrifice offers scholars of international relations an alternative way of thinking about both international order and the discipline itself.
Before proceeding, three caveats. Those who study the global politics of living and dying almost always compare the global North and South, showcasing the gross inequalities in life chances between the two. If and when COVID-19 runs its course, the final tally might follow the familiar pattern, particularly as the effects include deaths from food insecurity and starvation, the further deterioration of other parts of an already thin health sector, and rising poverty. But for the moment the US and other Western states in the heartland of the liberal order do not have a distinguished record of prevention or containment, and many countries in the global South, such as Vietnam and Rwanda, have put liberal states to shame. This observation has fueled speculation about whether democratic or nondemocratic states are better at plague management, and if so, why. Second, there is considerable variation among Western liberal democracies, which could reflect variations in neoliberalism and market fundamentalism; namely, the more pervasive and intensive the perceived sanctity of the market, the more vulnerable are the weakest members of society. As Maurice Halbwechs writes, there are “good reasons to assume that a society has the mortality rate it deserves and the number of deaths and their distribution among the different age groups faithfully reflects the value that a society attaches to the furtherance of life.”Footnote 10 Third, variations also exist in the meaning and practice of liberalism. The sacrificial practices of nineteenth century liberalism are not the same as today's. But the sacrifices remain.
Humanitarian Governance
Humanitarian governance is “the administration of human collectivities in the name of a higher moral principle that sees the preservation of life and the alleviation of suffering as the highest value of action.”Footnote 11 In the absence of such a principle it would be difficult to explain a nearly unprecedented aspect of the global response to COVID-19: the willingness of many states to bear considerable economic, political, and social costs to save lives and reduce suffering through lockdowns and quarantines.Footnote 12 There is a long and crooked history of the internationalization and institutionalization of humanitarian governance that cannot be surveyed here, but several elements are critical for understanding its existence and limits.
The seeds of humanitarian governance were planted with the enlightenment's emphasis on humanity. Unlike pre-enlightenment thought that contained hierarchies by reason of birthright, connection to God, or some other doctrine, enlightenment ideas of humanity emphasized how all individuals are humans, all humans are equal and capable of reason, and because humans form a common species they are obligated to “treat fellow humans as family.”Footnote 13 Contributing to these feelings of fellowship were processes of sacralization in which humans became “the object of a sort of religion … a common faith” and a “religion of humanity.”Footnote 14 Compassion also became a mark of the human. Compassion exists across all peoples, cultures, and religions, but beginning in eighteenth century Europe it became a higher order emotion. The spectacle of misery ceased to generate indifference and instead generated pity and compassion.Footnote 15 Such responses were produced not only by reason and rationality, but also by feelings of sentimentality generated by sad stories.Footnote 16 Suffering incited compassion and feelings of humanity.
Compassion is not enough—it also requires action, and the enlightenment produced a burst of voluntary associations, often organized by religious and humanistic organizations, for the purpose of addressing suffering. Many of these associations evolved from a charity-based model in which giving was motivated by kindness and not obligation, but there was a growing belief that individuals now had duties to others. Negative duties arose, such as avoiding action that produced unnecessary and foreseeable harm, as did positive duties to “prevent and alleviate human suffering,” “to protect life and health and to ensure respect for the human being,” and to “promote mutual understanding, friendship, co-operation and lasting peace amongst all peoples.”Footnote 17 And the enlightenment did more than instill a desire to act; it also provided the means to do so. Suffering was no longer something produced by the Gods, nature, or karma. There were humanistic and scientific explanations and solutions. Because of advances in science, technology, social organization, and administration, suffering could be mitigated by human intervention.
