Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T07:17:32.137Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE RELATIVIZED LASCAR GROUPS, TYPE-AMALGAMATION, AND ALGEBRAICITY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 May 2021

JAN DOBROWOLSKI
Affiliation:
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF LEEDSLEEDS, UK and INSTYTUT MATEMATYCZNY UNIWERSYTET WROCŁAWSKI WROCŁAW, POLAND E-mail: [email protected]
BYUNGHAN KIM
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS YONSEI UNIVERSITYSEOUL, KOREAE-mail: [email protected]
ALEXEI KOLESNIKOV
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS TOWSON UNIVERSITYTOWSON, MD, USAE-mail: [email protected]
JUNGUK LEE
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES KAIST, DAEJEON, KOREAE-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In this paper we study the relativized Lascar Galois group of a strong type. The group is a quasi-compact connected topological group, and if in addition the underlying theory T is G-compact, then the group is compact. We apply compact group theory to obtain model theoretic results in this note. For example, we use the divisibility of the Lascar group of a strong type to show that, in a simple theory, such types have a certain model theoretic property that we call divisible amalgamation. The main result of this paper is that if c is a finite tuple algebraic over a tuple a, the Lascar group of $\operatorname {stp}(ac)$ is abelian, and the underlying theory is G-compact, then the Lascar groups of $\operatorname {stp}(ac)$ and of $\operatorname {stp}(a)$ are isomorphic. To show this, we prove a purely compact group-theoretic result that any compact connected abelian group is isomorphic to its quotient by every finite subgroup. Several (counter)examples arising in connection with the theoretical development of this note are presented as well. For example, we show that, in the main result above, neither the assumption that the Lascar group of $\operatorname {stp}(ac)$ is abelian, nor the assumption of c being finite can be removed.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

0. Introduction and background

Given a complete theory T, the notion of the Lascar (Galois) group $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)$ was introduced by D. Lascar (see [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler2]). The Lascar group only depends on the theory and it is a quasi-compact topological group with respect to a quotient topology of a certain Stone type space over a model ([Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler2] or [Reference Ziegler and Tent13]). More recently, the notions of the relativized Lascar groups were introduced in [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3] (and studied also in [Reference Krupiński, Newelski and Simon11] in the context of topological dynamics). Namely, given a type-definable set X in a large saturated model of the theory T, we consider the group of automorphisms restricted to the set X quotiented by the group of restricted automorphisms fixing the Lascar types of the sequences from X of length $\lambda $ . The relativized Lascar groups also only depend on T, on the type that defines X, and on the cardinal $\lambda $ . These groups are endowed with the quasi-compact quotient topologies induced by the canonical surjective maps from $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)$ to the relativized Lascar groups.

This paper continues the study started in [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3], where a connection between the relativized Lascar groups of a strong type and the first homology group of the strong type was established. If T is G-compact (for example when T is simple), then the relativized Lascar group of a strong type is compact and connected, and we use compact group theory to obtain results presented here.

A common theme for the results in this paper is the connection between group theoretic properties of the Lascar group of a strong type and the model theoretic properties of the type. In Section 1, we use the fact that any compact connected group is divisible to show that any strong type p in a simple theory has a property we call divisible amalgamation. The property would follow from the Independence Theorem if p was a Lascar type, but here p is only assumed to be a strong type. Moreover, we give amalgamation criteria for when the Lascar group of the strong type of a model is abelian, and for when the strong type of a model is a Lascar type.

In Section 2, we study morphisms between the relativized Lascar groups. The main goal is to understand the connection between the Lascar group of $\operatorname {stp}(a)$ , for some tuple a, and the Lascar group of $\operatorname {stp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ or $\operatorname {stp}(ac)$ , for a finite tuple $c\in \operatorname {acl}(a)$ . We prove that if T is G-compact, then for a finite tuple c algebraic over a, the restriction map from a Lascar group of $\operatorname {stp}(ac)$ to that of $\operatorname {stp}(a)$ is a covering map. In addition, if the Lascar group of $\operatorname {stp}(ac)$ is abelian then this group is isomorphic to that of $\operatorname {stp}(a)$ as topological groups. In order to achieve this, we separately prove a purely compact group theoretical result that any compact connected abelian group is isomorphic to its quotient by a finite subgroup. We also give an example showing that the abelianity of the relativized Lascar group is essential in the isomorphism result.

In Section 3, we mainly present three counterexamples: a non-G-compact theory where $\operatorname {stp}(a)$ is a Lascar type but $\operatorname {stp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ is not a Lascar type; an example showing that in the above-mentioned isomorphism result in Section 2, the tuple c being finite is essential; and an example answering a question raised in [Reference Kim and Lee10], namely a Lie group structure example where an RN-pattern minimal 2-chain is not equivalent to a Lascar pattern 2-chain having the same boundary.

Let us remark that the results of Section 2 and the supplementary examples from Sections 3.1 and 3.2 do not make any use of the homology groups $H_1(p)$ , so a reader interested only in these results is advised to skip from Fact 0.4 to Section 2.

In the remaining part of this section we recall the definitions and terminology of basic notions, which, unless said otherwise, we use throughout this note. We work in a large saturated model ${\mathcal M}(={\mathcal M}^{\operatorname {eq}})$ of a complete theory T, and we use the standard notation. So $A, B,\dots $ and $M,N,\dots $ are small subsets and elementary submodels of ${\mathcal M}$ , respectively. Lower-case letters $a,b,\dots $ will denote tuples of elements from ${\mathcal M}$ , possibly infinite. We will explicitly specify when a tuple is assumed to be finite.

To simplify the notation, we state the results for types over the empty set (rather than over $\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )$ ). This does not reduce the generality because, after naming a parameter set, we assume for the rest that $\operatorname {dcl}(\emptyset )(=\operatorname {dcl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset ))=\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )(=\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset ))$ . We fix a complete strong type $p(x)\in S(\emptyset )$ with possibly infinite arity of x. For tuples $a,b$ , we write $a\equiv _Ab$ ( $a\equiv ^s_Ab$ , resp.) to mean that they have the same (strong, resp.) type over A. Note that $a\equiv ^s_Ab$ if and only if $a\equiv _{\operatorname {acl}(A)}b$ .

Let us recall the definitions of the Lascar groups and types. These are well-known notions in model theory. In particular, the Lascar group depends only on T and is a quasi-compact group under the topology introduced in [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler2] or [Reference Ziegler and Tent13]. Moreover, due to our assumption $\operatorname {dcl}(\emptyset )=\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )$ , the group is connected as well. Recall that a topological space is compact if it is quasi-compact and Hausdorff.

Definition 0.1.

  • $\operatorname {Autf}({\mathcal M})$ is the normal subgroup of $\operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M})$ generated by

    $$ \begin{align*}\{f \in \operatorname{Aut}({\mathcal M}) \mid f \mbox{ fixes some model } M \prec {\mathcal M} \mbox{ pointwise}\}.\end{align*} $$
  • For tuples $a,b \in {\mathcal M}$ , we say they have the same Lascar type, written $a\equiv ^Lb$ or $\operatorname {Ltp}(a)=\operatorname {Ltp}(b)$ , if there is $f\in \operatorname {Autf}({\mathcal M}) $ such that $f(a)=b$ . We say $a,b$ have the same KP(Kim–Pillay)-type (write $a\equiv ^{KP} b$ ) if they are in the same class of any bounded $\emptyset $ -type-definable equivalence relation.

  • The group $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T):=\operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M})/\operatorname {Autf}({\mathcal M})$ is called the Lascar ( Galois ) group of T.

  • We say T is G-compact if $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)$ is compact; equivalently $\{\mbox {id}\}$ is closed in $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)$ ; also equivalently $a\equiv ^L b$ iff $a\equiv ^{KP} b$ for any (possibly infinite) tuples $a,b$ from ${\mathcal M}$ [Reference Kim8].

Note that the above is the definition of “G-compactness over $\emptyset $ ,” but for convenience throughout this paper we omit “over $\emptyset $ .”

Fact 0.2. For tuples $a,b$ , we have $a\equiv ^L b$ if and only if the Lascar distance between a and b is finite, i.e., there are finitely many indiscernible sequences $I_1,\ldots , I_n$ , and tuples $a=a_0, a_1,\ldots , a_n=b$ such that each of $a_{i-1}I_i$ and $a_iI_i$ is an indiscernible sequence for $i=1,\ldots ,n$ .

Now let us recall, mainly from [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3], the definitions of various relativized Lascar groups of p and related facts.

Definition 0.3.

  • $\operatorname {Aut}(p):=\{ f \restriction p({\mathcal M}) \mid f\in \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M})\}$ ;

  • for a cardinal $\lambda> 0$ , $\operatorname {Autf}^{\lambda }(p)=\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {fix}}^{\lambda }(p):=$

    $$ \begin{align*}\{\sigma\in \operatorname{Aut}(p)\mid \mbox{ for any } \bar{a}=(a_i)_{i< \lambda} \mbox{ with } a_i\models p, \ \bar{a}\equiv^L \sigma(\bar{a}) \};\end{align*} $$
  • $\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {fix}}(p):=$

    $$ \begin{align*}\{\sigma\in \operatorname{Aut}(p) \mid \bar{a}\equiv^L \sigma(\bar{a})\mbox{ where } \bar{a} \mbox{ is some enumeration of } p({\mathcal M}) \};\end{align*} $$
    and $\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {res}}(p):=\{ f \restriction p({\mathcal M}) \mid f\in \operatorname {Autf}({\mathcal M})\}$ .

Notice that $\operatorname {Autf}^{\lambda }(p)$ , $\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {fix}}(p)$ , and $\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {res}}(p)$ are normal subgroups of $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ .

  • $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {fix}, \lambda }(p):=\operatorname {Aut}(p)/\operatorname {Autf}^{\lambda }(p)$ ;Footnote 1

  • $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {fix}}(p):=\operatorname {Aut}(p)/\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {fix}}(p)$ , and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {res}}(p):=\operatorname {Aut}(p)/\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {res}}(p)$ .

We will give an example (in Example 2.3) where $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^2(p)$ are distinct. In [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3, Remark 3.4], a canonical topology on each of the above groups was defined. With these topologies, they become quotients of the topological group $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)$ .

Fact 0.4 [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3]

$\operatorname {Autf}^{\omega }(p)=\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {fix}}(p)$ , and, for each $\lambda (\leq \omega )$ , $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)$ does not depend on the choice of a monster model, and is a quasi-compact connected topological group. Hence, if T is G-compact, $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)$ is a compact connected group.

If $p(x)$ is a type of a model, then $\operatorname {Autf}^1(p)=\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {fix}}(p)=\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {res}}(p)$ , $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {fix}}(p)=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {res}}(p)\cong \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)$ . The abelianization of $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ (i.e., the group $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)/(\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p))'$ ) is isomorphic to the first homology group $H_1(p)$ .

The last statement in the above fact explains the connection between the relativized Lascar group and the model theoretic homology group $H_1$ of the type. Let us recall now the key definitions in the homology theory in model theory. We fix a ternary automorphism-invariant relation between small sets of ${\mathcal M}$ satisfying

  • finite character: for any sets $A,B,$ and C, we have iff for any finite tuples $a\in A$ and $b\in B$ ;

  • normality: for any sets A, B, and C, if , then ;

  • symmetry: for any sets $A,B,$ and C, we have iff ;

  • transitivity: iff and , for any sets A and $B\subseteq C\subseteq D$ ;

  • extension: for any sets A and $B\subseteq C$ , there is $A'\equiv _BA$ such that .

Throughout this paper we call the above axioms the basic 5 axioms. We say that A is $*$ -independent from B over C if . Notice that there is at least one such relation for any theory, namely, the trivial independence relation given by: For any sets $A,B,C$ , put . Of course there is a non-trivial such relation when T is simple or rosy, given by forking or thorn-forking, respectively.

Notation 0.5. Let s be an arbitrary finite set of natural numbers. Given any subset $X\subseteq {\mathcal P}(s)$ , we may view X as a category where for any $u, v \in X$ , $\operatorname {Mor}(u,v)$ consists of a single morphism $\iota _{u,v}$ if $u\subseteq v$ , and $\operatorname {Mor}(u,v)=\emptyset $ otherwise. If $f\colon X \rightarrow {\mathcal C}_0$ is any functor into some category ${\mathcal C}_0$ , then for any $u, v\in X$ with $u \subseteq v$ , we let $f^u_v$ denote the morphism $f(\iota _{u,v})\in \operatorname {Mor}_{{\mathcal C}_0}(f(u),f(v))$ . We shall call $X\subseteq {\mathcal P}(s)$ downward closed if for any $u, v\in {\mathcal P}(s)$ , if $u\subseteq v$ and $v\in X$ then $u\in X$ . Note that if X is non-empty and downward closed then it has $\emptyset \subseteq \omega $ as an object.

We use now ${\mathcal C}$ to denote the category whose objects are the small subsets of ${\mathcal M}$ , and whose morphisms are elementary maps. For a functor $f:X\to {\mathcal C}$ and objects $u\subseteq v$ of X, $f^u_v(u)$ denotes the set $f^u_v(f(u))(\subseteq f(v))$ .

Definition 0.6. By a $*$ -independent functor in p, we mean a functor f from some non-empty downward closed $X\subseteq {\mathcal P}(s)$ , viewed as a category as above, into ${\mathcal C}$ satisfying the following:

  1. (1) If $\{ i \}\subseteq \omega $ is an object in X, then $f(\{ i \})$ is of the form $\operatorname {acl}(Cb)$ where $b\models p$ , $C=\operatorname {acl}(C)=f^{\emptyset }_{\{ i \}}(\emptyset )$ , and .

  2. (2) Whenever $u(\neq \emptyset )\subseteq \omega $ is an object in X, we have

    $$ \begin{align*} f( u) = \operatorname{acl} \left( \bigcup_{i\in u} f^{\{ i \}}_u(\{ i \}) \right) \end{align*} $$
    and $\{f^{\{i\}}_u(\{i\})|\ i\in u \}$ is $*$ -independent over $f^\emptyset _u(\emptyset )$ .

We let ${\mathcal A}^*_p$ denote the family of all $*$ -independent functors in p.