Importantly, the ability of states and societies to remove suffering and save lives in a continuous manner depended on administration and governance. Humanitarian governance contains a form of power that Foucault labelled biopower. For Foucault, Europe crossed a “threshold when the biological processes characterizing the life of human beings as a species became a crucial issue for political decision making, a new ‘problem’ to be addressed by governments” in both exceptional and normal times.Footnote 18 In other words, whereas once the sovereign “took life and let live,” now there is “making live and letting die.”Footnote 19 Biopower is diffused throughout the state apparatus and society; it is a decentralized structure of knowledge involving the state, society, and economy, evident in new fields of sanitation, urban planning, nutrition, social work, and public health. Biopower also changes how the subject defines the self; for instance, creating new self-understandings of responsibility and care of the self, particularly in the areas of hygiene and health. Foucault saw biopolitics, like he did other forms of power, as neither only good or bad but as having the potential for both. For instance, in Discipline and Punish he observes how in the seventeenth century the state responded to the Bubonic Plague by insinuating itself into the “smallest details of everyday life” and with quarantines, multiple separations, methods for delivering food, and new techniques of surveillance and control.Footnote 20 But methods and techniques designed to improve human life—particularly evident during pandemics such as COVID-19— can become institutionalized and part of systems of control. For instance, contact tracing apps used to contain the spread of COVID-19 can also be used by power-minded governments for tracking society and political opponents.Footnote 21
These practices of humanity that are intended to save life and mitigate suffering have been as uneven as humanity itself. Central to the debate about and expansion of humanity is the question of who is the human.Footnote 22 Distinctions have been made according to race, culture, religion, gender, and other categories of discrimination; liberalism is no exception as it contains status inequalities based on property, gender, and race. In the nineteenth century, liberalism's evolving concept of humanity was shaped by considerations of the physical and cognitive qualities an individual must possess to be counted as a human and of whether all humans are truly equal. Liberals such as John Stuart Mill claimed that there were two kinds of people: those who were fully human (that is, civilized white Westerners) and those who were humans-in-the-making (children in civilized societies and the colonized) because they were still acquiring the necessary rationality and reasoning. Only after World War II did the principle of all humans as equal become widely accepted, but it became diluted in practice as distinctions continued to generate hierarchies of humanity, particularly as they are intertwined with capital and markets. The following sections on the moral economy, triage, and sacrifice are suggestive of how market mechanisms in the liberal order are central to making live and letting die and producing sacrifices that are justified in the name of progress.
Moral Economy
The concept of the moral economy has many meanings, but I follow the tradition of E.P. Thompson, James Scott, and Karl Polanyi, who highlight whether, when, and how vulnerable populations are helped by others, including the state, through reciprocal expectations to acquire basic subsistence goods during crises.Footnote 23 Charles Tilly's definition works well: when “claimants to a commodity can invoke non-monetary rights to that commodity … and third parties will act to support these claims—when, for example community membership supersedes price as a basis of entitlement.”Footnote 24
Situations like COVID-19 showcase the moral economy when there is unequal access to life-saving medical treatment. During emergencies and situations of widespread hardship, goods are scarce and often priced beyond the reach of vulnerable populations. In many societies, what Scott calls social insurance kicks in at such moments. This insurance is provided by a web of reciprocal obligations among those in the community and is supported by patrimonial relations with political and economic elites and the state.Footnote 25 These are obligations that tap into deeply held beliefs about what is fair and just. However, a moral economy is no utopia; life is often lived on the margins and elites provide aid not because they necessarily care about others but rather because they care about preserving their rule.
Moral economists are particularly attentive to moments when these obligations disintegrate. This can occur for various reasons, but Scott, Thompson, and Polanyi highlight changes in market relations and economic ideologies. Thompson examined the imposition of the corn laws and the end of patrimonial relations between peasants and landowners. From the eighteenth century on, British governments responded to widespread hunger and famine with laissez-faire policies. Although Adam Smith is often cited as something of a bleeding-heart liberal because of his writing on moral sentiments, his heart turned to stone during periods of mass misery. As a fierce advocate of free trade, Smith opposed regulation, including paternalistic protections. He wanted to “demoralize” the market, by which he meant divesting it of intrusive moral imperatives that might interfere with prices and incentives. During the debate over the corn laws in the early 1770s he acknowledged that laissez-faire policies might cause starvation in the short run. But he opposed moral interventions on the grounds that the regulation of corn prices through such measures as a cap on prices would cause speculation and black markets, lead farmers to cut production, retard long-run growth, and increase the risk of future famines.Footnote 26 Scott argued that the introduction of colonialism and the transition to capitalist agriculture in Vietnam and Burma caused landowners to increase their rate of exploitation of increasingly commodified labor and to shred the existing safety net. Polanyi famously proposed the distinction between embedded and disembedded economies. Embedded economies “submerge production and exchange to the purposes and practices of far more significant social, political, or religious institutions.”Footnote 27 Disembedded economies, on the other hand, have wrenched the market from social relations and institutions, have an autonomy of their own, and shape what counts as moral, just, and fair. Beyond preventable deaths, what results from the rupture of the moral economy? Thompson documented food riots, Scott protest movements, and Polanyi a “double movement” that created left- and right-wing movements in Europe and the United States.
Markets are global and so, too, are moral economies. Colonial powers often refused to intervene in the market and permitted millions to die as a consequence. In Ireland from 1845 to 1855 about one million Irish died and another two million emigrated in part because Britain's economic ideology and racism led it to elevate the market over humanity. This Smithian ideology guided the British colonial authorities’ response to a series of food shortages and famines in India.Footnote 28 In 1803–04 the colonial administrators refused to protect food supplies, ban food exports, or provide food subsidies, causing the death of millions. A similar story occurred in 1835, when an estimated 15 to 20 percent of a population of eight million perished. During the Spanish flu perhaps 20 million deaths in western India occurred because the British allowed food exports during a major drought, which led to famine, malnutrition, suppressed immune systems, and widespread flu and pneumonia.Footnote 29
Many of the classic contributions to the scholarship on the modern international political economy include a central concern with the moral economy. Building on Polanyi's The Great Transformation are John Ruggie's arguments about postwar embedded liberalism.Footnote 30 A critical lesson of the interwar period is that Western leaders needed to manage the world economy in a way that expanded trade while protecting society from economic downturns. Conversely, the rise of global neoliberalism is credited with helping to dismantle embedded liberalism's moral economy and the obligations of the state for societal welfare during recessions and depressions.Footnote 31 This dismantling required replacing the idea of a society comprised of mutual obligations with a view that it consists of nothing more than voluntary, self-interested exchanges, and that when members fall on hard times they must look to themselves, their neighbor, or charity, and rarely to the government.
How liberalism and neoliberalism have shaped the moral economy has been an important theme in discussions surrounding COVID-19.Footnote 32 There has been considerable commentary on how neoliberalism has eroded the health infrastructure in many liberal economies, a phenomenon made particularly evident by the lack of preparedness of countries that have prided themselves on their health care. Because of the decline of federal funding and the rise of for-profit medicine and insurance companies, US medical facilities have underfunded hospitals, resulting in a severe shortage of beds and 60,000 fewer employees in public health departments today compared to in 2008.Footnote 33 The millions of uninsured and underinsured in the United States also contributes to increasing death rates. In the United Kingdom, the editor of the premier British-based medical journal The Lancet observed that austerity “blunted the ambition and commitment of the government to protect its people,” and led to the loss of 17,000 hospital beds and to 40,000 vacant nursing positions.Footnote 34 These trends in advanced liberal economies can be considered self-inflicted because choices were made, but in the global South, international financial institutions—with the backing of the United States and other major Western economies—pushed structural adjustment policies that contributed to a decline in health outcomes for the most vulnerable.Footnote 35
The moral economy focuses on vulnerabilities, recognizes that not all are equally vulnerable, and observes that patterns of vulnerability are often caused by existing economic inequalities and marginalization of particular societal groups. Most discussions of the relationship between the moral economy and vulnerability focus on unequal access to subsistence needs during periods of extremis. But the moral economy also includes the structures that account for why some groups are more likely to have the preconditions that make them vulnerable to disease.Footnote 36 For instance, poverty is often correlated with poor nutrition, toxins in water and the environment, and higher rates of severe stress and mental health challenges. And some racial and minority groups are more likely to live impoverished lives than the rest of society because of a history of exclusion and marginalization, which means that they are more likely to have poor health and less likely to get treatment. This pattern exists in COVID-19. Many news accounts report on how the combination of poverty and other environmental factors explain the higher rates of COVID-19 among minority populations in the United States, and that when members of those populations are infected, they are less likely to receive a high quality of care.