A $*$ -independent functor f is called a $*$ -independent n-simplex in p if $f(\emptyset )=\emptyset $ , our named algebraically closed set, and $\operatorname {dom}(f)={\mathcal P}(s)$ with $s\subseteq \omega $ and $|s|=n+1$ . We call s the support of f and denote it by $\operatorname {supp}(f)$ .

In the rest we may call a $*$ -independent n-simplex in p just an n-simplex of p, as far as no confusion arises.

Definition 0.7. Let $n\geq 0$ . We define:

$$ \begin{align*} &S_n({\mathcal A}^*_p):= \{\, f\in {\mathcal A}^*_p \mid f\ \mbox{is an}\ n\mbox{-simplex of}\ p\, \},\\ &C_n({\mathcal A}^*_p): = \mbox{the free abelian group generated by}\ S_n({\mathcal A}^*_p). \end{align*} $$

An element of $C_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)$ is called an n-chain of p. The support of a chain c, denoted by $\operatorname {supp}(c)$ , is the union of the supports of all the simplices that appear in c with a non-zero coefficient. Now for $n\geq 1$ and each $i=0, \ldots , n$ , we define a group homomorphism

$$ \begin{align*} \partial^i_n\colon C_n({\mathcal A}^*_p) \rightarrow C_{n-1}({\mathcal A}^*_p) \end{align*} $$

by putting, for any n-simplex $f\colon {\mathcal P}(s) \rightarrow {\mathcal C}$ in $S_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)$ where $s = \{ s_0 <\cdots < s_n \}\subseteq \omega $ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \partial_n^i(f):= f\restriction {\mathcal P}(s\backslash\{s_i\}) \end{align*} $$

and then extending linearly to all n-chains in $C_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)$ . Then we define the boundary map

$$ \begin{align*} \partial_n\colon C_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)\rightarrow C_{n-1}({\mathcal A}^*_p) \end{align*} $$

by

$$ \begin{align*} \partial_n(c):=\sum_{0\leq i\leq n}(-1)^i \partial_n^i(c). \end{align*} $$

We shall often refer to $\partial _n(c)$ as the boundary of c. Next, we define:

$$ \begin{align*} &Z_n({\mathcal A}^*_p):= \operatorname{Ker} \, \partial_n,\\ & B_n({\mathcal A}^*_p):= \operatorname{Im} \, \partial_{n+1}. \end{align*} $$

The elements of $Z_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)$ and $B_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)$ are called n-cycles and n-boundaries in p, respectively. It is straightforward to check that $ \partial _{n}\circ \partial _{n+1} =0.$ Hence we can now define the group

$$ \begin{align*} H^*_n(p):= Z_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)/B_n({\mathcal A}^*_p) \end{align*} $$

called the nth $*$ -homology group of p.

Notation 0.8.

  1. (1) For $c\in Z_n({\mathcal A}^*_p)$ , $[c]$ denotes the homology class of c in $H^*_n(p)$ .

  2. (2) When n is clear from the context, we shall often omit it in $\partial ^i_n$ and in $\partial _n$ , writing simply $\partial ^i$ and $\partial $ .

Definition 0.9. A $1$ -chain $c\in C_1({\mathcal A}^*_p)$ is called a $1$ - $*$ -shell (or just a $1$ -shell) in p if it is of the form

$$ \begin{align*}c =f_0-f_1+f_2, \end{align*} $$

where $f_i$ ’s are $1$ -simplices of p satisfying

$$ \begin{align*} \partial^i f_j = \partial^{j-1} f_i \quad \mbox{whenever}\ 0\leq i < j \leq 2. \end{align*} $$

Hence, for $\operatorname {supp}(c)=\{n_0< n_1< n_2\}$ and $ k\in \{0,1, 2\}$ , it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{supp}(f_k)=\operatorname{supp}(c)\backslash \{n_k\}.\end{align*} $$

Notice that the boundary of any $2$ -simplex is a $1$ -shell. Recall that a notion of an amenable collection of functors into a category is introduced in [Reference Goodrick, Kim, Kolesnikov, Jang, Kim, Lee and Yie5]. Due to the 5 axioms of , it easily follows that ${\mathcal A}^*_p$ forms such a collection of functors into ${\mathcal C}$ . Hence the following corresponding fact holds.

Fact 0.10 [Reference Goodrick, Kim, Kolesnikov, Jang, Kim, Lee and Yie5] or [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3]

$$ \begin{align*} H^*_1(p) = \{ [c] \mid c \mbox{ is a } 1-\mbox{*}\mbox{-shell with}\ \operatorname{supp}(c) = \{ 0, 1, 2 \} \, \}. \end{align*} $$

We now recall basic notions and results that appeared in [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3]. For the rest of this section we assume that p is the strong type of an algebraically closed set.

Definition 0.11.

  1. (1) Let $f:{\mathcal P}(s)\to {\mathcal C}$ be an n-simplex of p. For $u\subseteq s$ with $u = \{ i_0 <\cdots < i_k \}$ , we shall write $f(u)=[a_0 \ldots a_k]_u$ , where each $a_j\models p$ is an algebraically closed tuple as assumed above, if $f(u)=\operatorname {acl}(a_0\ldots a_k)$ , and $\operatorname {acl}(a_j)=f^{ \{ i_j \} } _u (\{i_j\})$ . So, $\{a_0,\ldots ,a_k\}$ is $*$ -independent. Of course, if we write $f(u)\equiv [b_0 \ldots b_k]_u$ , then it means that there is an automorphism sending $a_0\ldots a_k$ to $b_0\ldots b_k$ .

  2. (2) Let $s=fv_{12}-f_{02}+f_{01}$ be a 1- $*$ -shell in p such that $\operatorname {supp}(f_{ij})=\{n_i,n_j\}$ with $n_i< n_j$ for $0\le i< j \le 2$ . Clearly there is a quadruple $(a_0,a_1,a_2,a_3)$ of realizations of p such that $f_{01}(\{n_0,n_1\})\equiv [a_0 a_1]_{\{n_0,n_1\}}$ , $f_{12}(\{n_1,n_2\})\equiv [a_1 a_2]_{\{n_1,n_2\}}$ , and $f_{02}(\{n_0,n_2\})\equiv [a_3 a_2]_{\{n_0,n_2\}}$ . We call this quadruple a representation of s. For any such representation of s, call $a_0$ an initial point, $a_3$ a terminal point, and $(a_0,a_3)$ an endpoint pair of the representation.

We summarize some properties of endpoint pairs of $1$ -shells. We define an equivalence relation $\sim ^*$ on the set of pairs of realizations p as follows: For $a,a',b,b'\models p$ , $(a,b)\sim ^*(a',b')$ if two pairs $(a,b)$ and $(a',b')$ are endpoint pairs of $1$ -shells s and $s'$ respectively such that $[s]=[s']\in H^*_1(p)$ . We write ${\mathcal E}^*=p({\mathcal M})\times p({\mathcal M})/\sim ^*$ . We denote the class of $(a,b)\in p({\mathcal M})\times p({\mathcal M})$ by $[a,b]$ . Now, define a binary operation $+_{{\mathcal E}^*}$ on ${\mathcal E}^*$ as follows: For $[a,b],[b',c']\in {\mathcal E}^*$ , $[a,b]+_{{\mathcal E}^*} [b',c']=[a,c]$ , where $bc\equiv b'c'$ .

Fact 0.12. The operation $+_{{\mathcal E}^*}$ is well-defined, and the pair $({\mathcal E}^*,+_{{\mathcal E}^*})$ forms an abelian group which is isomorphic to $H^*_1(p)$ . More specifically, for $a,b,c\models p$ and $\sigma \in \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M})$ , we have:

  • $[a,b]+[b,c]=[a,c];$

  • $[a,a]$ is the identity element;

  • $-[a,b]=[b,a];$

  • $\sigma ([a,b]):=[\sigma (a),\sigma (b)]=[a,b];$ and

  • $f:{\mathcal E}^*\to H^*_1(p)$ sending $[a,b]\mapsto [s]$ , where $(a,b)$ is an endpoint pair of s, is a group isomorphism.

We identify ${\mathcal E}^*$ and $H^*_1(p)$ .

Fact 0.13. $H_1^*(p)$ is isomorphic to $G/N$ where $G:=\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ and N is the normal subgroup of G consisting of all automorphisms fixing setwise all orbits of elements of $p({\mathcal M})$ under the action of $G'$ (so $G/N$ does not depend on the choice of a monster model). Hence $H_1^*(p)$ does not depend on the choice of and we write $H_1(p)$ for $H_1^*(p)$ .

Fact 0.14. Let p be the fixed strong type of an algebraically closed set.

  1. (1) Let be an independence relation satisfying the 5 basic axioms. Let $a,b \models p$ . Then the following are equivalent.

    1. (a) $[a,b]=0$ in $H_1(p);$

    2. (b) There is a balanced-chain-walk from a to b, i.e., there are some $n\geq 0$ and a finite sequence $(d_i)_{0\le i\le 2n+2}$ of realizations of p satisfying the following conditions:

      1. (i) $d_0=a$ , and $d_{2n+2}=b;$

      2. (ii) $\{d_{j},d_{j+1}\}$ is $*$ -independent for each $j\le 2n+1;$ and

      3. (iii) there is a bijection

        $$ \begin{align*}\sigma:\{0,1,\ldots,n\}\to\{0,1,\ldots,n\}\end{align*} $$
        such that $d_{2i} d_{2i+1}\equiv d_{2\sigma (i)+2}d_{2\sigma (i)+1}$ for $ i \le n;$

    3. (c) There are some $n\geq 0$ and finite sequences $(d_i:0\le i\le n)$ , $(d^j_i: i< n,\ 1\le j\le 3)$ of realizations of p such that $d_0=a$ , $d_n=b$ , and for each $i< n$ , $d_id^1_i\equiv d^3_id^2_i$ , $d^1_id^2_i\equiv d_{i+1}d^3_i$ .

    4. (d) $h(a)=b$ for some h in the commutator subgroup of $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ .

    In particular, if $a\equiv ^L b$ then $[a,b]=0\in H_1(p)$ .

  2. (2) The following are equivalent.

    1. (a) $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is abelian;

    2. (b) For all $a,b \models p$ , $[a,b]=0$ in $H_1(p)$ if and only if $a \equiv ^L b$ .

  3. (3) p is a Lascar type (i.e., $a\equiv ^Lb$ for any $a,b\models p)$ if and only if $H_1(p)$ is trivial and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is abelian.

Remark 0.15. (1) Assume that $p(x)$ is the type of a small model. Then for any $M, N\models p$ , the equivalence classes of (equality of) Lascar types of M and N are interdefinable: Let $M\equiv ^L M'$ and $MN\equiv M'N'$ . It suffices to show that $N\equiv ^L N'$ . Now there is $f\in \operatorname {Autf}({\mathcal M})$ such that $f(M')=M$ . Let $N'':=f(N')$ so that $N''\equiv ^LN'$ and $MN\equiv MN''$ . Hence $N\equiv _{M}N''$ and $N\equiv ^L N''\equiv ^L N'$ as wanted. When p is a type of any tuple we will see that the same holds if $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is abelian (Remark 1.10).

(2) Notice that for tuples $a,b\models p$ , we have:

  • (**) there is a commutator f in $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ such that $f(a)=b$ if and only if there are $d^1,d^2,d^3\models p$ such that $ad^1\equiv d^3d^2$ and $bd^3\equiv d^1d^2$ .

Now we recall the following fact of compact group theory by M. Gotô from [Reference Hofmann and Morris6, Theorem 9.2]: Assume $(F,\cdot )$ is a compact connected topological group. Then $F'$ , the commutator subgroup of F, is simply the set of commutators in F, i.e.,

$$ \begin{align*}F'=\{ f\cdot g \cdot f^{-1}\cdot g^{-1}\mid f,g \in F\}.\end{align*} $$

It follows that $F'$ is a closed subgroup of F, and both $F'$ and $F/F'$ are compact connected groups as well.

Due to the theorem we newly observe here that if T is G-compact then in Fact 0.14(1)(c), we can choose $n=1$ : If the equivalent conditions in Fact 0.14(1) hold, then we have that $h(a)=b$ for some h in the commutator subgroup of $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ . Now, as T is G-compact, we get by Gotô’s Theorem that h is a commutator in $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ , so, by $(**)$ , there are $d^1,d^2,d^3\models p$ such that $bd^3\equiv d^1d^2$ .

1. Amalgamation properties of strong types in simple theories

Note that if T is simple then since T is G-compact, each $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)$ is a compact (i.e., quasi-compact and Hausdorff) connected group, so it is divisible (see [Reference Hofmann and Morris6, Theorem 9.35]). In this section we assume T is simple (except Remark 1.10 and Example 1.11), and the independence is nonforking independence. It is still an open question whether the strong type p is necessarily a Lascar type. If so, then the following theorem follows easily by the $3$ -amalgamation of Lascar types in simple theories. But regardless of the answer to the question, p has the following amalgamation property. We do not assume here that a realization of p is algebraically closed.

Theorem 1.1 (Divisible amalgamation)

Let p be a strong type in a simple theory. Let $a,b\models p$ and . Then for each $n\geq 1$ , there are independent $a=a_0,a_1,\ldots ,a_n=b$ such that $a_0a_1\equiv a_ia_{i+1}$ for every $i< n$ .

Proof Clearly we can assume $n>1$ . Note that there is $f \in \operatorname {Aut}(p)$ such that $b=f(a)$ . Then since $G:=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is divisible, there is $h \in \operatorname {Aut}(p)$ such that $[h]^n=[f]$ (in G). Put $c=h(a)$ . Now there is $c_1\equiv ^L c$ such that . Then there is $h' \in \operatorname {Autf}^1(p)$ such that $h'(c)=c_1$ . Let $g=h'\circ h$ . Then $[g]=[h]$ so $[g]^n=[f]$ too, and $g(a)=c_1$ .

Claim. We can find additional elements $c_2,\ldots ,c_n$ such that $\{a=c_0,c_1,\ldots ,c_n,b\}$ is independent, and for each $1\leq m\leq n$ , $c_0c_1\equiv c_{m-1}c_{m}$ and there is $h_m\in \operatorname {Aut}(p)$ such that $[h_m]=[g]^m$ in G, and $h_m(a)=c_m$ .

Proof of the Claim For an induction hypothesis, assume for $1\leq m< n$ we have found $a=c_0,c_1,\ldots , c_m$ such that $\{c_0,c_1,\ldots ,c_m,b\}$ is independent and $c_0c_1\equiv c_{i-1}c_{i}$ for all $1\leq i\leq m$ and there is $h_m\in \operatorname {Aut}(p)$ such that $[h_m]=[g]^m$ in G, and $h_m(c_0)=c_m$ .

Notice now that then $c^{\prime }_m:=g^m(a)\equiv ^L h_m(a)=c_m$ . Put $c^{\prime }_{m+1}:=g(c^{\prime }_m)=g^{m+1}(a)$ . Then there is $c_{m+1}$ such that $c_mc_{m+1}\equiv ^L c^{\prime }_mc^{\prime }_{m+1}$ , and $\{c_0,c_1,\ldots ,c_{m+1},b\}$ is independent. Since $c_{m+1}\equiv ^L c^{\prime }_{m+1}$ , there is $h'' \in \operatorname {Autf}^1(p)$ , such that $h''(c^{\prime }_{m+1})=c_{m+1}$ and so for $h_{m+1}:=h''\circ g^{m+1}$ , we have $h_{m+1}(a)=c_{m+1}$ and $[g]^{m+1}= [h_{m+1}]$ in G. Moreover the equality of types $c_mc_{m+1}\equiv c^{\prime }_mc^{\prime }_{m+1} \equiv c_0c_1$ is witnessed by $g^m$ . Hence the claim is proved.

Notice that $ c_n=h_n(a)$ with $[h_n]=[g]^n=[f]$ . Hence $c_n\equiv ^L b=f(a)$ . Then, by $3$ -amalgamation, we find $b' \models \operatorname {tp}(b/a) \cup \operatorname {tp}(c_n/c_1\dots c_{n-1})$ with . Then the automorphic images of $c_1\dots c_{n-1}$ (rename them as $a_1\ldots a_{n-1}$ ) under a map sending $b'$ to b over a satisfy the conditions of the theorem.⊣

Now we assume that p is the type of an algebraically closed tuple. For $a,a'\models p$ , we have a better description of $[a,a']=0$ in $H_1(p).$

Proposition 1.2. For $a,a'\models p$ , the following are equivalent.

  1. (1) $[a,a']=0$ in $H_1(p)$ , equivalently there is h in the commutator subgroup of $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ such that $h(a)=a'$ .

  2. (2) There are $b,c,d\models p$ such that each of $\{a,b,c,d\}$ , $\{a', b,c,d\}$ is independent, and $ab\equiv cd$ , $bd\equiv a'c$ .

Proof (1) $\Rightarrow $ (2) Since T is G-compact, by Remark 0.15(2) there are $b',c',d'\models p$ such that $ab'\equiv c'd'$ and $b'd'\equiv a'c'$ . Now there is $b\equiv ^L b'$ such that . Hence, by $3$ -amalgamation, there is $d_0\equiv ^L d'$ such that $d_0\models \operatorname {tp}(d'/b) \cup \operatorname {tp}(d''/b')$ and , where $d''b'\equiv d'b$ and $d''\equiv ^L d'\equiv ^L d_0$ . By extension there is no harm in assuming that .

Now since $a'c'\equiv b'd'$ , there are $a''c$ such that $b'd'bd_0\equiv a'c'a''c$ . Hence, $c\equiv ^L c'$ , $a''\equiv ^L a'$ , and . Again by extension, we can further assume that . Moreover, since $ab'\equiv c'd'$ , there is $d_1\equiv ^L d'$ such that $ab'b\equiv c'd'd_1$ . Then since with $c\equiv ^Lc$ , and , again by $3$ -amalgamation we can assume that $c'd_1\equiv cd_1$ and .

Now the situation is that , , and . Moreover, $d_0\equiv ^L d'\equiv ^L d_1$ . Hence, by $3$ -amalgamation, we have $d\models \operatorname {tp}(d_0/aa'b)\cup \operatorname {tp}(d_1/c)$ and . Therefore, each of $\{a,b,c,d\}$ , $\{a', b,c,d\}$ is independent. Moreover, due to above combinations

$$ \begin{align*}ab\equiv c'd_1\equiv cd_1\equiv cd,\end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*}bd\equiv bd_0\equiv bd'\equiv b'd''\equiv b'd_0\equiv a'c\end{align*} $$

as wanted.

(2) $\Rightarrow $ (1) Clear by Remark 0.15(2).⊣

From now until Theorem 1.8, we assume that $p(x)$ is the ( strong ) type of a small model, and all tuples $a,b,c,\dots $ realize p, so all are universes of models. Hence, by Fact 0.4, $\operatorname {Autf}^1(p)=\operatorname {Autf}_{\operatorname {fix}}(p)$ and $(\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)\cong )\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {fix}}(p)=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(p)$ , which we simply write $\operatorname {Autf}(p)$ and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(p)$ , respectively. Moreover, $H_1(p)\cong \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(p)/(\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(p))'$ and hence it is a compact connected (so divisible) abelian group.

Definition 1.3. Let $r(x,y), s(x,y)$ be types completing .

  1. (1) We say p has abelian (or commutative) amalgamation of r and s, if there are independent $a,b,c,d\models p$ such that $ab,cd\models r$ and $ac, bd\models s$ .We say p has abelian amalgamation if it has abelian amalgamation for any such completions r and s.

  2. (2) We say p has reversible amalgamation of r and s if there are independent $a,b,c,d\models p$ such that $ab,dc\models r$ and $ac, db\models s$ .We say p has reversible amalgamation if it has reversible amalgamation for any such completions r and s.

Lemma 1.4. The following are equivalent.

  1. (1) The type p has abelian amalgamation.

  2. (2) Let $r(x,y), s(x,y)$ be any types completing , and let $a,b,c\models p$ be independent such that $ac\models s$ and $ab\models r$ . Then there is $d\models p $ independent from $abc$ such that $cd\models r$ and $bd \models s$ .

Proof (1) $\Rightarrow $ (2) By (1), there are $b_0, d_0\models p$ such that $\{a,c,b_0,d_0\}$ is independent, $ab_0,cd_0\models r$ , and $ac, b_0d_0\models s$ . Hence, there is $d_1$ such that $abd_1\equiv ab_0d_0$ . Now by $3$ -amalgamation over the model a, there is

$$ \begin{align*}d\models \operatorname{tp}(d_0/a;c) \cup \operatorname{tp}(d_1/a;b),\end{align*} $$

such that $\{a,b,c,d\}$ is independent. Moreover, $cd\equiv cd_0\models r$ and $bd\equiv bd_1\equiv b_0d_0 \models s$ , as desired.

(2) $\Rightarrow $ (1) Clear.⊣

By the same proof we obtain the following too.

Lemma 1.5. The following are equivalent.

  1. (1) The type p has reversible amalgamation.

  2. (2) Let $r(x,y), s(x,y)$ be any types completing , and let $a,b,c\models p$ be independent such that $ac\models s$ and $ab\models r$ . Then there is $d\models p $ independent from $abc$ such that $dc\models r$ and $db \models s$ .

Theorem 1.6. The following are equivalent.

  1. (1) $ \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(p)(\cong \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T))$ is abelian.

  2. (2) p has abelian amalgamation.

Proof (1) $\Rightarrow $ (2) Assume (1). Thus for $G:=\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ , we have $G'\leq \operatorname {Autf}(p)$ . Now let $r(x,y)$ and $s(x,y)$ be some complete types containing . There are independent $a,a', b,d,c\models p$ such that $ab,cd\models r$ and $bd, a'c\models s$ . Hence there is a commutator $f\in G'\leq \operatorname {Autf}(p)$ such that $f(a)=a'$ , so $a\equiv ^L a'$ . Then by $3$ -amalgamation of $\operatorname {Lstp}(a)$ , there is

$$ \begin{align*}a_0\models \operatorname{tp}(a/bd)\cup \operatorname{tp}(a'/c)\end{align*} $$

such that $\{a_0,b,c,d\}$ is independent, $a_0b\equiv ab\models r$ , and $a_0c\equiv a'c\models s$ . Therefore p has commutative amalgamation.

(2) $\Rightarrow $ (1) To show (1), due to Fact 0.14(2) it is enough to prove that if $a,a'\models p$ and $[a,a']=0\in H_1(p)$ ( $\dagger $ ), then $a\equiv ^L a'$ . Now assume (2) and ( $\dagger $ ). Thus, by Proposition 1.2, there are $b,c,d\models p$ such that each of the sets $\{a,b,c,d\}$ and $\{a', b,c,d\}$ is independent, $ab\equiv cd$ , and $bd\equiv a'c$ . Now by Lemma 1.4 and extension there is $c'\models p$ such that and $ac'\equiv bd\equiv a'c$ and $c'd\equiv ab\equiv cd$ . Then, since d is a model, we have $c \equiv ^L c'$ , and there is $a''$ such that $a'c\equiv _da''c'$ , so $a\equiv ^L a''$ and $a''\equiv _{c'}a$ . Since $c'$ is a model as well, we conclude that $a'\equiv ^L a''\equiv ^L a$ .⊣

A proof similar to that of the above Theorem 1.6 (2) $\Rightarrow $ (1) applying Fact 0.14(1)(b) gives the following as well.

Proposition 1.7. If p has reversible amalgamation, then $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(p)$ is abelian (equivalently, p has abelian amalgamation).

Proof Assume that p has reversible amalgamation, and $[a,b]=0\in H_1(p)$ for $a,b\models p$ ( $\dagger $ ). As before it is enough to prove that $a\equiv ^L b$ . It follows from the extension axiom for Lascar types together with Fact 0.14(1)(b), there are $b'\equiv ^L b$ and a finite independent sequence $(d_i)_{0\le i\le 2n+2}$ of realizations of p satisfying the following conditions:

  1. (i) $d_0=a$ , $d_{2n+2}=b'$ ; and

  2. (ii) there is a bijection

    $$ \begin{align*}\sigma:\{0,1,\ldots,n\}\to\{0,1,\ldots,n\}\end{align*} $$
    such that $d_{2i} d_{2i+1}\equiv d_{2\sigma (i)+2}d_{2\sigma (i)+1}$ for $ i \le n$ .

In other words, there is an independent balanced chain-walk from a to $b'$ , and it suffices to prove $a\equiv ^L b'$ . Notice that, by reversible amalgamation, condition (2) of Lemma 1.5 implies that in the above chain-walk two adjacent edges can be swapped with sign reversed (i.e., for say $d_jd_{j+1}$ and $d_{j+1}d_{j+2}$ there is such that $d_jd^{\prime }_{j+1}\equiv d_{j+2}d_{j+1}$ and $d^{\prime }_{j+1}d_{j+2}\equiv d_{j+1}d_{j}$ ). By iterating this process one can transfer the chain-walk to another balanced chain-walk $(d^{\prime }_i)_{0\le i\le 2n+2}$ from a to $b'$ such that the walk has a Lascar pattern, i.e., the bijection $\sigma $ for the new walk is the identity map. Hence it follows $d^{\prime }_{2i}\equiv _{d^{\prime }_{2i+1}} d^{\prime }_{2i+2}$ for $i\leq n$ , and since each $d^{\prime }_{2i+1}$ is a model, we have $a=d^{\prime }_0\equiv ^Lb'$ , as wanted.⊣

A stronger consequence is obtained.

Theorem 1.8. The strong type p is a Lascar type if and only if p has reversible amalgamation.

Proof ( $\Rightarrow $ ) It follows from $3$ -amalgamation of Lascar strong types.

( $\Leftarrow $ ) Assume p has reversible amalgamation. Due to Fact 0.14(3) and Proposition 1.7, it suffices to show $H_1(p)$ is trivial. Let an arbitrary $[s]\in H_1(p)$ be given, and let $[a,b']=[s]$ for $a,b'\models p$ . Then, for any $b\equiv ^L b'$ with , we have $[a,b]=[a,b']+[b',b]=[s]+0=[s]$ . Similarly, for $c\equiv ^L b$ with , we have $[b,c]=0$ in $H_1(p)$ . Now reversible amalgamation (or Lemma 1.5) says that $[s]=[a,b]+[b,c]=[c,b]+[b,a]=-[s]$ . Hence $[s]+[s]=0$ . Since $H_1(p)$ is compact and connected so divisible, any element in $H_1(p)$ is divisible by $2$ . Therefore, $H_1(p)=0$ by what we have just proved.⊣

Question 1.9. Can the same results hold if p is the type of an algebraically closed tuple (not necessarily a model) in a simple theory? The answer to this question is yes if any two Lascar equivalence classes in p are interdefinable, since essentially this property (Remark 0.15(1)) implied the results in this section when p is the type of a model. At least we can show the following remark.

Remark 1.10. Let T be any theory, and let a realization of p be any tuple. If $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is abelian then any two Lascar equivalence classes in p are interdefinable: Let $a,b\models p$ , and $f\in \operatorname {Aut}(p)$ . Assume $f(a)\equiv ^L a$ . We want to show the same holds for b. Now there is $g\in \operatorname {Aut}(p)$ such that $g(a)=b$ . Since $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is abelian, we have $f(b)=f(g(a))\equiv ^L g(f(a))\equiv ^L g(a)=b$ .

Notice that $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is the group of automorphic permutations of the Lascar classes in p. Hence, if $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is abelian, then $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(p)\in \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is determined by the pair of Lascar classes of c and $f(c)$ for some (any) $c\models p$ .

Example 1.11. Let $({\mathcal M},<)$ be a monster model of $\operatorname {Th}({\mathbb Q},<)$ . Then thorn-independence in ${\mathcal M}$ coincides with $\operatorname {acl}$ -independence. We can also consider a notion of reversible amalgamation using thorn independence instead of nonforking independence. Note that the Lascar group of $\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M})$ is trivial because of o-minimality, but the reversible amalgamation for fails.