Preconditions are not only produced nationally but also globally. Colonialism and imperialism created unequal exchanges between the core and the periphery—patterns that continued after decolonization and produced enduring vulnerabilities to developments in the core and the global economy in much of the global South. Western-sponsored neoliberal policies are among such pressures, and are associated with growing health inequalities between the global West and South and a decline in health outcomes among marginalized population. The South's vulnerabilities owe not only to its own incapacities but also to its incapacitation.Footnote 37
The market also shapes whose suffering and mortality matters because of its influence on which drugs are produced and who has access to them. Large, profit-oriented pharmaceutical companies play a central role in deciding which diseases get attention, and they prioritize not the diseases that do the most harm but rather those that generate the greatest profits. Accordingly, companies prioritize research and development that target Western consumers, and neglect infectious and noninfectious diseases that primarily affect impoverished populations in the global South.Footnote 38 The satirical newspaper The Onion nailed this feature with the following headline: “Experts: Ebola Vaccine at Least 50 White People Away.”Footnote 39 Additionally, once vaccines and treatments are brought to market, they are often unaffordable for the poor and most in the global South. In response, various coalitions have formed access to medicine campaigns to negotiate with pharmaceutical companies for lower prices and the production of generics.Footnote 40 The question of access is becoming increasingly urgent as global publics anticipate a vaccine for COVID-19. There are global efforts to provide equitable access, but, so far, they are no match for “vaccine nationalism;” the primary drug-producing countries, China, Western states, and India, have gone to the head of the line and the global South to the back, which brings us to the concept of triage.Footnote 41
Triage
The word “triage” originated sometime in the fourteenth century from the French word triere, meaning to select, choose, organize, prioritize, or arrange according to the quality of a traded product, such as coffee beans or pelts. Contemporary meanings refer to sorting and prioritizing in situations of scarcity, and especially during medical emergencies. But ordering along what criteria? There are two principal methods: egalitarian and utilitarian.Footnote 42
Perhaps the best-known example of the egalitarian method is prioritizing by medical need, introduced by Baron Dominique Jean Larrey, Napoleon's Surgeon-in-Chief. Prior to the introduction of this method of triage, wounded soldiers were typically left to languish until the battle ended; only then could they hope for medical care, and often by local townspeople. Rather than waiting until it was too late, Larrey began retrieving the wounded for treatment behind the frontlines and systematized the order of treatment to improve the chances of survival. Following the French spirit of equality, he proposed that those most severely wounded be treated first and those with minor injuries later. The revolutionary implication was that medical need trumped military rank, birth, title, or other social status. This egalitarian model of triage has become widely adopted.
The utilitarian model privileges the values and interests of the group over the individual. Influenced by the utilitarian reasoning that dominated British philosophy and ethics in the early nineteenth century, two British physicians developed a method based on the value of the individual to the group.Footnote 43 During World War I the United States adopted a triage method that prioritized those soldiers that could be most quickly returned to combat.Footnote 44 At the current moment health-care workers often get priority because of their value for saving lives; they are also expected to be among the first to receive the Coronavirus vaccine when it becomes available. Unlike with treatment based on need—which can generate reasonably objective criteria—with the utilitarian model groups will often disagree about which values matter most. For instance, aid workers tend to prioritize need but have confronted situations where local populations demand that modestly wounded village elders be treated prior to more severely wounded children because of the former's relative importance.Footnote 45 Because assigning value to a life is inherently subjective, those wanting calculability and more objective indicators for ranking have used likelihood of recovery, expected income generated, and anticipated years of life remaining to determine quality of life.Footnote 46 The elderly and those with pre-existing conditions do not do so well in these rankings.
The egalitarian and utilitarian models usually include an authority, either a trained individual or a small committee, to decide the order. But there is no such authority in global life to determine which states or peoples are most in need or have the most value when distributing scarce resources during emergencies, especially in a world where multiple emergencies occur simultaneously. Under these circumstances charity, mutual aid, and markets become the primary methods of allocation. Charity and humanitarian assistance are perhaps the most famous methods of allocation, especially for vulnerable and marginalized populations in the global South. These affected populations rely on the kindness of strangers, but kindness is usually in short supply relative to demand, especially in pandemics and emergencies. And kindness does not necessarily channel charity to those most in need. Those who give often do so because of perceived need and pre-existing connections and commitments; moral and causality responsibility; guilt, anger, and shame; status seeking; and salvation. Aid agencies routinely try to get people to keep giving by playing the so-called humanity card, circulating graphic images of victims and sad stories about those in need, and preaching that if one can make a life-saving difference without having to sacrifice much, one should. These appeals work on actors with a conscience, which are not states’ best feature. States give primarily because of their economic and strategic interests. In response to this inequality, international nongovernmental organizations working with states and international organizations have established various mechanisms to increase the chance that those in need but without powerful friends still get assistance.
In contrast to leaving assistance to unpredictable emotions, there are implicit and explicit contracts of mutual aid based on reciprocity.Footnote 47 Principles of mutual aid and diffuse reciprocity operate best when there are pre-existing networks of exchange and attachment, when the aid contract is based on a limited number of actors, and when there is a long shadow of the future. International relations scholars have tested these norms of cooperation under various circumstances, and the norms do not hold up as well in situations where the perceived survival of the actor is at stake, which is, of course, precisely the issue with COVID-19 and the reason that vaccine nationalism appears to be besting various proposals for mutual aid. Evidence of the disintegration of the mutual aid contract came early in the pandemic. The European Union has a convention and emergency bureau to coordinate joint action during disasters. In response to the rapid increase in cases and shortage of medical equipment, Italy called for the bureau's implementation, which included the mandated sharing of national stockpiles and sending doctors to areas with high infection rates and shortages of medical personnel. But every member of the EU refused.Footnote 48
Lastly, markets inform triage practices. Markets might create efficiencies and incentives for producers to shift from making underwear to masks, for example.Footnote 49 But the reliance on markets during emergencies also has complications if the goal is to save as many as possible and preserve a modicum of equity. There is no guarantee that efficiencies will arrive in time to save lives, that producers will shift to public needs, or that life-saving goods will reach those who cannot afford them. A Spencerian survival of the fittest can lead to cutthroat rivalry, outbidding, hoarding, price-gouging, and opportunistic scam artists attempting to sell defective goods at inflated prices. The highest bidder is likely to be the actor with the deepest pockets and the fewest moral scruples. In general, while triage in medical facilities integrates ethics, ethics appears to diminish in prominence as we move away from the hospital and toward the global.
Sacrifice
Anthropological and religious writings on sacrifice connect the person doing the sacrificing, the thing to be sacrificed, and the broader moral or sacred order.Footnote 50 The sacrifice can serve various functions. It can be a gift—an offering to the heavens for recent fortune, to placate or to honor the Gods, or to solicit protection.Footnote 51 It can communicate gratitude for past and future blessings. It can demonstrate absolute faith in the demands from heavens. Abraham nearly sacrificed his only son Isaac as a sign of his devotion and submission to God. Sacrifices can be part of a process of atonement, repentance, or expatiation for those who have sinned, caused offense, or committed a crime. The crucifixion of Jesus Christ was a sacrifice for our sins. In religious ceremonies those who oversee the sacrifice can be believed to be part of the sacred. Although the discourse of sacrifice has religious overtones, there are secular counterparts. Soldiers are venerated for their sacrifice to the nation, and their sacrifices are often commemorated through monuments, holidays, and other rites and rituals that bind the nation.Footnote 52 In this way, most religious and secular sacrifices serve the foundational function of binding the community. The moral order feeds off the dead.Footnote 53
Bradol labelled those innocents who lost their lives in Western-sponsored just wars as sacrifices in relationship to the liberal international order. In other words, the West is doing the sacrificing, the innocents are those being sacrificed, and the recipient of the sacrifice is a sacred liberal international order that aspires to defend humanity and advance moral progress. What about deaths from COVID-19? The connections between the sacrifice, the sacrificed, and the sacred order seem much more tenuous in this case because of ambiguities regarding who is doing the sacrificing and what is the moral order, but this shaky connection returns us to the relationship between COVID-19 and whose lives matter.