Let p be the unique $1$ -type over $\emptyset (=\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset ))$ . Consider two types $r(x,y)=\{x< y\}$ and $s(x,y)=\{y< x\}$ completing . Then p has no reversible amalgamation of r and s. Suppose $a,b,c,d\models p$ such that $ab,dc\models r$ and $ac,db\models s$ . Then $a< b< d< c < a$ , and there are no such elements. Thus, a type of a model does not have reversible amalgamation either.

2. Relativized Lascar Galois groups and algebraicity

As mentioned in the introduction, this section does not make any use of the homology groups and thus can be read independently from Section 1. Recall that throughout we assume that $\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )=\operatorname {dcl}(\emptyset )$ . In Remark 1.8 from [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3] it was noticed that if $\operatorname {tp}(a)$ is a Lascar type, and a finite tuple c is algebraic over a then $\operatorname {tp}(ac)$ is also a Lascar type, and hence if additionally T is G-compact then $\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ is also a Lascar type. In other words, if $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\operatorname {tp}(a))$ is trivial, then $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ is trivial when T is G-compact. It seems natural to ask whether, more generally, $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\operatorname {tp}(a))$ and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ must be always isomorphic in a G-compact T. In general, the answer turns out to be negative (see Section 3), but we obtain some positive results if, instead of looking at $\operatorname {acl}(a)$ , we add only a finite part of it to a.

Remark 2.1. The only properties of Lascar equivalence $\equiv ^L$ in G-compact theories used in this section are that it is a bounded $\emptyset $ -type definable equivalence relation and that for any compatible tuples a and b with $a\equiv ^L b$ we also have $a_0\equiv b_0$ for all corresponding subtuples $a_0\subseteq a$ and $b_0\subseteq b$ . As KP-equivalence $\equiv ^{KP}$ has these properties in any theory, all the main results of this section: Theorem 2.6, Corollary 2.9, Propositions 2.12 and 2.14, and Corollaries 2.16 and 2.20 hold without the G-compactness assumption if we replace the Lascar equivalence by KP-equivalence, and relativized Lascar groups $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)$ by relativized Kim–Pillay groups $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {KP}}^{\lambda }(p):=\operatorname {Aut}(p)/\operatorname {Autf}^{\lambda }_{\operatorname {KP}}(p)$ , where $\operatorname {Autf}^{\lambda }_{\operatorname {KP}}(p)$ is defined as the group of automorphisms in $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ fixing the KP-type of any $\lambda $ -many realizations of p.

For the whole Section 2, we fix the following notation.

Notation 2.2. Assume that $p=\operatorname {tp}(a)$ and $\bar {p}=\operatorname {tp}(ac)$ , where $c\subseteq \operatorname {acl}(a)$ is finite. Consider the natural projection $\pi _{\lambda }:\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(\bar {p})\to \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)$ , and put $ \pi :=\pi _1$ . We denote the kernel of $\pi $ by K. Denote by E the relation of being Lascar-equivalent (formally, E depends on the length of tuples on which we consider it). Let $ac_1,\dots ,ac_{N}$ be a tuple of representatives of all E-classes in $\bar {p}$ in which the first coordinate is equal to a (so $N\leq $ the number of realizations of $\operatorname {tp} (c/a)$ ), and for any $a'\models p$ , let $a'c^{a'}_1,\dots ,a'c^{a'}_{N}$ be its conjugate by an automorphism sending a to $a'$ .

Example 2.3. We give an example of a structure and a type p such that $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^2(p)$ are distinct. Let $\mathbb {C}=\mathbb {R}\times \mathbb {R}$ be a Euclidean plane. Let $\Lambda =\{r\pi \mid r\in \mathbb {Q}\cap (0,\frac {1}{2}]\}$ . For $q\in \Lambda $ , define $R_q(xy, zw)$ on $\mathbb {C}^4$ such that $R_q(ab, cd)$ iff $a\ne b$ , $c\ne d$ , and either the lines $L(ab)$ containing $a,b$ and $L(cd)$ are parallel, or the smaller angle between $L(ab)$ and $L(cd)$ is $\leq q$ . Also define a family of ternary relations $S_r(x,y,z)$ , for $r\in \mathbb {Q}^+$ , so that $S_r(a,b,c)$ if and only if $|ab|< r|ac|$ .

Consider a model $M=(\mathbb {C}; R_q(xy,zw); S_r(x,y,z))_{q\in \Lambda ,r\in \mathbb Q^+}$ . Then $F(xy,zw):=\bigwedge _{q\in \Lambda }R_q(xy,zw)$ is an $\emptyset $ -type-definable bounded equivalence relation in $T=\mbox {Th}(M)$ , and each class corresponds to a class of lines whose slopes are infinitesimally close.

Let $\mathcal R$ be a sufficiently saturated model of the reals, $\mathcal {C}=\mathcal R^2$ , $N\models T$ , a a finite tuple in N, and $c\in N$ an element. Then for any $b\in \mathcal {C}$ that has the same quantifier-free type as a there is $d\in \mathcal {C}$ such that $ac$ and $bd$ have the same quantifier-free type.

Let p be the unique complete $1$ -type over $\emptyset $ . Indeed p is a Lascar type, so $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is trivial. On the other hand, a rotation of $\mathcal {C}$ around a point in $\mathbb {C}$ belongs to $\operatorname {Autf}^1(p)$ but does not belong to $\operatorname {Autf}^2(p)$ . One can show that $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^2(p)$ is a circle group, and T is G-compact (see Definition 0.1 and Fact 0.2).

In fact for any $n>0$ , and any finite $a_{< n}=a_0\dots a_{n-1}$ and $b_{< n}=b_0\dots b_{n-1}$ ( $a_j, b_j\in \mathcal {C}^1$ ), the following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $a_{< n}\equiv ^L b_{<n}$ .

  2. (2) $F(a_ia_j,b_ib_j)$ for $i< j< n$ .

  3. (3) There is $I=( c^i_{< n}\mid i< \omega )$ such that both $a_{< n}I$ and $b_{< n}I$ are indiscernibles.

It is enough to show $(2)\Rightarrow (3)$ . We write $a_{ij}=a_ia_j$ for $i,j< n$ . We say that $a_0$ , $a_1$ , and $a_2$ are collinear if $F(a_{ij},a_{ik})$ for $\{i,j,k\}=\{0,1,2\}$ . Suppose $F(a_{ij}, b_{ij})$ for all $i<j<n$ . Then there is $d\in \mathcal {C}$ such that $d,a_i,b_i$ are collinear for each $i< n$ . (Even when $F(a_ib_i, a_jb_j)$ holds for each $i< j< n$ , there still is such $d\in {\mathcal M}$ , by compactness.) In other words, there is a perspective point d for the sets $a_{< n}$ and $b_{< n}$ in $\mathcal {C}$ .

Let $N\prec \mathcal R$ be a small elementary substructure containing all coordinates of the points $a_{< n}\cup b_{< n}$ . Consider a complete type $p_{\infty }(x)=\{x>a:a\in N\}$ over N in the ordered ring language. Let $\{\alpha _i\mid i<\omega \}$ be a Morley sequence of realizations $p_{\infty }$ such that $\operatorname {tp}(\alpha _i/N\alpha _{< i})$ is an heir extension of $p_{\infty }$ so that $\alpha _i$ is infinite with respect to $\operatorname {dcl}(N\alpha _{< i})$ . Now, we can take I to be the sequence of scaled by $\alpha _i$ copies of $a_{< n}$ relative to the point d: $c^i_{j} = \alpha _i(a_j-d)+d$ .

Let us recall basic definitions and facts on covering maps between topological groups (see for example [Reference Hofmann and Morris6]).

Remark 2.4.

  • Let $X, Y$ be topological spaces, and let $f:X\to Y$ be a continuous surjective map. We call f a ( k- ) covering map if for each $y\in Y$ there is an open set V containing y such that $f^{-1}(V)$ is a union of (k-many) disjoint open sets in X, and f induces a homeomorphism between each such open set and V. We call f a local homeomorphism if for any $x\in X$ , there is an open set U containing x such that $f\restriction U:U\to f(U)$ is a homeomorphism. Obviously a covering map is a local homeomorphism. Conversely, if both X and Y are compact, then a local homeomorphism is a covering map. We call X a covering space of Y if there is a covering map from X to Y.

  • Let G be topological group, and let H be a normal subgroup of G such that $G/H$ with its quotient topology is also a topological group, and the projection map $\mbox {pr}: G\to G/H$ is an open continuous homomorphism. Recall that $\mbox {pr}$ is a covering map if and only if H is a discrete subgroup. If G is compact, then H is discrete if and only if H is finite, and hence iff $\mbox {pr}$ is a covering map.Assume F is another topological group and $f:G\to F$ is a continuous surjective homomorphism. If G is compact and F is Hausdorff, then f induces an isomorphism between the compact topological groups $G/\operatorname {Ker}(f)$ and F.

  • Assume T is G-compact. By the above, $\pi _{\lambda }$ is a covering homomorphism iff the kernel of $\pi _{\lambda }$ is finite. In particular, we shall show that $\pi =\pi _1$ is a covering homomorphism (Corollary 2.9).

If T is G-compact then the Lascar equivalence E is $\emptyset $ -type-definable (see [Reference Kim7, Proposition 20]), and we can assume any formula $\varphi $ in E is symmetric (i.e., $\varphi (\bar z,\bar w)\models \varphi (\bar w,\bar z)$ ).

Lemma 2.5. Assume T is G-compact. There is a formula $\alpha (xy,x'y')\in E(xy,x'y')$ such that if $\bar p(xy)\wedge \bar p(x'y') \wedge \alpha (xy,x'y')\wedge E(x,x')$ holds then $\models E(xy,x'y').$

Proof Notice that the type

$$ \begin{align*}E(xy,x'y')\wedge\exists zwz'w'\equiv xyx'y' \left(\bigvee_{ 1\leq i\ne j\leq N} (E(zw,ac_i)\wedge E(z'w',ac_j))\right)\end{align*} $$

is inconsistent, and choose $\alpha (xy,x'y')\in E(xy,x'y')$ so that the type

$$ \begin{align*}\alpha(xy,x'y')\wedge\exists zwz'w'\equiv xyx'y' \left(\bigvee_{1\leq i\ne j\leq N} (E(zw,ac_i)\wedge E(z'w',ac_j))\right)\end{align*} $$

is inconsistent. Now, if $\bar p(xy)\wedge \bar p(x'y') \wedge \alpha (xy,x'y')\wedge E(x,x')$ holds, then we can find $c'a'c''$ such that $ac'a'c'' \equiv xyx'y'$ , and then $a'\equiv ^L a$ so $a'c'' \equiv ^L ac_i$ for some i, and also $ac' \equiv ^L ac_j$ for some j, but, by the choice of $\alpha $ , $i=j$ so $ac'\equiv ^L a'c''$ , so $xy \equiv ^L x'y'$ .⊣

The following theorem and its proof will use the setting described in Notation 2.2.

Theorem 2.6. If T is G-compact, then K is finite.

Proof Assume T is G-compact. Since E is transitive, there is $\phi (xy,x'y')\in E(xy,x'y')$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\phi(xy,zw)\wedge \phi(x'y',zw)\vdash \alpha(xy,x'y')\ \ (*),\end{align*} $$

where $\alpha \in E$ is the formula given by Lemma 2.5.

Let $(a_{\ell })_{\ell \in I}$ be a small set of representatives of E-classes of realizations of p. For any $a'c'\models \bar {p}$ , there are $\ell \in I$ and $1\leq j\leq N$ such that $\models E(a'c',a_{\ell }c_j^{a_{\ell }})$ , so $\models \phi (a'c',a_{\ell }c_j^{a_{\ell }})$ . Hence, by compactness, there are $a_0,\dots ,a_k\models p$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\bar{p}(xy) \vdash \bigvee\{ \phi(xy,a_ic^{a_i}_j)\mid i\leq k;\ 1\leq j\leq N \}\ \ (**).\end{align*} $$

Claim 2.7. Let $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})\in K$ . For each $a_ic_j^{a_i}$ chosen above, there is a unique $a_ic^{a_i}_{j'}$ with $ 1\leq j'\leq N$ such that $\phi (f(a_ic^{a_i}_j), a_ic^{a_i}_{j'})$ holds. Such a $j'$ does not depend on the choice of a representative of $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})$ .

Proof Notice that $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})\in K$ implies $E(f(a_i),a_i)$ , so $E(f(a_ic^{a_i}_j), a_ic^{a_i}_{j'})$ holds for some $j'$ . Now if $\phi (f(a_ic^{a_i}_j), a_ic^{a_i}_{j''})$ holds as well, then due to $(*)$ (with the symmetry of the formulas) and Lemma 2.5, we must have $j'=j''$ . The second statement of the claim follows similarly.⊣

Claim 2.8. Let $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})$ , $g/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})\in K$ . Assume that the permutations of tuples $a_ic_j^{a_i}$ by f and g described in the claim above are the same. Then $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})=g/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})$ .

Proof Let $a'c'\models \bar p$ . By $(**)$ , there is some $a_ic_j^{a_i}$ such that $\phi (a'c', a_ic_j^{a_i})$ holds. Hence, $\phi (f(a'c'), f(a_ic_j^{a_i}))$ and $\phi (g(a'c'), g(a_ic_j^{a_i}))$ hold. Moreover, by the previous claim with our assumption, there is $ j'\leq N$ such that $\phi (f(a_ic^{a_i}_j), a_ic^{a_i}_{j'})$ and $\phi (g(a_ic^{a_i}_j), a_ic^{a_i}_{j'})$ hold.

Then, again due to $(*)$ and Lemma 2.5, $f(a_ic^{a_i}_j)\equiv ^L g(a_ic^{a_i}_j)$ since $f(a_i)\equiv ^Lg(a_i)\equiv ^L a_i$ . Hence, there is $h\in \operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar p)$ such that $f(a_ic^{a_i}_j)=hg(a_ic^{a_i}_j)$ . Now by $(*)$ again, $\alpha (f(a'c'), hg(a'c'))$ holds, and, since $f(a')\equiv ^Lhg(a')\equiv ^L a'$ , we have $f(a'c')\equiv ^L hg(a'c')\equiv ^L g(a'c')$ . We conclude that $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})=g/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})$ .⊣

As there are only finitely many permutations of $a_ic_j^{a_i}$ ( $i\leq k$ , $ 1\leq j\leq N$ ), K is finite.⊣

By Remark 2.4, we have the following.

Corollary 2.9. If T is G-compact then $\pi :\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(\bar {p})\to \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(p)$ is a covering homomorphism.

Example 2.10. Consider the following model:

$$ \begin{align*}M=((M_1,S_1,\{g^1_n\mid 0< n\}),(M_2,S_2,\{g^2_n\mid 0< n\}),\delta),\end{align*} $$

a 2-sorted structure. Here $M_1, M_2$ are disjoint unit circles. For $i=1,2$ , $S_i$ is a ternary relation on $M_i$ such that $S_i(a,b,c)$ holds iff $a,b,c$ are distinct and b comes before c going clockwise around $M_i$ from a; and $g^i_n$ is the clockwise rotation of $M_i$ by $\frac {2\pi }{n}$ -radians. The map $\delta :M_1\to M_2$ is a double covering, i.e., if we identify each $M_i$ as the unit circle in $xy$ -plane centered at $0$ , then $\delta $ is given by $(\cos t, \sin t)\mapsto (\cos 2t,\sin 2t).$ By arguments similar to those described in [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3] for $M_i$ , it follows that $T=\operatorname {Th}(M)$ is G-compact, and, in T, $\emptyset =\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset )$ . Let ${\mathcal M}_1,{\mathcal M}_2$ be saturated models of $M_1,M_2$ respectively. For any $a_i,a^{\prime }_i\in {\mathcal M}_i$ , we have $a_i\equiv a^{\prime }_i$ ; and $a_i\equiv ^La^{\prime }_i$ iff they are infinitesimally close. Now, given $a\in M_2$ , there are two antipodal $c_1,c_2\in M_1$ such that $\delta (c_i)=a$ . Then $c_i\in \operatorname {acl}(a)$ and $ac_1\equiv ac_2$ , but $ac_1\not \equiv ^L ac_2$ . For $p=\operatorname {tp}(a)$ and $\bar p=\operatorname {tp}(ac_1)$ , $\pi :\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(\bar p)\to \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(p)$ is a 2-covering homomorphism of circle groups. Notice that for any $n>2$ ,

$$ \begin{align*}\delta(y)=x \wedge \delta(y')=x' \wedge (S_1(y,y',g_n^1(y)) \vee S_1(y',y,g_n^1(y')))\end{align*} $$

serves as the formula $\alpha (xy,x'y')$ in Lemma 2.5.

Question 2.11. If T is G-compact, then is the kernel of the projection $\pi _{\lambda }:\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(\bar {p})\to \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)$ finite as well for $\lambda>1$ ? Is T being G-compact essential in Theorem 2.6?

We have a partial answer to the second question above. Namely, we also get that K is finite when we replace the assumption of G-compactness by abelianity of $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {p})$ .

Proposition 2.12. If $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {p})$ is abelian, then $|K|=N$ .

Proof If $f/\operatorname {Autf}^1(\bar {p})\in K$ , then $f(a)\equiv ^L a$ , so there is another representative $f'$ fixing a. Now, since $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {p})$ is abelian, by Remark 1.10, the class of an automorphism $f'$ fixing a depends only on the Lascar type of $f'(ac)=af'(c)$ for which, due to our choice, there are exactly N possibilities.⊣

We will investigate the epimorphism $\pi $ further assuming the theory T satisfies, in addition to G-compactness, some other nice hypotheses, obtaining better versions of Theorem 2.6 in these cases.

Remark 2.13.

  1. (1) Let X be an $\emptyset $ -type-definable set, and let F be a bounded $\emptyset $ -type-definable equivalence relation on X. Recall the logic topology on $X/F$ : A subset of $X/F$ is closed if and only if its pre-image in X is type-definable over some parameters. It follows that $X/F$ is compact with the logic topology.

  2. (2) Assume T is G-compact. By the natural embedding, $G:=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ can be considered as a subgroup of $\operatorname {Homeo}(p({\mathcal M})/E)$ , where $p({\mathcal M})/E$ is equipped with the logic topology. Moreover, for $x:=a/E$ and $G_x:=\{ g\in G\mid g. x= x\}$ (the stabilizer subgroup of G at x), we have that $G/G_x$ as a homogeneous coset space with the quotient topology and $p({\mathcal M})/E$ with the logic topology are homeomorphic. Needless to say, analogous facts hold for $\bar p$ .

  3. (3) Let $X,Y$ be topological spaces. Recall that if X is path-connected then so is any quotient space of X. Moreover, if X is a connected covering space of Y, then X is path-connected if and only if Y is.

  4. (4) Given a covering map $\delta :X\to Y$ , the unique path-lifting property says that for any $x_0\in X$ , $y_0\in Y$ with $\delta (x_0)=y_0$ , and any path $\gamma $ in Y starting at $y_0$ (i.e., $\gamma :[0,1]\to Y$ is continuous and $\gamma (0)=y_0$ ), there is a unique path $\gamma '$ starting at $x_0$ such that $\delta \circ \gamma '=\gamma $ .

Proposition 2.14. Assume T is G-compact and consider the canonical restriction map $\delta :\bar {p}({\mathcal M})/E\to p({\mathcal M})/E$ of compact spaces $\bar {p}({\mathcal M})/E$ , $p({\mathcal M})/E$ equipped with the logic topology. Then $\delta $ is an N-covering map.

Proof Choose $\phi $ as in the proof of Theorem 2.6 and fix $a'c'\models \bar {p}$ . Define $D:=\bar {p}({\mathcal M})\backslash \{a''c''/E:a''c''\models \bar {p}\ \wedge \neg \phi (a''c'',a'c')\}$ . Then D is an open neighborhood of $a'c'/E$ in $\bar {p}({\mathcal M})/E$ . To show that $\delta $ is a covering map, by Remark 2.4, it is enough to see that $\delta $ is injective on D. So choose two pairs $a^0c^0,a^1c^1 \models \bar {p}$ such that $a^0c^0/E,a^1c^1/E \in D$ and $\delta (a^0c^0/E)=\delta (a^1c^1/E)$ . Then, by the first condition, $\models \phi (a^0c^0,a'c')\wedge \phi (a^1c^1,a'c')$ , and, by the second one, $E(a^0,a^1)$ . We conclude by the choice of $\phi $ that $a^0c^0/E=a^1c^1/E$ . By our choice of N, we have that $\delta $ is N-covering map.⊣

Observe the following remark on covering maps.

Remark 2.15. Given topological spaces $X,Y$ , suppose that $\delta :X\to Y$ is a k-covering. Put $F:=\{f\in \operatorname {Homeo}(X): \delta \circ f=\delta \}$ .

  1. (1) If Y is path-connected, then $|F|\leq k!$ and this bound is optimal.

  2. (2) If X is path-connected (thus so is Y), then $|F|\le k$ .

Proof We prove (1) first. It is enough to show that if $f(\in F)$ fixes some fiber $\delta ^{-1}(y)$ with $y\in Y$ pointwise $(*)$ , then f is identity. Fix $x'\in X$ and let $y'=\delta (x')$ . Now there is a path $\alpha $ from y to $y'$ . Then, by the unique path-lifting property, there is a unique path $\beta $ starting at x, say, and ending at $x'$ such that $\delta \circ \beta =\alpha $ . Hence, $\delta (x)=y$ . Now, since $f\in F$ , we have $\delta \circ (f\circ \beta )=\delta \circ \beta =\alpha $ too. Moreover due to $(*)$ , $f(x)=x$ and by the uniqueness, we have $f\circ \beta =\beta $ , so $f(x')=x'$ . Therefore f is the identity map as desired.

To see that the bound is optimal, consider $X=\bigcup _{1\le i\le k} (i-1,i)$ and $Y=(0,1)$ . Define a covering map $\delta :X\rightarrow Y, x\mapsto x-\lfloor x\rfloor $ , where $\lfloor x\rfloor $ is the greatest integer which is less than or equal to x. Then, each permutation on $\{1,\ldots , k\}$ induces a homeomorphism of X fixing each fibers of $\delta $ and in this case, $|F|=k!$ .

For (2), it is enough to show that if $f\in F$ fixes a point x in X, then f is the identity. Suppose $f\in F$ fixes $x\in X$ . If X is path-connected, then for each $x'\in X$ , there is a unique path $\beta $ from x to $x'$ due to the unique path-lifting property, so f is the identity by a similar argument as in the proof of (1).⊣

Recall that, by Fact 0.4, the topological group $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is connected (due to our assumption $\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )=\operatorname {dcl}(\emptyset )$ ). By Remarks 2.13(2)(3) and 2.15 and Proposition 2.14, we immediately get the following:

Corollary 2.16. Assume T is G-compact. If $\bar {p}({\mathcal M})/E$ or $p({\mathcal M})/E$ is path-connected—each of which holds if $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ is path-connected, for example a (connected) Lie group—then $|K|=N$ .

Now we show a purely compact abelian group theoretical result, which implies Corollary 2.20. Gleason–Yamabe Theorem [Reference Yamabe12, Theorem 5] states that every locally compact group G is a generalized Lie group, i.e., for every neighbourhood U of the identity there is an open group $G_1$ of G and a compact normal subgroup C of $G_1$ such that $C\subseteq U$ and $G_1/C$ is a Lie group [Reference Gleason4, Definition 1.4]. Note that if additionally G is connected, then its only open subgroup is G itself, so the above gives the following folklore fact:

Fact 2.17. Every locally compact connected group is an inverse limit of Lie groups.

Lemma 2.18. Let G be an abelian compact connected topological group, and let F be a finite subgroup of G. Then G and $G/F$ are isomorphic as topological groups.

Proof Recall that given a finite group F and a prime number q dividing the order of F, there is a subgroup of F of order q. Hence, we can assume that F has a prime order q (applying the prime order case and quotienting out finitely many times to obtain the conclusion for any finite F).

By Fact 2.17 we can present G as $\mathop {\lim }_{\longleftarrow I} G_i$ with some directed system $(I,\le )$ and continuous homomorphisms $f_{i,j}:G_i\to G_j$ for $j\leq i\in I$ , where each $G_i$ is an abelian connected Lie group, hence a torus. We can assume each $f_{i,j}$ is surjective. Since F has a prime order, it is generated by a single element, say $a=(a_i)_{i\in I}$ . Also, replacing I by $I_{i_0}:=\{i\in I|\ i_0\le i\}$ for an appropriate $i_0$ , we can assume that I has the least element $i_0$ , and that each $F_i$ (i.e., the projection of F onto the ith coordinate) has order q. We have that

$$ \begin{align*}G/F=\lim_{\longleftarrow I} H_i,\end{align*} $$

where $H_i=G_i/F_i$ , with maps $k_{i,j}:H_i\to H_j$ induced by $f_{i,j}$ . Moreover, for each $i\in I$ , we let $S_i$ be the unique one-dimensional subtorus of $G_i$ containing $a_i$ .

Claim 2.19. We can find subtori $T_i< G_i$ , $i\in I$ , such that:

  1. (1) $G_i$ is the direct sum of $T_i$ and $S_i$ (in other words, $T_i$ intersects $S_i$ trivially, and $G_i=T_i+S_i$ ), and

  2. (2) $f_{i,j}[T_i]\subseteq T_j$ for each $j\le i$ .

Proof For $i=i_0$ , we choose any torus $T_{i_0}$ such that $G_{i_0}=T_{i_0}\oplus S_{i_0}$ (we can do this just because $S_{i_0}$ is a subtorus of $G_{i_0}$ ).

Now, take any other $i\in I$ . Put $V_i=f_{i,i_0}^{-1}[T_{i_0}]$ . Since both $a_i$ and $a_{i_0}$ have order q and $f_{i,i_0}(a_i)=a_{i_0}$ , the map $f_{i,i_0}$ maps $S_i$ isomorphically onto $S_{i_0}$ . Hence, $S_i\cap V_i=\{e\}$ (if x was a nontrivial element in the intersection, then $f_{i,i_0}(x)$ would be a nontrivial element in $T_{i_0}\cap S_{i_0}$ ). Also, for any $x\in G_i$ , there are $y\in T_{i_0}$ and $z\in S_{i_0}$ such that $f_{i,i_0}(x)=y+z$ , so choosing $w\in S_{i}$ such that $f_{i,i_0}(w)=z$ , we get that $f_{i,i_0}(x-w)=y\in T_{i_0}$ and $x\in S_i+V_i$ . Hence, $G_i$ is the direct sum of $S_i$ and $V_i$ . Note that $V_i$ is a closed (so compact) subgroup of $G_i$ .

Now let $T_i$ be the identity component of the group $V_i$ . Then $T_i$ is a torus of the same dimension as $V_i$ intersecting $S_i$ trivially, so $\operatorname {dim}(T_i+S_i)=\operatorname {dim}(G_i)$ . Hence, by the connectedness of $G_i$ , we get that $G_i=T_i\oplus S_i$ .

To see that $f_{i,j}[T_i]\subseteq T_j$ for $j\le i$ , notice first that $f_{i,j}[T_i]\subseteq V_j$ . Now, since $f_{i,j}$ is continuous and $T_i$ is connected, $f_{i,j}[T_i]$ is a connected subgroup of $G_j$ , so it must be contained in the connected component $T_j$ of $V_j$ . This gives the claim.⊣

Now we will define isomorphisms $g_i$ from $H_i$ to $G_i$ such that, for $j< i$ ,

$$ \begin{align*}f_{i,j}g_i=g_jk_{i,j} \ \ (*).\end{align*} $$

(Recall that $k_{i,j}:H_i\to H_j$ is the map induced by $f_{i,j}$ .) Clearly, we can write $H_i=G_i/F_i$ as $T_i\oplus (S_i/\langle a_i\rangle )$ . We define $g_{i}$ to be the identity map on $T_i$ , and to be equal to the map $\alpha _q:S_i/\langle a_i\rangle \to S_i$ induced by multiplication by q of representatives modulo $\langle a_i\rangle $ on $S_i/\langle a_i\rangle $ , and extend additively to a map from $H_i=T_i\oplus (S_i/\langle a_i\rangle )$ to $T_i \oplus S_i=G_i$ . To check $(*)$ , notice that, for $x\in T_i$ , both $f_{i,j}g_i(x)$ and $g_jk_{i,j}(x)$ are equal to $f_{i,j}(x)$ , and for $y/\langle a_i\rangle \in S_i/\langle a_i\rangle $ , we have that $f_{i,j}g_i(y/\langle a_i\rangle )$ and $g_jk_{i,j}(y/\langle a_i\rangle )$ are both equal to $qf_{i,j}(y)/\mathbb {Z}$ , where $S_j=(\mathbb {R},+)/\mathbb {Z}$ .