Thus far I have claimed that the liberal international order is often treated by those in the West as sacred because of its relationship to humanity and progress. Additionally, I have observed how a market economy that is part of liberalism has been viewed as a source of morality and ethics.Footnote 54 The consequence is that these two moral objects, humanity and the market, are sometimes reinforcing and sometimes incongruent. Liberals venerate humanity and recognize the many sacrifices that have been made in its name. Liberals also treat the market as an important mechanism of progress, and there are times when humans are asked to sacrifice for the economy. As bluntly put by Texas Deputy Governor Dan Patrick, there are more important things than living, and those include saving the economy.Footnote 55 And while humanity and market can go hand-in-hand—as when markets are viewed as important to human well-being and progress—there are other times when humanity and markets appear to operate at cross-purposes. At the outset of the pandemic, lives were seen as taking precedence over the needs of the economy. But how long would that be allowed to continue? Writing in early May when government and health officials still agreed on using lockdown measures to flatten the curve, three scholars predicted: “As the ‘sufferings’ of capital intensify in the current crisis, we can expect a shift in crisis policy toward a more open assertion that if the biopolitical interests of capital and those of human life increasingly clash, the interests of capital ‘must’ be given precedence.”Footnote 56
My selectively scattered and completely unscientific reading of how deaths from COVID-19 are framed suggests that the language of sacrifice comes more naturally when it is connected to humanity than when it is connected to the market, but the market is not without a flock. The language of sacrifice is most prevalent when referring to the deaths of those who caught COVID-19 and died as a result of trying to save the lives of others. These are medical personnel, health-care workers, and care givers.Footnote 57 They were not sacrificed but rather acted in the quasi-religious spirit of self-sacrifice. And they gave their lives for the belief that all lives are equal and are equally deserving of care. Health workers are singled out for their courage and humanity, and called saintly by their loved ones and others who worked alongside them. In this respect, they bear considerable resemblance to aid workers who have died while providing relief during humanitarian emergencies. And like aid workers, those treating victims of COVID-19 are often seen as waging their battle on a frontline. A future indicator that health workers who died in the line of duty have obtained the status of sacrifices is if memorials are erected to consecrate their service in the name of humanity.
The language of sacrifice is used less frequently in connection to essential workers. Bus drivers, those working in slaughterhouses, UPS delivery persons, Instacart employees filling orders at Whole Foods for wealthy families, and teachers mandated to return to the classroom are risking their lives for others, but rarely described as a sacrifice in relationship to a moral order. Why not? Among the possibilities, two stand out. One is that the term “essential workers” is too broad because it potentially includes those taking risks so that others do not, and also those whose status as “essential” seems much more debatable. For instance, do we want to equate the pharmacist with the person working at a gun shop or a liquor store that is deemed essential by the local or state government? A second possibility is that sacrifice should be reserved for those who enact a calling that connects to the sacred. Medical personnel are assumed to qualify, but what about those who perform essential services because they need to earn a paycheck? They appear to be operating in the realm of the profane and not the sacred. It is entirely understandable that they would put themselves at risk—they need a job to put food on the table, to keep their home, and to afford medical care. But those who work for a living rather than a calling are rarely labeled as sacrifices, and their deaths are rarely mourned in the same way.
There is another category of death that might be more appropriate for those who die from COVID-19 after being compelled or forced to put themselves at risk: “those who can be killed.” Agamben created this category in his discussion of homo sacer.Footnote 58 Homo sacer derives from Roman law and is a person who has been judged to have committed a crime. Although he cannot be sacrificed, he can be killed, and his killer cannot be charged with homicide. The sovereign is the one who can decide to give and take away life, and the one who can use the law to exclude the person from the protection of law. Although essential workers and those who have no viable alternative to returning to a risky workplace have committed no crime, they resemble those who can be killed. They are often individuals who are compelled to take high-risk jobs because of the money—those at or below the poverty line—or because of state mandates, as with teachers. In both cases, though, the state could alleviate this pressure. For those who are economically vulnerable, the government could provide more relief, extended unemployment benefits, food stamps, health coverage, and other supports. But this would hold back the economy and require a rise in deficit spending. For teachers, the state could permit online learning, which would make it more difficult for parents to go back to work. In order to protect public and private institutions from lawsuits from an employee or user of a public or private facility who contracts COVID-19, some states are introducing liability laws that minimize damages or give immunity. If institutions do not receive this protection, the argument goes, then they will be unable to open because of the risk of litigation if someone gets sick or dies. But what if these institutions do not take basic precautions to protect their workers? Does this mean that the state has sanctioned their death by COVID-19? Do those teachers and professors who have been forced to go back into the classroom count as “those who can be killed”?
Are there other categories of the dead? There are regrettable deaths: those who died despite valiant efforts. There are needless deaths: those who died above and beyond the numbers that might have occurred had reasonable precautions and actions been taken by the state. There are also the abandoned: those who have been left to die because the state has put them aside and given up on them, resembling triage.Footnote 59 And then there are the unseen: those whose lives are not even recognized and whose deaths are not grievable. Some of them reside in the liberal order, but many are outside of it or on its borders. They are refugees, displaced, and migrants, those from lower castes in places such as India, and millions more marginalized and vulnerable people. In terms of the hierarchy of humanity, they are on the bottom rung. According to Richard Rorty, these people become “dead to us.”Footnote 60
Conclusion
All international orders demand their sacrifices. Coming from the medical relief sector, Bradol adopted a broad notion of sacrifice that included needless and preventable deaths. Religious and anthropological discussions of sacrifice, however, are more circumscribed and premised on a connection between the dead and the moral order. In other words, there are many needless and preventable deaths, but only a sanctified few obtain the status of sacrifice. Although all international orders have their sacrificial element, they can potentially be distinguished by the basis used to select the sacrifices and the meanings invested in them. The sacrificial elements can be hidden from view during settled times, but during unsettled times they emerge out of the mist and into view. COVID-19 is most definitely an unsettled period, and as with all humanitarian emergencies, the hierarchy of humanity and who is saved and who dies become the focus of attention.
The liberal international order is comprised of various principles and parts, though I have focused on the relationship between humanity and the market. Both are central to the liberal international order, and their relationship can be mutually beneficial, constraining, or constituting. Beginning with the enlightenment and the establishment of liberalism, moral progress defined by humanity and a market-driven material progress have often been viewed as mutually beneficial. Guided by a humanitarian governance that held that saving lives and reducing suffering make up the highest moral principle, states and societies increasingly became organized around human betterment. The state and society developed various humanitarian institutions that were designed to help the worst-off, but in the long run it would be an expanding market economy and not charity that would generate peace, prosperity, and progress.
But COVID-19 provides a window into a much more complicated relationship between morality and markets. Despite the claim of equality, liberalism contains a hierarchy of humanity, which is particularly evident in situations when lives are at stake. The market profoundly shapes who gets access to life-saving resources, who benefits from making live, and who suffers from letting die. The concept of the moral economy focuses attention on just these considerations, especially during periods of extreme hardship, economic crises, and pandemics when life-saving resources are scarce and states often make life-and-death decisions regarding who will live and die. The moral economy is not just national but also global. The global method of triage tends to be neither egalitarian nor utilitarian but rather market-driven, which reinforces a moral economy in which those who are last in line for access to necessary resources are the first in line for death. Such ordering is not random but rather an effect of historically-produced and structurally-induced preconditions that leave some groups more vulnerable than others. Some of the dead will be counted as sacrifices, but arguably many more on the death registry will be listed as unseen, abandoned, and permitted to be killed. Most of them will end up in a Potter's Field.
The liberal international order has a difficult time recognizing its dead. This is an order that is built around the belief in humanity and progress, in which all lives are equal and deserving of equal care and shared duties and responsibilities exist to alleviate unnecessary pain and suffering. To what extent does the discipline of international relations resemble the theory and practice of the liberal international order? How much attention is there to the hierarchy of humanity and the process of giving life and letting die? Does the discipline have the theories and the ethics to account for those who occupy the lesser rungs? Is it capable of making connections between those at the top and those at the bottom? COVID-19 challenges not just the current international order but how the discipline chooses to conceptualize international order. What would the discipline look like if the concept of sacrifice became an organizing principle? Would it be much more likely to follow Foucault's guidance that “the misfortunes of men must never be the silent leftover of politics”?Footnote 61
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the editors for providing the opportunity to write this essay and for their excellent comments. In addition to the comments provided by those on the Zoom meetings, I want to thank Tanisha Fazal, Bud Duvall, Antonio Donini, Miriam Ticktin, Ilana Feldman, Unni Karunakara, and Peter Redfield.