Now, the system of isomorphisms $g_i$ induces an isomorphism of topological groups G and $G/F$ .⊣

Corollary 2.20. Suppose T is G-compact, and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {p})$ is abelian. Then, $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {p})$ and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ are isomorphic as topological groups.

Proof By Proposition 2.12 or Theorem 2.6, K is finite; hence, by Lemma 2.18, the compact connected group $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ isomorphic to $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {p})/K$ must be isomorphic to $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {p})$ as well.⊣

Finally, we observe that Corollary 2.20 does not generalize to the non-abelian case.

Proposition 2.21. Let G be a connected compact Lie group, and N a finite normal subgroup of G. Then, one can find types $p=\operatorname {tp}(a)$ and $\bar p=\operatorname {tp}(ac)$ (with $c\in \operatorname {acl}(a)$ finite) in some G-compact theory T with $\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )=\operatorname {dcl}(\emptyset )$ (in $T^{\operatorname {eq}}$ so that $G=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar p)$ and $G/N=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$ . The same holds for the groups $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {res}}$ and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }$ for any $\lambda $ .

If we take $G = SO(4,\mathbb {R})$ , $N = Z(G) = \{I, -I\}$ , then $G/N = PSO(4,\mathbb {R})$ and $Z(G/N)$ is trivial, so G and $G/N$ are not isomorphic.Footnote 2

Proof The Lie group G is definable in some o-minimal expansion ${\mathcal R}$ of the ordered field of real numbers (see for example the discussion preceding Fact 1.1 in [Reference Barriga and Onshuus1]), and (using elimination of imaginaries for o-minimal expansions of $\mathbb {R}$ ) we identify ${\mathcal R}$ with ${\mathcal R}^{eq}$ . Put $H:=G/N$ . We can assume that $N\subseteq \operatorname {dcl}(\emptyset )=\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )$ , so H is $0$ -definable. We consider a structure ${\mathcal M}=({\mathcal R},X,Y)$ , where ${\mathcal R}$ comes with its original structure, X and Y are sets equipped with a regular G-action and a regular $G/N$ -action, respectively (both denoted by $\cdot $ ), and we add to the language the map $\pi :X\to Y$ , defined as follows: fix any elements $x_0\in X$ and $y_0\in Y$ , and, for any $g \in G$ , we set $\pi (g\cdot x_0):=gN\cdot y_0$ . Put $T=\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M})$ .

Note that ${\mathcal M}=({\mathcal R},X,Y)$ is $0$ -interpretable in the structure $({\mathcal R},X)$ , so every automorphism of $({\mathcal R},X)$ extends to an automorphism of ${\mathcal M}$ . Moreover, this extension is unique, as $Y\subseteq \operatorname {dcl}(X)$ . The same holds for the saturated extension ${\mathcal M}^*=({\mathcal R}^*,X^*,Y^*)$ , hence, by [Reference Ziegler and Tent13, Chapter 7], every automorphism of ${\mathcal M}^*$ is of the form $\bar {g}\bar {\phi }$ , where $g\in G^*$ and $\phi \in \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal R}^*)$ (using the notation from [Reference Ziegler and Tent13], and identifying an automorphism of $({\mathcal R}^*,X^*)$ with its unique extension to ${\mathcal M}^*$ ), and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)=G$ .

Let q and p be the unique (strong) types of the sorts $X^*$ and $Y^*$ , respectively. It follows from [Reference Ziegler and Tent13] that an automorphism $\bar {g}\bar {\phi }$ is Lascar-strong iff $g\in G^*_{\inf }$ (the group of infinitesimals of $G^*$ ). It follows that two elements $x,y\in X^*$ have the same Lascar type iff there is $g\in G^*_{\inf }$ such that $g\cdot x=y$ , and two elements $w,u\in Y$ have the same Lascar type iff there is $g\in G^*_{\inf }$ and $n\in N$ such that $(gn)\cdot w=u$ . As all automorphism of the form $\bar {\phi }$ move any $x\in X^{*}$ to its translate by some element of $G^{*}_{\inf }$ , we conclude easily that

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Autf}^1(q)=\operatorname{Autf}^{\operatorname{res}}(q)=\{\bar{g}\bar{\phi}:g \in G^*_{\inf}, \phi\in \operatorname{Aut}(R^*)\}\end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{Autf}^1(p)=\operatorname{Autf}^{\operatorname{res}}(p)=\{\bar{g}\bar{\phi}:g \in G^*_{\inf}N, \phi\in \operatorname{Aut}(R^*)\}.\end{align*} $$

Hence, the map

$$ \begin{align*}g\mapsto [\bar{g}_{|X^*}]\end{align*} $$

is an isomorphism $G\to \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(q)=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {res}}(q)$ , and the map

$$ \begin{align*}g\mapsto [\bar{g}_{|Y^*}]\end{align*} $$

is an epimorphism $G\to \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {res}}(p)$ with kernel N, so $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)=\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\operatorname {res}}(p)=G/N=H$ .

Now, if we take $c\models q$ and $a=\pi (c)\models p$ and $\bar {p}=\operatorname {tp}(ac)$ , then $c\in \operatorname {acl}(a)$ (as the fibers of $\pi $ are finite), but the Lascar-Galois groups of p are isomorphic to H, and we see (as $ac$ is interdefinable with c) that those of $\bar {p}$ are isomorphic to G.

Finally, since $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(T)=G$ is connected, its connected component $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^0(T)$ is the same as G, so we get by Theorem 21 from [Reference Ziegler and Tent13] that all algebraic imaginaries are fixed by all automorphisms over $\emptyset $ , hence $\operatorname {acl}(\emptyset )=\operatorname {dcl}(\emptyset )$ .⊣

We will see in Theorem 3.7 that, in a non-G-compact T, some $\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a)/\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset ))$ fails to be a Lascar type while $\operatorname {tp}(a/\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset ))$ is a Lascar type. We will also see in Proposition 3.10 that, even in a G-compact theory, $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a)/\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset ))$ may be abelian but not isomorphic to $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\operatorname {tp}(a/\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset ))$ .

3. Examples

The starting point of the study in Section 2 was the result observed in [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3] that in a G-compact T if $\operatorname {stp}(a)$ is a Lascar type, then so is $\operatorname {stp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ . In this section we give an example showing that T being G-compact is essential in the result. Moreover, it is natural to ask whether all the hypotheses are essential in Corollary 2.20. In Example 2.21, we have already seen that the abelianity assumption cannot be removed, and we present in this section an example showing that the assumption that c is finite cannot be removed either. Lastly, we find a Lie group structure example answering a question raised in [Reference Kim and Lee10], which asks whether there exists an RN-pattern minimal 2-chain not equivalent to a Lascar pattern 2-chain having the same boundary.

We now explain preliminary examples. Throughout this section we will use ${\mathcal M}$ , ${\mathcal N}$ , …to denote some models which need not be saturated. For a positive integer n, consider a structure ${\mathcal M}_{1,n}=(M;S,g_n)$ , where M is a unit circle; S is a ternary relation on M such that $S(a,b,c)$ holds if and only if $a,b,c$ are distinct and b comes before c going around the circle clockwise starting at a; and $g_n=\sigma _{1/n}$ , where $\sigma _r$ is the clockwise rotation by $2\pi r$ -radians.

For $p=\operatorname {tp}(a)$ , we will denote $\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ by $\bar {\bar {p}}$ .

Fact 3.1 [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler2]

  1. (1) $\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_{1,n})$ has a unique 1-complete type $p_n(x)$ over $\emptyset $ , which is isolated by the formula $x=x$ .

  2. (2) $\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_{1,n})$ is $\aleph _0$ -categorical and has quantifier elimination.

  3. (3) For any subset $A\subseteq M_n$ , $\operatorname {acl}(A)=\operatorname {dcl}(A)=\bigcup _{0\le i< n} g_n^i(A)$ (in the home sort), where $g_n^i=\underbrace {g_n \circ \cdots \circ g_n}_{i~\text {times}}$ .

  4. (4) The unique complete 1-type $p_n$ is also a Lascar type.

3.1. Non- $G$ -compact theory with $p$ Lascar type but $\bar {\bar {p}}$ not Lascar type

We give an example of non-G-compact theory which has a Lascar strong type $\operatorname {tp}(a)$ but $\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ is not a Lascar strong type. Let ${\mathcal M}=(M_i,S_i,g_i,\pi _i)_{i\ge 1}$ be a multi-sorted structure where ${\mathcal M}_{1,i}=(M_i,S_i,g_i)$ (as introduced in Fact 3.1, but of course $M_i$ and $M_j$ are disjoint for $i\ne j$ ) and $\pi _i:\ M_i\rightarrow M_1$ sending $x\mapsto x^i$ for each $i\ge 1$ (if we identify each $M_i$ with the unit circle in the complex plane). For each $n\ge 1$ , let ${\mathcal M}_{\le n}=(M_i,S_i,g_i,\pi _i)_{1\leq i\le n}$ . Let $T=\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M})$ , $T_i=\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_{1,i})$ , and $T_{\le n}=\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_{\le n})$ .

Remark 3.2. Both T and $T_{\le n}$ are $\aleph _0$ -categorical.

Remark 3.3. Let ${\mathcal N}=(N_i,\ldots )$ be a model of T. For $A\subseteq {\mathcal N}$ , define $A_1:=\mathop {\bigcup }_{i\ge 1} \pi _i(\mathop {\bigcup }_{j\le i} g_i^j(A\cap N_i) )$ , and $\operatorname {cl}(A)=\bigcup _{i\ge 1}\pi _i^{-1}[A_1].$

  1. (1) $\operatorname {cl}(A)$ is the smallest substructure containing A.

  2. (2) For $B,C\subseteq {\mathcal N}$ algebraically closed, if $B_1=C_1$ , then $B=C$ .

Fact 3.4 [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3, Theorem 5.5]

Let T be $\aleph _0$ -categorical and let ${\mathcal M}=(M,\ldots )$ be a saturated model of T. Suppose that if $X\subseteq M^1$ is definable over each of two algebraically closed sets $A_0$ and $A_1$ , then X is definable over $B:=A_0\cap A_1$ .

Then, for any subset Y of $M^n$ , if Y is both $A_0$ -definable and $A_1$ -definable, then it is B-definable. Furthermore, in this case, T has weak elimination of imaginaries.

Proposition 3.5.

  1. (1) Both T and $T_{\le n}$ , $n\ge 1$ , have quantifier elimination.

  2. (2) Both T and $T_{\le n}$ , $n\ge 1$ , weakly eliminate imaginaries.

Proof $(1)$ Here we prove that T has quantifier elimination. By a similar reason, each $T_{\le n}$ has also quantifier elimination. Let ${\mathcal N}_1=(N_{i}^1,\ldots )$ and ${\mathcal N}_2=(N_{i}^2,\ldots )$ be models of T. Take some finite $A\subseteq {\mathcal N}_1$ , and let $f: \operatorname {cl}(A) \rightarrow {\mathcal N}_2$ be a partial embedding. Take $a\in {\mathcal N}_1$ arbitrary. It is enough to show that there is a partial embedding $g :\operatorname {cl}(Aa)\rightarrow {\mathcal N}_2$ extending f. By Remark 3.3(1), we may assume that $A=A_1\subset N_1^1$ . Suppose $a\in N_i^1$ . Let $a_1=\pi _i(a)$ . If $a_1\in A$ , then $a\in \operatorname {acl}(A)$ , and we are done. Without loss of generality, we may assume that $a_1\not \in A$ . Since $T_1$ has quantifier elimination, we can pick $b_1\in N_{1}^2$ such that $b_1\models \operatorname {tp}_{T_1}(a_1/A)$ . Let $A_i=\pi _i^{-1}[A]\subseteq N_i^1$ , which is finite, and let $\bar {a}_i=(a_i^1,\ldots ,a_i^i)$ be an enumeration of $\pi _i^{-1}(a_1)$ . Since each $T_i$ has quantifier elimination, we can pick an enumeration $\bar {b}_i=(b_i^1,\ldots ,b_i^i)$ of $\pi _i^{-1}(b_1)$ such that $\bar {b}_i\models \operatorname {tp}_{T_i}(\bar {a}_i/A_i)$ . Note that $\operatorname {cl}(Aa)=\operatorname {cl}(A)\cup \mathop {\bigcup }_{i\ge 1} \pi _i^{-1}(a_1)$ . Consider a map $g=f\cup \{(a_i^j,b_i^j)|\ 1\le i,1\le j\le i\}$ . For each i, $g\restriction _{N_i^1}$ is a partial embedding to $N_i^2$ , and for each $j\le i$ , $b_1=\pi _i(b_i^j)=\pi _i(g(a_i^j))$ . Therefore $g:\operatorname {cl}(Aa)\rightarrow {\mathcal N}_2$ is a partial embedding extending f, and we are done. As a consequence, $\operatorname {acl}(A)=\operatorname {cl}(A)$ for each A.

$(2)$ We first show that each $T_{\le n}$ weakly eliminates imaginaries. We consider ${\mathcal M}_{\le n}$ as ${\mathcal M}_{\le n}'=(M',S',g',\pi ')$ , where $M'=M_1\cup \cdots \cup M_n$ , $ S'=S_1\cup \cdots \cup S_n$ , $g'=g_1\cup \cdots \cup g_n$ , and $\pi '=\pi _1\cup \cdots \cup \pi _n$ . Let $T_{\le n}'=\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_{\le n}')$ . It is enough to show that $T_{\le n}'$ weakly eliminates imaginaries. Note that $T_{\le n}'$ is $\aleph _0$ -categorical. Let ${\mathcal N}=(N(=N_1\cup \cdots \cup N_n),\ldots )$ be a saturated model of $T_{\le n}'$ . By Fact 3.4, it is enough to show that a subset X of $N^1$ which is both A-definable and B-definable, where A and B are algebraically closed, is also definable over $C=A\cap B$ . Let $A_i$ , $B_i$ , and $C_i$ denote the intersections of A, B, and C, respectively, with $N_i$ , $1\le i \le n$ . Note that $C_i=A_i\cap B_i$ for each $1\le i\le n$ and $C=\operatorname {acl}(C_1)$ . We may assume that $X\subseteq N_{i}$ for some $1\le i\le n$ by taking $X\cap N_{i}$ . By quantifier elimination, X is definable over $A_{i}$ and $B_{i}$ . Then from the proof of [Reference Kim, Kim and Lee9, Theorem 4.3(1)], X is definable over $C_{i}=A_{i}\cap B_{i}$ and clearly over $C=\operatorname {acl}(C_i)$ . Thus $T_{\le n}'$ weakly eliminates imaginaries and so does $T_{\le n}$ .

Let ${\mathcal M}'$ be a saturated model of T and let ${\mathcal M}_{\le n}'$ be the saturated structure corresponding to ${\mathcal M}_{\le n}$ . By Remark 3.3(1) and quantifier elimination, there is no strictly decreasing chain of algebraically closures of finite sets in ${\mathcal M}'$ . Since ${\mathcal M}'=\bigcup _n {\mathcal M}_{\le n}$ , by the same reasoning as in the proof of [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3, Theorem 5.9], we conclude that T weakly eliminates imaginaries.⊣

Let ${\mathcal N}=(N_i,\ldots )$ be a saturated model of T. By Proposition 3.5, $\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset )=\emptyset $ . Let $a\in N_1^1$ , and consider strong types $p:=\operatorname {tp}(a)$ (isolated by $x=x$ ) and $\bar {\bar {p}}:=\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ .

Fact 3.6 [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler2]

For $a\neq b\in N_n$ , a and b have the same type over some elementary substructure of $N_n$ if and only if $N_n\models S_n(a,b,g_n(a))\wedge S_n(g_n^{-1}(a),b,a)$ . So there are $a,b\in N_n$ whose Lascar distance is at least $n/2$ .

Theorem 3.7. The type p is a Lascar strong type but $\bar {\bar {p}}$ is not a Lascar strong type.

Proof By Fact 3.6, p is a Lascar strong type. Take $a,b\in N_1$ which are Lascar equivalent. Let $\bar {a}_i=(a_i^1,\ldots ,a_i^i)$ and $\bar {b}_i=(b_i^1,\ldots ,b_i^i)$ be enumerations of $\pi _i^{-1}(a)$ and $\pi _i^{-1}(b)$ . Denote $\sigma _i(a_i)=(a_i^{\sigma (1)},\ldots ,a_i^{\sigma (i)})$ for each permutation $\sigma \in S_i$ . Let $\tau _i$ be the permutation of $\{1,2,\ldots , i\}$ sending j to $j+1$ for $j< i$ and i to $1$ . Then $(a_1,\tau _2^{k_2}(\bar {a}_2),\tau _3^{k_3}(\bar {a}_3),\ldots )\models \bar {\bar {p}}$ for arbitrary $k_2,k_3,\ldots (*)$ . For each i, there are $a_i\in \pi _i^{-1}(a_1)$ and $b_i\in \pi _i^{-1}(b_1)$ whose Lascar distance is at least $i/2$ . So, by $(*)$ , $\bar {\bar {p}}$ is not a Lascar strong type.⊣

3.2. A $G$ -compact theory with $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(\bar {\bar {p}})$ abelian and not isomorphic to $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)$

We will use the symbols $\sigma _r$ , $g_n$ , and $(M_i, S_i)$ defined in the previous subsection. Put $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}=\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_1=(M_1,S_1,g_{1,n})_{n\geq 1}$ , where $g_{1,n}$ is the same rotation as $g_n$ on the unit circle $M_1=S^1$ . We define a multi-sorted structure

$$ \begin{align*}{\mathcal M}'=((\widetilde{{\mathcal M}}_k),\delta_k)_{k\geq 1},\end{align*} $$

where each $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_k:= (M_k=\{x_{(k)}:x \in S^1\},S_k,g_{k,n})_{n\geq 1}$ is a copy of $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_1$ (again $g_{k,n}$ is the same rotation as $g_n$ on $M_k$ , and we may omit k in $S_k$ and $g_{k,n}$ ), and $\delta _k:\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{k+1}\to \widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_k$ is given by $\delta _k (x_{(k+1)})=x^2_{(k)}$ . Put $T'=\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}')$ .

Lemma 3.8. $T'$ admits quantifier elimination.

Proof It is enough to prove quantifier elimination for the restriction of ${\mathcal M}'$ to finitely many sorts $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{\leq k}$ for each k, but such a restriction is quantifier-free interpretable in the structure ${\mathcal M}'$ for some n, which is known to admit quantifier elimination [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3, Theorem 5.8].⊣

Using quantifier elimination, it is easy to check that two (possibly infinite) tuples have the same Lascar type if and only if their corresponding coordinates are infinitesimally close (in the same sort), and S induces corresponding partial orders on the tuples. As this is a type-definable condition, we get that $T'$ is G-compact.

By Theorem 5.9 from [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3], $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}$ , and hence also any $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{\leq k}$ , weakly eliminates imaginaries. Hence, we get:

Remark 3.9. $T'$ weakly eliminates imaginaries.

By Lemma 3.8, one easily gets that $\operatorname {acl}_{T'}(\emptyset )=\emptyset $ in the home-sort; hence, by Remark 3.9, $\operatorname {acl}_{T'}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset )=\emptyset $ . Now, let p be the (unique) type of an element $a\in \widetilde {{\mathcal M}}$ . Then $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^1(p)\cong \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}(\operatorname {Th}(\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}))\cong S^1$ . On the other hand, for $\bar {\bar {p}}=\operatorname {tp}(\operatorname {acl}(a))$ , we have:

Proposition 3.10. $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(\bar {\bar {p}})$ is isomorphic to the $2$ -solenoid $G:=\varprojlim _i \mathbb {R}/2^i\mathbb {Z}$ (the projections in the inverse limit are the natural quotient maps). Hence, $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(\bar {\bar {p}})$ is abelian and non-isomorphic to $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(p)$ .

Proof Consider the homomorphism $\phi :G=\varprojlim _i \mathbb {R}/2^i\mathbb {Z}\to \operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(\bar {\bar {p}})$ sending a sequence $(r_i/2^i\mathbb {Z})_i$ to the class induced by the automorphism $f_{(r_i)_i}$ (defined on a monster model of $T'$ ) equal to $\sigma _{r_i/2^i}$ on $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{i}$ for each i. If $r_i\notin 2^i\mathbb {Z}$ , then $f_{(r_i)_i}$ does not preserve the Lascar types of elements of $\widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{i}$ , hence $\operatorname {Ker}(\phi )=\{0\}$ . It remains to check that $\phi $ is surjective. Consider a class in $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{1}(\bar {\bar {p}})$ induced by an automorphism f. As all elements of $ \widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{1}$ have the same Lascar type, we may assume that $f(a)=a$ for some $a\in \widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{1}$ (by composing f with a strong automorphism sending $f(a)$ to a). Now, for each i, as f commutes with $\delta _1\delta _2\dots \delta _{i-1}$ , it must preserve $\operatorname {acl}(a)\cap \widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{i}$ setwise. Hence, there is $r_i$ such that on $\operatorname {acl}(a)\cap \widetilde {{\mathcal M}}_{i}$ , f is equal to $\sigma _{r_i/2^i}$ . Then f and $f_{(r_i)_i}$ have infinitesimally close values on every element of the monster model, so $f^{-1}f_{(r_i)_i}$ is Lascar strong and $\phi (f_{(r_i)_i})$ is equal to the class induced by f.⊣

3.3. RN but not a Lascar pattern $2$ -chain

Let p be a strong type of an algebraically closed set. In [Reference Kim, Kim and Lee9], it was shown that any $2$ -chain in p with $1$ -shell boundary can be reduced to a $2$ -chain having an RN-pattern or an NR-pattern.Footnote 3 Also for $a,b\models p$ , if $a\equiv ^L b$ , then $(a,b)$ is an endpoint pair of a $1$ -shell which is the boundary of a $2$ -chain having a Lascar pattern, a kind of an RN-pattern. In [Reference Kim and Lee10, Question 4.5], it was asked whether all minimal $2$ -chains having an RN-pattern with $1$ -shell boundary should be equivalent to one having a Lascar pattern. It was also noticed that if there is a counterexample, then its length should be at least $7$ .

In this subsection, we assume the reader has some familiarity with the notions described in [Reference Kim, Kim and Lee9, Reference Kim and Lee10], and we work with the trivial independence to define independent functors in a strong type (see Definition 0.6), and corresponding $1$ -shells and $2$ -chains. We now give descriptions of $2$ -chains having an RN- or a Lascar pattern in terms of balanced walks, rather than original definitions. For more combinatorial descriptions for RN- or Lascar pattern $2$ -chains, see [Reference Kim and Lee10].

Remark/Definition 3.11. Let $a,b\models p$ . For $n\ge 1$ , a balanced edge-walk of length $2n$ from a to b is simply a balanced chain-walk of length $2n$ from a to b in Fact 0.14 (1)(b) with the trivial independence (so (1)(b)(ii) is removed), that is, a finite sequence $(d_i)_{0\le i\le 2n}$ of realizations of p satisfying the following conditions:

  1. (1) $d_0=a$ , and $d_{2n}=b;$ and

  2. (2) there is a bijection

    $$ \begin{align*}\sigma:\{0,1,\ldots,n-1\}\to\{0,1,\ldots,n-1\}\end{align*} $$
    such that $d_{2i} d_{2i+1}\equiv d_{2\sigma (i)+2}d_{2\sigma (i)+1}$ for $ i < n$ .

With the trivial independence, a balanced edge-walk of length $2n$ from a to b induces a $2$ -chain of length $2n+1$ (having the $1$ -shell boundary whose endpoint pair is $(a,b)$ ), which is a chain-walk (cf., the proof of [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3, Theorem 4.2]). Such an induced $2$ -chain need not be unique but it is unique up to the first homology class.

In particular, given a minimal $2$ -chain $\alpha $ of length $2n+1$ with the $1$ -shell boundary s, $\alpha $ is equivalent to a Lascar pattern $2$ -chain if and only if $\alpha $ is equivalent to a chain-walk induced by a balanced edge-walk of length $2n$ from a to b with $\sigma =\operatorname {id}$ such that $[a,b]=[s]\in H_1(p)$ .

Fact 3.12 [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Lee3, Reference Kim and Lee10]

Let $\alpha $ be a minimal $2$ -chain of length $2n+1 (n\geq 1)$ in p with the boundary $s=g_{12} -g_{02} + g_{01}$ such that $\operatorname {supp}(g_{ij})=\{i,j\}$ . Then the following are equivalent.

  1. (1) The $2$ -chain $\alpha $ has an RN-pattern.

  2. (2) The $2$ -chain $\alpha $ is equivalent to a $2$ -chain

    $$ \begin{align*}\alpha'=\mathop{\sum}\limits_{i=0}^{2n} (-1)^i f_i,\end{align*} $$
    which is a chain-walk of $2$ -simplices from $g_{01}$ to $-g_{02}$ such that $\partial ^2 f_{0}=g_{01}$ , $\partial ^0 f_{2n}=g_{12}$ , $\partial ^1(f_{2n})=-g_{02}$ , and $\operatorname {supp}(\alpha ')=3=\{0,1,2\}$ .
  3. (3) There are an endpoint pair $(a,b)$ of s, and a balanced-edge-walk of length $2n$ from a to b which induces a $2$ -chain equivalent to $\alpha $ .

In this subsection we will give a minimal $2$ -chain example (with 1-shell boundary) having an RN-pattern but not equivalent to that having a Lascar pattern. The example will have length $7$ . We start with preparatory constructions. Let G be a connected compact Lie group definable in ${\mathbb R}$ in the ordered ring language. Let X be a set equipped with a regular G-action. Let ${\mathcal M}_2=({\mathcal R},X,\cdot )$ be a two sorted structure, where ${\mathcal R}$ is the field of real numbers with a named finite set of elements over which G is definable. Let ${\mathcal N}_n=({\mathcal M}_{1,n}, {\mathcal M}_2)$ , and there is no interaction between ${\mathcal M}_{1,n}$ and ${\mathcal M}_2$ .

Let ${\mathcal N}_n^*=({\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*,{\mathcal M}_2^*)$ be a saturated model of $\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_n)$ such that ${\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*=(M^*,S,g_n)$ and ${\mathcal M}_2^*=({\mathcal R}^*,X^*,\cdot )$ are saturated models of $\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_{1,n})$ and $\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_2)$ respectively. Since there are no other interactions between ${\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*$ and ${\mathcal M}_2^*$ , we have that

  • $\operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal N}_n^*)=\operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*)\times \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M}_2^*)$ .

  • For $a\in {\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*$ and $b\in {\mathcal M}_2^*$ , $\operatorname {acl}(ab)=\operatorname {acl}_{{\mathcal M}_{1,n}}(a)\cup \operatorname {acl}_{{\mathcal M}_2}(b)$ , where $\operatorname {acl}_{{\mathcal M}_{1,n}}$ and $\operatorname {acl}_{{\mathcal M}_2}$ are the algebraic closures taken in ${\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*$ and ${\mathcal M}_2^*$ respectively.

  • For $a\in {\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*$ and $b\in {\mathcal M}_2^*$ , $\operatorname {tp}(ab)=\operatorname {tp}_{{\mathcal M}_{1,n}}(a)\cup \operatorname {tp}_{{\mathcal M}_2}(b)$ where $\operatorname {tp}_{{\mathcal M}_{1,n}}(a)$ and $\operatorname {tp}_{{\mathcal M}_2}(b)$ are complete types in ${\mathcal M}_{1,n}^*$ and ${\mathcal M}_2^*$ respectively.

First, let us recall a fact on minimal lengths of $1$ -shells in $p_n$ from [Reference Kim, Kim and Lee9].

Definition 3.13. Let ${\mathcal A}$ be a non-trivial amenable collection and let s be a $1$ -shell. Define

$$ \begin{align*}B(s) :=\min \{~|\tau| : \tau~\text{is a (minimal) 2-chain and}~\partial(\tau)=s ~\}.\end{align*} $$

If s is not the boundary of any $2$ -chain, define $B(s) := - \infty $ .

Fact 3.14. For $n\ge 7$ , there is a $1$ -shell s in $p_n$ such that $B(s)=7$ .

Note that in [Reference Kim, Kim and Lee9], the authors considered $1$ -shells and $2$ -chains defined under $\operatorname {acl}$ -independence for Fact 3.14. By similar methods as in the proofs, it is not hard to see that the same Fact 3.14 holds for $1$ -shells and $2$ -chains defined under the trivial independence as in this subsection.

Next, let us recall some facts about ${\mathcal M}_2^*$ from [Reference Ziegler and Tent13]. Let $G^*$ be the extension of G in ${\mathcal R}^*$ . Let $\mu $ be the normal subgroup of infinitesimals in $G^*$ . We fix a base point $x_0\in X^*$ so that for $x\in X^*$ there is a unique element $h\in G^*$ with $x=h\cdot x_0$ .

Fact 3.15.

  1. (1) Each $\phi \in \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal R}^*)$ is extended to $\operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M}^*_2)$ defined by $\bar {\phi }(h\cdot x_0):=\phi (h)\cdot x_0$ . An automorphism which fixes ${\mathcal R}^*$ pointwise is of the form $\bar {g}$ for some $g\in G^*$ , where $\bar {g}(h\cdot x_0)=(hg^{-1})\cdot x_0$ , and the commutation rule is given by $\bar {\phi }\bar {g}=\overline {\phi (g)}\bar {\phi }$ . So we have $\operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal M}^*_2)=\operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal R}^*)\ltimes G^*$ .

  2. (2) An automorphism $\Phi =\bar {\phi }\bar {g}$ is a strong automorphism if and only if g is an infinitesimal. So the Lascar Galois group of $\operatorname {Th}({\mathcal M}_2)$ is isomorphic to G.

  3. (3) $\mu =\{h^{-1}\phi (h)|\ h\in G^*,\ \phi \in \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal R}^*)\}$ .

We note that in $X^*$ , there is a unique $1$ -type over $\emptyset $ and it is also a strong type over $\emptyset $ .

Proposition 3.16. For any $x\in X$ , $x\equiv x_0$ and $\operatorname {tp}(x_0)=\operatorname {stp}(x_0)$ .

Proof Suppose there are $x,x'\in X^*$ with $\operatorname {stp}(x)\neq \operatorname {stp}(x')$ . Then there is an $\emptyset $ -definable finite equivalence relation E on $X^*$ such that $\neg E(x,x')$ . Define $H:=\{g\in G^*|\ E(x,g\cdot x)\}$ . Since E is $\emptyset $ -definable, H is $\emptyset $ -definable subgroup of $G^*$ , and it is proper. We claim that $[G^*:H]$ is finite. Note that $gg^{-1}\in H$ if and only if $E(g\cdot x,g'\cdot x)$ . So the map sending $gH\in G^*/H\mapsto g(x)E\in X^*/E$ is a bijection because $G^*$ acts on $X^*$ transitively. Since $X^*/E$ is finite, so is $G^*/H$ , contradicting the connectedness of G.⊣

Let $\operatorname {acl}_{{\mathcal R}^*}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset )$ be the algebraic closure of $\emptyset $ in $({\mathcal R}^*)^{\operatorname {eq}}$ . For $x\in X^*$ , $\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(x)=\{x\}\cup \operatorname {acl}_{{\mathcal R}^*}^{\operatorname {eq}}(\emptyset )$ . From Proposition 3.16, we have that $\operatorname {tp}(x)\models \operatorname {stp}(\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(x))$ . So we say $x_1$ and $x_2$ are endpoints if $\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(x_1)$ and $\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(x_2)$ are endpoints of a $1$ -shell in $p:=\operatorname {stp}(\operatorname {acl}^{\operatorname {eq}}(x))$ .

Lemma 3.17. For $x_1, x_2, x_3\in X^*$ , if $x_1x_2\equiv x_3x_2$ , then there is $h\in \mu $ such that $\bar {h}(x_1)=x_3$ .

Proof Let $x_1,x_2,x_3\in X^*$ be such that $x_1x_2\equiv x_3x_2$ . Let $h_1,h_2,h_3\in G^*$ be such that $x_i=h_i\cdot x_0$ . It is enough to show that $h_3h_1^{-1}\in \mu $ .

Take $\phi \in \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal R}^*)$ and $g\in G^*$ such that $\bar g \bar \phi (x_1x_2)=x_3x_2$ . Then we have

$$ \begin{align*} \bar g \bar \phi(x_1x_2) &=\bar g((\phi(h_1)\cdot x_0) (\phi(h_2) \cdot x_0))\\ &=(\phi(h_1)g^{-1}\cdot x_0)(\phi(h_2)g^{-1}\cdot x_0)\\ &=(h_3\cdot x_0)(h_2\cdot x_0). \end{align*} $$

By the regularity of the action of $G^*$ , we have $\phi (h_1)g^{-1}=h_3$ and $\phi (h_2)g^{-1}=h_2$ , and so $g=h_2^{-1}\phi (h_2)\in \mu $ . And $h_3h_1^{-1}=\phi (h_1)g^{-1}h_1^{-1}=\phi (h_1)h_1^{-1}=\operatorname {id}$ modulo $\mu $ because $\mu $ is a normal subgroup of $G^*$ . Thus $h_3h_1^{-1}\in \mu $ .⊣

Theorem 3.18. For $x_1,x_2\in X^*$ , the following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $x_1\equiv ^{L}x_2$ .

  2. (2) There is $h\in \mu $ such that $\overline h(x_1)=x_2$ .

  3. (3) $x_1$ and $x_2$ are endpoints of a $1$ -shell which is the boundary of a $2$ -chain in p having a Lascar pattern.

Proof $(1) \Leftrightarrow (2)$ was proved in [Reference Ziegler and Tent13] and $(1)\Rightarrow (3)$ was proved in [Reference Kim, Kim and Lee9]. It is enough to show $(3)\Rightarrow (2)$ . By definition of Lascar pattern 2-chain (in [Reference Kim, Kim and Lee9]) and Lemma 3.17, $(3)\Rightarrow (2)$ is also true.⊣

Now we give a promised example of a minimal $2$ -chain having an RN-pattern but not equivalent to one having a Lascar pattern. Denote $[g,h]=ghg^{-1}h^{-1}$ . Consider ${\mathcal N}_n^*$ for some $n\ge 7$ and let $q=\operatorname {tp}(ab)$ for $a\models p$ and $b\models p_n$ , which is a strong type.

Theorem 3.19. Suppose G is not abelian. Then there is a minimal $2$ -chain in q which has an RN-pattern but not equivalent to any Lascar pattern 2-chain.

Proof Suppose G is not abelian. We can choose $g_1, g_2, g_3\in G$ such that $[(g_3g_2)^{-1},(g_2g_1))]\neq \operatorname {id}$ . Let $h_1:=g_1$ , $h_2:=g_2$ , $h_3:=g_3$ , $h_4:=h_1^{-1}[h_1,(h_3h_2)]$ , $h_5:=h_2^{-1}[h_2,(h_4h_3)]$ , and $h_6:=h_3^{-1}[h_3,(h_5h_4)]$ . Set $x_i=(h_i h_{i-1}\cdots h_1)^{-1}\cdot x_0$ for $1\le i\le 6$ . Consider a $1$ -shell $s=f_{01}+f_{12}-f_{02}$ , where $f_{01}(\{01\})\equiv [x_0 x_0]$ , $s=f_{12}(\{1,2\})=[x_0 x_0]$ , and $f_{02}(\{0,2\})\equiv [x_6 x_0]$ , and its endpoints are $x_0$ and $x_6$ . Let $f_i=h_ih_{i-1}\cdots h_1\in G\subseteq G^*$ for $1\le i\le 6$ . Then we have that

  • $f_4=f_3f_1^{-1}$ ;

  • $f_5f_1^{-1}=f_4f_2^{-1}$ ; and

  • $f_6f_2^{-1}=f_5f_3^{-1}$ .

This implies $\bar f_4(x_0x_1)=x_4x_3$ , $\overline {f_5f_1^{-1}}(x_1x_2)=x_5x_4$ , and $\overline {f_6f_2^{-1}}(x_2x_3)=x_6x_5$ . Then we have that $x_0x_1\equiv x_4x_3$ , $x_1x_2\equiv x_6x_5$ , and $x_2x_3\equiv x_5x_4$ .

This gives a $2$ -chain $\alpha $ of length $7$ having the $1$ -shell boundary s. Note that

$$ \begin{align*} f_6&= (h_6h_5h_4h_3)h_2h_1\\ &=(h_5h_4)h_2h_1\\ &=(h_4h_3h_2^{-1}h_3^{-1})h_2h_1\\ &=(h_4h_3)(h_2^{-1}h_3^{-1})(h_2h_1)\\ &=(h_3h_2)(h_2h_1)^{-1}(h_2^{-1}h_3^{-1})(h_2h_1)\\ &=[(h_3h_2),(h_2h_1)^{-1}]\neq \operatorname{id}, \end{align*} $$

and $f_6\notin \mu $ . By Theorem 3.18, s is not the boundary of $2$ -chain with a Lascar pattern and $B(s)\le 7$ .

Let $b,b'\models p_n$ where $(b,b')$ is an endpoint pair of a $1$ -shell $s'$ of $p_n$ such that $B(s')=7$ in ${\mathcal M}_{1,n}$ . Let $\alpha '$ be a minimal $2$ -chain with an RN-pattern having the $1$ -shell boundary $s'$ of length $7$ . Note that we can take such a $2$ -chain because $p_n$ is a Lascar type. Consider $a=(x_0,b),a'=(x_6,b')\models q$ . Let $s''$ be a $1$ -shell induced from s and $s'$ with an endpoint pair $(a,a')$ . Consider a $2$ -chain $\alpha ''$ in q induced from $\alpha $ and $\alpha '$ , which does not a Lascar pattern and has length $7$ . We claim that $\alpha ''$ is minimal. Since $B(s)\le 7$ and $B(s')=7$ , we have that $B(s'')=7$ and so $\alpha ''$ is minimal. By the construction of $\alpha ''$ , it has an RN-pattern. Therefore, the minimal $2$ -chain $\alpha ''$ has an RN-pattern but is not equivalent to a Lascar pattern $2$ -chain.⊣

Acknowledgments

The first author was supported by European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Sklodowska-Curie grant agreement No. 705410. The second and fourth authors were supported by an NRF of Korea grant 2018R1D1A1A02085584 and Samsung Science Technology Foundation under Project Number SSTF-BA1301-03, respectively.

Footnotes

1 Similarly, $\operatorname {Autf}^{\lambda }_{\operatorname {KP}}(p)$ is defined as the group of automorphisms in $\operatorname {Aut}(p)$ fixing the KP-type of any $\lambda $ -many realizations of p, and $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {KP}}^{\lambda }(p):=\operatorname {Aut}(p)/\operatorname {Autf}^{\lambda }_{\operatorname {KP}}(p)$ . Then in this paper, one may work with $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {KP}}^{\lambda }(p)$ instead of $\operatorname {Gal}_{\operatorname {L}}^{\lambda }(p)$ , and remove the assumption of T being G-compact where that is assumed. See Remark 2.1 for more details.

2 This example is pointed out to us by Prof. Sang-Hyun Kim from Seoul National University.

3 In this paper, we change terminology “ $\dots $ -type” to “ $\dots $ -pattern” in order to avoid confusion with the existing notion of a type—a set of formulas.

References

Barriga, E. and Onshuus, A., Classifying torsion free groups in o-minimal expansions of real closed fields . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 167 (2016), pp. 12671297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casanovas, E., Lascar, D., Pillay, A., and Ziegler, M., Galois groups of first order theories . Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 1 (2001), pp. 305319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobrowolski, J., Kim, B., and Lee, J., The Lascar groups and the first homology groups in model theory . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 168 (2017), pp. 21292151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gleason, A. M., The structure of locally compact groups . Duke Mathematical Journal , vol. 18 (1951), pp. 85104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodrick, J., Kim, B., and Kolesnikov, A., Amalgamation functors and homology groups in model theory . Proceedings of ICM 2014 (Jang, S. Y., Kim, Y. R., Lee, D.-W., and Yie, I., editors), vol. II, Seoul, Kyung Moon Sa, 2014, pp. 4158.Google Scholar
Hofmann, K. H. and Morris, S. A., The Structure of Compact Groups, De Gruyter, Berlin and Boston, 2013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, B., A note on lascar strong types in simple theories, this Journal, vol. 63 (1998), pp. 926936.Google Scholar
Kim, B., Simplicity Theory, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2014.Google Scholar
Kim, B., Kim, S. Y., and Lee, J., A classification of 2-chains having 1-shell boundaries in rosy theories, this Journal, vol. 80 (2015), pp. 322340.Google Scholar
Kim, S. Y. and Lee, J., More on 2-chains with 1-shell boundaries in rosy theories . Journal of the Mathematical Society of Japan , vol. 69 (2017), pp. 93109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krupiński, K., Newelski, L., and Simon, P., Boundedness and absoluteness of some dynamical invariants in model theory . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 19 (2019), p. 1950012.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yamabe, H., A generalization of a theorem of Gleason . Annals of Mathematics , vol. 58 (1953), pp. 351365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ziegler, M., Introduction to the Lascar group , Tits Buildings and the Model Theory of Groups (Tent, K., editor), London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, vol. 291, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2002, pp. 279298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar