Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-21T15:22:02.589Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

From radical evil to constitutive moral luck in Kant’s Religion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 December 2024

Robert J. Hartman*
Affiliation:
Department of English, Philosophy and Religion, Ohio Northern University, Ada, OH, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The received view is that Kant denies all moral luck. But I show how Kant affirms constitutive moral luck in passages concerning radical evil from Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason. First, I explicate Kant’s claims about radical evil. It is a morally evil disposition that all human beings have necessarily, at least for the first part of their lives, and for which they are blameworthy. Second, since these properties about radical evil appear to contradict Kant’s even more famous claims about imputation, ‘ought implies can’, and free will, I unpack Henry Allison’s proof of radical evil and show how it is consistent with interpretations of Kant’s broader views about morality. Third, I define and illustrate the category of constitutive moral luck and argue that Kant embraces the existence of constitutive moral luck given Allison-style interpretations of radical evil. This provides a reason for philosophers to reject the received view, and it creates an occasion for Kantians and Kant scholars to check their reasons if they deny moral luck.

Type
Original Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press.

Moral luck occurs when factors outside of an agent’s control positively affect how much praise or blame she deserves (Hartman Reference Hartman2017, 23; cf. Nagel Reference Nagel1979, 26).Footnote 1 By ‘positively affect’, I mean that the luck at issue does not undermine praiseworthiness or blameworthiness and does make a positive difference in how much praise or blame is deserved. The source of the lack of control differentiates various kinds of moral luck. Thomas Nagel’s (Reference Nagel1979, 28) taxonomy of sources includes consequences, circumstances, constitution, and causal determination.

The received view, in the literature on moral luck and elsewhere, is that Immanuel Kant’s moral philosophy rules out all kinds of moral luck. Consider some representative statements: ‘Kant’s moral philosophy is one of the grandest attempts in Western philosophy to banish any form of luck from the realm of morality’ (Vaida Reference Vaida2014, 124); ‘the Kantian [moral] position is presented as entirely incompatible with the possibility of luck’ (Athanassoulis Reference Athanassoulis2005, 100; see also Kahn Reference Kahn2021, 366–368; Nagel Reference Nagel1979, 24; Williams Reference Williams1981, 38).

Elsewhere, I have argued that there are plausible interpretations of Kant in which he embraces or does not deny various kinds of moral luck. Kant does not deny moral luck in results (Hartman Reference Hartman2019a; see also Kahn Reference Kahn2021; Moran Reference Moran, Church and Hartman2019), and Kant embraces moral luck in actions influenced by lucky circumstances and psychological dispositions that affect the degree of difficulty in doing the right thing (Hartman Reference Hartman2024; see also Moran Reference Moran, Church and Hartman2019).Footnote 2

In this article, I expand the argument against the received view. Appealing to passages from Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason about radical evil, I argue that Kant embraces both moral luck in a disposition and in an action influenced by a lucky disposition. Ascribing moral luck in a disposition to Kant’s philosophy is new. Other pro-moral luck interpretations of Kant concern only moral luck in results and actions.

Radical evil is a morally evil disposition that human beings must have, at least for part of their lives,Footnote 3 and for which they are blameworthy. On behalf of the claim about necessary possession, Kant asserts that the morally evil propensity is ‘innate’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:22), ‘universal’ in human beings (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:30), ‘woven into human nature’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:30), and ‘entwined with humanity itself and, as it were, rooted in it’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:32). On behalf of the claim about blameworthiness, Kant asserts that the evil propensity is ‘something that a human being can be held accountable for’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:32), ‘we can well be responsible for the propensity to evil … imputed to the subject as itself guilty of it’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:35), and it is something for which human beings have ‘innate guilt’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:38). Radical evil seems to be a paradigm case of constitutive moral luck because the possession of this innate and universal disposition in human beings is at least partially outside of their control and yet they are blameworthy for this disposition.

Although these passages strongly indicate that Kant embraces constitutive moral luck, there is no consensus about how best to understand radical evil and its consistency with Kant’s famous view that moral goodness, badness, praiseworthiness, and blameworthiness must be traced back to exercises of free will. In view of these puzzles, I appeal to Henry Allison’s (Reference Allison1990, Reference Allison2002, Reference Allison2020) prominentFootnote 4 interpretation of radical evil because it provides a general approach to radical evil that showcases its consistency with Kant’s moral ideas about imputation, ‘ought implies can’, and free will.

I proceed as follows. First, I unpack Kant’s claims about radical evil. Second, I explicate Henry Allison’s proof of radical evil and show how the general move coheres with a plausible interpretation of Kant’s broader moral commitments. Third, I define and illustrate the nature of constitutive moral luck and show how Allison’s interpretation, and other relevantly similar interpretations, commit Kant to embracing two kinds of constitutive moral luck. This article provides another reason for philosophers to reject the received view. It also creates an occasion for Kantians and Kant scholars to check their reasons if they deny moral luck.

Kant on radical evil

According to Kant (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:18), human persons are ‘radically evil’. Radical evil is a morally evil propensity, a corrupt character that inclines a human person to do what is morally wrong.Footnote 5 The inclination is to prioritize self-love and self-conceit over respect for the moral law (Kant Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:36). When human persons act on this corrupt prioritization, they do what is morally wrong, for example, by making an irrational exception for themselves or by using others as a mere means to advance their own happiness.

Kant’s claims that radical evil is ‘innate’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:22) and ‘morally evil’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:32) generate a puzzle. After all, these claims seem to contradict Kant’s claim about imputing moral evil:

The human being must make or have made himself into whatever he is or should become in a moral sense, good or evil. These two must be an effect of his free power of choice, for otherwise they could not be imputed to him and, consequently, he could be neither morally good nor evil (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:44, italics in original).

In other words, actions and dispositions are morally good or evil only if they are the product of free choice. Since radical evil is a morally evil disposition (and a blameworthy disposition), it must be freely chosen. But how can an innate disposition be freely chosen?

Kant offers a solution. Human persons freely choose their innate fundamental moral orientation in a timeless noumenal free choice, an ‘intelligible deed cognizable through reason alone apart from any temporal condition’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:31). The content of this timeless deed is to choose a ‘supreme maxim’ that incorporates and subordinates either the incentive of the moral law to the incentive of self-love (the morally evil propensity), or the incentive of self-love to the incentive of the moral law (the morally good propensity) (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:31). Human beings do timelessly freely choose the morally evil propensity, and this propensity provides the dispositional basis for all free choices in time, which accounts for the innate character of the propensity. This intelligible deed, however, has no phenomenal deed as its counterpart (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:31). All we observe in the phenomenal world is its effect, which is our fundamental evil moral orientation. So, the timeless free choice is what explains the innate character of radical evil.

But Kant’s appeal to a timeless choice generates yet another puzzle because Kant also claims that radical evil is ‘universal’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:30), ‘woven into human nature’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:30), and ‘entwined with humanity itself and, as it were, rooted in it’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:32). Why would all human persons make the same free choice to subordinate the incentive of the moral law to the incentive of self-love as their fundamental moral orientation? And what does that free choice have to do with human nature? Kant, in my view, fails to answer these questions and merely points to an inductive generalization as evidence for radical evil: ‘we can spare ourselves the formal proof that there must be such a corrupt propensity rooted in the human being, in view of the multitude of woeful examples that the experience of human deeds parades before us’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:32–33; italics in original). But an empirical generalization is inadequate to explain the universality of radical evil.

Allison’s proof of radical evil

Henry Allison (Reference Allison1990, Reference Allison2002, Reference Allison2020) provides a solution to this puzzle on Kant’s behalf that has the potential to explain the universality of radical evil and its relevance to human nature. In brief, the proof is that human beings must be either good or evil in their fundamental moral orientation; human nature rules out the fundamental good moral orientation; thus, the fundamental moral orientation must be evil. So, human nature ensures that human beings timelessly choose the morally evil propensity.

The first premise is explicit in Kant’s writing. In a timeless deed, human beings must choose either a morally good or evil propensity (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:22–25).Footnote 6 Human nature furnishes human beings with two incentives, and only two incentives, to action that must be incorporated into their supreme maxim that itself constitutes their fundamental moral orientation. These two incentives are self-love and respect for the moral law. If human beings timelessly choose to prioritize respect for the moral law over self-love, the meta-maxim, and fundamental moral orientation, is good. If human beings fail to prioritize respect for the moral law, they prioritize self-love instead. This choice is morally evil due to its turning away from the moral law. There is no morally indifferent option because the only possible meta-maxims involve a morally good or evil priority; there is also no mixed character option because either choice amounts to a global priority. Thus, human beings must choose either a morally good or evil propensity.

Second, Allison’s (Reference Allison2002, 342) innovation is to argue that human nature rules out choosing the morally good fundamental orientation, or the morally good propensity. To see how human nature rules it out, consider what the morally good propensity would be. It would be a supreme maxim to subordinate the incentive of self-love to the incentive of respect for the moral law. That meta-maxim amounts to a ‘spontaneous preference for the impersonal requirements of morality over an agent’s need as a sensuous being’ (Allison Reference Allison2002, 342). A fundamentally morally good human person, then, could not be tempted to transgress duty and the moral law would not even function as a constraint for them; such a human being would be beyond duty because their automatic disposition is to do what is permissible (Allison Reference Allison2002, 342).

But human nature rules out this spontaneous preference for morality. Human nature includes what Kant calls ‘a predisposition to humanity’ that provides the incentive to self-love that must be incorporated in some way into the supreme maxim (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:27; cf. 6:26–28). This predisposition is the capacity to use reason to promote self-love; it is a necessary end of human rationality to pursue happiness: ‘it is unavoidable for human nature to wish for and seek happiness, that is, satisfaction with one’s states …’ (Reference Kant and Gregor1996e, 6:387). This unavoidable end of happiness requires agents at least first to consider the claims of happiness when deliberating about what to do (Allison Reference Allison2002, 342). This is not to say that human beings cannot choose to prioritize respect for the moral law over self-love on a particular occasion but that such a choice can occur only after happiness first gets its due consideration. Such prior consideration of happiness is precisely what the morally good propensity rules out. That is, if human beings make the timeless free choice for the meta-maxim that subordinates self-love to respect for the moral law, they would have a spontaneous preference for morality and would automatically fulfil duty from duty without first considering the claims of happiness. So then, given the necessary end for happiness that is a part of human nature in the predisposition to humanity, human beings cannot choose a fundamentally good moral orientation.

Third, we can now complete Allison’s proof of radical evil. Because human beings must have either a fundamentally good or evil orientation and they cannot have a fundamentally morally good orientation, they must have a fundamentally morally evil orientation. So then, that human beings must choose the evil propensity explains the universality of radical evil.

There are important questions about the plausibility of Allison’s proof, just as there are questions about the plausibility of any interpretation of Kant’s vexing claims about radical evil, but it is not my aim to explore them in this article.Footnote 7 Instead, I lean on Allison’s general approach to show how any interpretation of the choice to be radically evil due to a necessary feature of human nature can be consistent with Kant’s views on free will, duty, and imputation, which highlights a general approach to Kant’s embracing constitutive moral luck from radical evil. I accomplish this aim by considering and responding to two objections.

Objection 1: Kant’s incompatibilism rules out a necessary choice’s being a free choice. Incompatibilism is the view that an action’s being causally determined by factors external to one’s self is incompatible with its being a free action. Free choice has the property of ‘absolute spontaneity’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:24). This spontaneity may be described negatively as ‘independence from the determining causes of the world of sense’ (Reference Kant and Gregor1996b, 4:452) and positively as the initiation of new causal chains that begin ‘a series of consequences entirely from himself’ (Reference Kant, Guyer and Wood1998, A555/B583).

Reply 1: If Kant is a leeway incompatibilist, a necessitated choice cannot be free. According to leeway incompatibilism, a choice is free only if the agent has alternative possibilities at the moment of choice. But necessitation rules out alternative possibilities. Thus, the choice to be radically evil cannot be necessitated and free if Kant is a leeway incompatibilist.

But Allison (Reference Allison2002, 343) plausibly interprets Kant as a sourcehood incompatibilist: ‘Kant characterizes freedom in terms of a causality of reason rather than a general capacity to do otherwise’ (see also Pereboom Reference Pereboom2006, 542–543). According to sourcehood incompatibilism, an action is free only if the agent’s rationality and will are the proper source of the action. Causal determination by a factor external to one’s self, such as from the external world, rules out being the proper source of the action. But the choice for radical evil is different. It is necessitated by a feature internal to the agent: human rationality. As Allen Wood (Reference Wood1984, 82) puts it, ‘Kant holds that a holy will is free even though its acts are necessitated, because they are necessitated from within reason rather than by sensuous impulses that are foreign to our rational nature.’ According to the sourcehood view, necessity is compatible with freedom if the necessity proceeds from reason. So, the choice to be radically evil can be a free choice even though it is necessitated precisely because Kant is a sourcehood incompatibilist rather than a leeway incompatibilist.

Objection 2: The necessary free choice to be radically evil involves an inconsistency if there is a duty to choose the morally good propensity. Here is the inconsistency:

  1. (1) The morally good propensity cannot be chosen.

  2. (2) Ought implies can.

  3. (3) There is a duty to choose the morally good propensity.

(1) follows from Allison’s proof and other approaches to radical evil that appeal to a feature of human nature to explain why human beings universally choose the evil propensity; thus, (1) is in good standing. (2) is an obvious feature of Kant’s moral philosophy: ‘we ought to conform to it, and therefore we must also be able to’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:62) and ‘So considered, a rational being can now righty say of every unlawful action he performed that he could have omitted it …’ (Reference Kant and Gregor1996a, 5:98). That is, if a person had a moral duty to x and she failed to x, she must have been able to x, and thus she must have had alternative possibilities at the moment of choice in that circumstance.Footnote 8 Although leeway is not essential to freedom in general, it is essential to free choices that violate duty. Thus, (2) is plausible. So, the inconsistent triad depends on a defence of (3). Although I have not seen a defence for it, one might defend it by analogy to one of Kant’s other duties. Kant embraces an obligation to be holy: ‘Here the command is “be holy”’ (Reference Kant and Gregor1996e, 6:446; cf. Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:66), which amounts to a duty to acquire a character above reproach that is well-pleasing to God.

Reply 2: But appeal to the duty to be holy is not a good reason to believe (3) because there is an important difference between these duties. The command to be holy requires God’s grace to fulfil, but a person choosing their fundamental moral character in the original circumstance cannot be a recipient of divine grace.

Consider some background on Kant’s view of divine grace.Footnote 9 Divine grace cannot improve human moral character without human free will: ‘To expect an effect of grace means, however, the very contrary, namely that the good (the morally good) is not of our doing, but that of another being – that we, therefore, can only come by it by doing nothing, and this contradicts itself’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:53, italics in original). Two movements in human free will are essential for receiving divine grace. First, before receiving divine grace, human beings must have freely made themselves ‘worthy of this assistance’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:52). To make themselves worthy, they must have fulfilled the duty to be holy to the extent that they are able:

Reason says that whoever does, in a disposition of true devotion to duty, as much lies within his power to satisfy his obligation (at least in a steady approximation toward complete conformity to the law), can legitimately hope that what lies outside his power will be supplemented by the supreme wisdom in some way or other (which can render permanent the disposition to this steady approximation) (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:171, italics in original).

[T]here is no other means (nor can there be any) by which to become worthy of heavenly assistance, except the earnest endeavor to improve his moral nature in all possible ways, thereby making himself capable of receiving a nature fully fit – as is not in his power – for divine approval (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:192).

Second, after the divine assistance comes, the human being must freely accept it:

Granted that some supernatural cooperation is also needed to his becoming good or better, whether this cooperation only consists in the diminution of obstacles or be also a positive assistance … he must accept this help (which is no small matter), i.e. he must incorporate this positive increase of force into his maxim: in this way alone is it possible that the good be imputed to him, and that he be acknowledged a good human being (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:44, italics in original).

The original circumstance in which a person timelessly chooses a fundamental moral orientation rules out the possibility of divine grace. In that circumstance, human beings make their first free choice where ‘first’ refers to logical or sequential priority rather than a temporal priority. It follows, then, that they cannot have performed more fundamental free actions to make them worthy of divine assistance nor can they have performed earlier free actions to accept divine grace. But God provides divine assistance to make human beings morally good only if they have antecedently performed free actions that make them worthy of it and they have accepted it. Thus, since human persons cannot be worthy of divine assistance in the original circumstance and they must be worthy of it to receive divine assistance, human beings cannot receive divine assistance when choosing their fundamental moral orientation. Without such assistance, they are unable to choose the morally good propensity due to the limitations of human nature.

So then, even if there is a duty to be holy, it does not follow that there is also a duty to choose the morally good propensity precisely because human beings cannot be raised beyond the powers of human nature via divine grace to choose the fundamental good moral orientation. If there is no other reason to embrace (3), we should conclude that (3) is false. After all, we have strong reasons to embrace (1) and (2), and they are inconsistent with (3).Footnote 10 Thus, ‘ought implies can’ provides no reason to doubt that human beings can freely choose the morally evil propensity precisely because there is no duty to choose the morally good propensity.

Therefore, the choice to be radically evil ensured by a necessary feature of human nature is consistent with Kant’s broader views on imputation, freedom, and the ‘ought implies can’ link between duty and freedom.

From radical evil to constitutive moral luck

Constitutive moral luck occurs when an agent possesses dispositions at least in part due to factors beyond her control and those dispositions positively affect her praiseworthiness or blameworthiness.Footnote 11 David Enoch and Andrei Marmor (Reference Enoch and Marmor2007, 426) helpfully highlight an ambiguity in this definition concerning whether the object of moral responsibility is a disposition or an action. We can disambiguate it according to these two objects of moral responsibility. First, direct constitutive moral luck occurs when a person’s possession of a disposition is influenced by factors beyond her control and those factors positively affect her praiseworthiness or blameworthiness for the disposition. For example, a person raised in an irascible household possesses irascible tendencies through habituation that is at least in part beyond her control. If she is blameworthy for being irascible, it is a case of direct constitutive moral luck. Second, indirect constitutive moral luck occurs when a person’s possession of a disposition is influenced by factors beyond her control and that disposition positively affects her praiseworthiness or blameworthiness for an action. For example, if a person is blameworthy for performing wrathful actions that are motivated by an irascible disposition that is possessed due at least partially to factors outside of her control, it is a case of indirect constitutive moral luck.

The Allison-style interpretation of radical evil definitely commits Kant to indirect constitutive moral luck. After all, a necessary feature of human nature beyond the control of each human being ensures that in the original choice scenario, each human being freely chooses the evil propensity. And it must be a choice for which a person is blameworthy given that human beings are blameworthy for its effect – namely, the morally evil propensity. Thus, interpretations of radical evil that explain its universality and innateness through a timeless free choice ensured by a feature of human nature are committed to indirect constitutive moral luck.Footnote 12

The Allison-style interpretation of radical evil plausibly also commits Kant to the existence of direct constitutive moral luck. It is beyond a person’s control to some extent that they possess the morally evil propensity because human nature has so confined the options for free choice in the original circumstance to guarantee that each human possesses the morally evil propensity. So, even though it is a free choice to adopt the morally evil propensity, the choice is so shaped by luck that possession of the morally evil propensity is due at least partially to factors beyond the agent’s control. And human beings are also blameworthy for the morally evil propensity: it is ‘something that a human being can be held accountable for’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c: 6:32), ‘we can well be responsible for the propensity to evil … imputed to the subject as itself guilty of it’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c: 6:35), and it is something for which we have ‘innate guilt’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c: 6:38). So then, the possession of the morally evil propensity is significantly influenced by factors beyond their control (namely, human nature) in a way that positively affects blameworthiness for it. So, Kant embraces at least some degree of direct constitutive moral luck in every human person. To my knowledge, no one else has argued that Kant embraces direct constitutive moral luck, and so these passages point to a completely new source of moral luck in Kant’s moral philosophy.

One might reasonably wonder about the coherence between Kant’s views of freedom and the morally evil propensity, on the one hand, and the contemporary category of luck, on the other. I consider and reply to two more objections.

Objection 3: It is incoherent to assert that a free action is lucky. Intuitively, an action is free only if its occurrence is not a matter of luck (Mele Reference Mele2006; van Inwagen Reference van Inwagen and Kane2002). Radical evil is chosen as a matter of constitutive luck. Thus, the choice for radical evil cannot be free.

Reply 3: I reject the premise that ‘radical evil is chosen as a matter of constitutive luck’ – at least if ‘choosing as a matter of luck’ includes the normative property of ruling out freedom. According to Allison, if the decision proceeds from constitutive features of her reason and will in the right way – and the choice for radical evil does – the choice is up to the agent in the sense relevant to be a free action. Thus, the choice for the evil propensity must not occur as ‘a matter of luck’. But how, then, does luck figure into the choice? There is a plausible distinction between an event’s being a matter of luck and its being influenced by luck. A choice’s being influenced by luck means that factors beyond the agent’s control shape the manner in which the choice is up to the agent, for example, by influencing the choice options, incentives, and difficulties. In this way, the free choice to be radically evil is significantly influenced by luck but is not a matter of luck.

Objection 4: It is incoherent to assert that a necessary event is lucky. Intuitively, an event is lucky only if it could easily have failed to occur (Pritchard Reference Pritchard, Church and Hartman2019) or if its occurrence is improbable (Rescher Reference Rescher, Church and Hartman2019). The necessary choice of radical evil could not easily have failed to occur and it is not improbable. Thus, the choice of radical evil is not lucky. If the choice of radical evil is not lucky, the choice of radical evil is not morally lucky. Thus, the choice of radical evil is not morally lucky.

Reply 4: I deny the premise that ‘if the choice of radical evil is not lucky, the choice of radical evil is not morally lucky’. That premise assumes that moral luck is a species of luck. But it is not. The phrase ‘moral luck’ is a misnomer; it is not about luck per se (Hartman Reference Hartman2017, 23–31; see also Anderson Reference Anderson2019; Statman Reference Statman, Church and Hartman2019). Most philosophers writing on moral luck employ the lack of control conception of luck with the clear understanding that it is an implausible definition of luck itself.Footnote 13 But lack of control is a paradigmatic feature of lucky events. And it is this paradigmatic feature of luck that is necessary and sufficient to generate the tension in our moral thinking that Bernard Williams (Reference Williams1981, 21–22) coined ‘moral luck’ to describe. The tension is in a person’s being praiseworthy or blameworthy for something that is beyond her control in some way. We can substitute ‘moral lack of control’ for ‘moral luck’, and nothing substantive would change about this debate. But if the absence of control is the feature of luck highlighted in a definition of moral luck, the problem dissolves; a lucky event can be necessary if what makes it necessary is beyond one’s control (Hartman Reference Hartman2019b, 3186). So then, the necessary choice to be radically evil is morally lucky because it is features of human nature about reason beyond their control that ensure the choice.

Conclusion

The received view about Kant is that his moral philosophy rules out all moral luck. But Kant’s claims about radical evil highlight previously unrecognized sources of indirect and direct constitutive moral luck in his moral philosophy.

Radical evil is a disposition that a person has necessarily and innately but for which she is blameworthy. If human beings are blameworthy for radical evil, they must have freely chosen it, but the free choice must be timeless for radical evil to be innate. Following Henry Allison, I argued that certain kinds of necessitated choices can be free because Kant is a sourcehood incompatibilist; alternative possibilities at the moment of choice are not necessary for a choice to be free. Additionally, I argued that a timeless, necessary, and free choice for the morally evil propensity does not violate ‘ought implies can’ because there is no duty to choose the morally good propensity in the original circumstance. Furthermore, I argued also that the free choice to have the morally evil propensity should be classified as ‘influenced by luck’ rather than occurring as ‘a matter of luck’ and that an essential feature of human nature can be a suitable source of ‘luck’ in ‘moral luck’ because the relevant definition of ‘luck’ is the absence of control.

Allison-style interpretations of radical evil commit Kant to the existence of two kinds of constitutive moral luck. The blameworthy free choice for the morally evil propensity shaped by constitutive features of human nature is a case of indirect constitutive moral luck. The blameworthy disposition (the morally evil propensity) possessed at least in part due to factors beyond the agent’s control is a case of direct constitutive moral luck.

This article strengthens the case against the received view that Kant’s moral philosophy precludes all moral luck by appealing to passages from the Religion. Thus, philosophers have yet another reason to reject the received view, which may also provide Kantians and Kant scholars an occasion to check their reasons if they deny moral luck.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Conrad Damstra, Chris Firestone, Brandon Love, Stephen Palmquist, Bas Tönissen, and especially Benjamin Vilhauer for discussing with me the ideas in this article; I am also grateful to two anonymous referees and the editor of Religious Studies for their comments and consideration. Finally, I thank audience members for lively questions and objections at the 2020 Leuven Kant Conference hosted online by KU Leuven, Belgium, and the 2023 Conference on Kant’s Moral Vision as Affirmative Religion at the University of Notre Dame, Indiana, put on by Meredith Drees.

Footnotes

1. For an interesting treatment of Kant’s position on luck and moral properties different from praiseworthiness and blameworthiness such as moral obligation and virtue, see Athanassoulis (Reference Athanassoulis2005, chs. 6–7).

2. In Hartman Reference Hartman(forthcoming), I have enlisted Kant’s categorical imperative to argue that proponents of moral luck can accommodate a sense in which luck should make people more sparing with blame: although various kinds of luck can increase a person’s blameworthiness, the categorical imperative implies that people should forgo angrily blaming the person who deserves it at least sometimes due in part to their common moral luck.

3. The caveat that ‘at least for part of their lives’ is to make room for Kant’s view that it is possible for human beings to cease to be radically evil through some kind of moral conversion.

4. As for its prominence, consider a claim from Erik Hanson (Reference Hanson, Fraser and Onof2012): ‘Many subsequent articles [on radical evil] tend to defend either [Henry] Allison or [Allen] Wood.’

5. The ‘radical’ in ‘radical evil’ is used in an etymological sense to signify the ‘root’ of all moral evil (Allison Reference Allison2002, 344); it does not mean that human persons are diabolical or evil through and through.

6. Allison (Reference Allison2002, 338) rejects an ontological interpretation of the timeless free choice. He construes the choice as a thought experiment or postulate to which Kant is committed to make sense of the fundamental evil disposition. According to this interpretation, my claim is that Kant accepts constitutive moral luck as a postulate.

7. Here is a serious objection to Allison’s characterization of the morally good propensity, which I thank an anonymous referee for raising: (1) If a fundamentally good human cannot be tempted to transgress duty and the moral law would not even function as a constraint for them, then, by parity of reasoning, a fundamentally evil human cannot be tempted to fulfil duty and the moral law would not even function as a motive for them. (2) A fundamentally evil human can feel the pull to fulfil duty, and the moral law does function as a motive for them. Thus, (3) it is not the case that a fundamentally good human could not be tempted to transgress duty and the moral law would not even function as a constraint for them. Allison does not consider this powerful objection. But a plausible defence of Allison’s position would have to highlight some kind of asymmetry between the incentives of self-love and respect for the moral law that would provide a ground for denying (1).

8. How exactly Kant understands ‘ought implies can’ is controversial (see, e.g., Kohl Reference Kohl2015; Stern Reference Stern2004).

9. Here is Kant’s moral argument for the necessity of divine grace: ‘the command that we ought to become better human beings still resounds unabated in our souls; consequently, we must also be capable of it, even if what we can do is of itself insufficient and, by virtue of it, we only make ourselves receptive to a higher assistance inscrutable to us’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:45, italics in original). In other words, human beings have a duty to be holy; ought implies can; but human beings are unable to become holy on their own steam (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c, 6:178); and thus, human beings can rationally hope to ‘achieve it [the holy disposition] by God’s cooperation’ (Reference Kant, Gregor, Anchor, Wood and Di Giovanni1996d, 7:44).

10. One might think that divine grace is another source of constitutive moral luck (cf. Hartman Reference Hartman2014, 78). God’s assistance is lucky for human beings. It is outside of their control that God exists and has the qualities that ensure assistance for people who are worthy of it. I agree that there is a kind of moral luck implicated in acquiring a holy will. But acquiring a holy will involves an increase in the property of moral goodness by luck, and moral goodness is not the kind of moral evaluation at stake in the contemporary moral luck debate, which is exclusively about moral praiseworthiness and blameworthiness.

11. The ‘at least in part’ is important because constitutive luck comes in degrees. Some dispositions are more constitutively lucky than others if their possession is due more to factors beyond their possessor’s control.

12. Other interpretations of Kant about radical evil preclude constitutive moral luck. For example, Galen Strawson (Reference Strawson1994, Reference Strawson2010) argues that we can find the following principles – call them Strawson’s Premises 1 and 2 – in Kant’s thinking, which Strawson employs in his famous argument for the impossibility of moral responsibility (see also Adams Reference Adams and Ambrosio1999, 82):

SP1: An agent is morally responsible for her action only if she is morally responsible for the character trait that explains her action.

SP2: An agent is morally responsible for her character trait only if she has freely performed an action in which she intentionally and successfully brought about her having that character trait.

Strawson offers various proof-texts for SP1 and SP2. Here is the proof-text for SP2: ‘The human being must make or have made himself into whatever he is or should become in a moral sense, good or evil’ (Kant (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c), 6:44; see Strawson (Reference Strawson1994), 11; (Reference Strawson2010), 42n35). It provides strong support for SP2. Here is the proof-text for SP1: ‘[A] rational being can now rightly say of every unlawful action he performed that he could have omitted it even though as appearance it is sufficiently determined in the past and, so far, is inevitably necessary; for this action, with all the past which determines it, belongs to a single phenomenon of his character, which he gives to himself and in accordance with which he imputes to himself, as a cause independent of all sensibility, the causality of those appearances’ (Reference Kant and Gregor1996a, 5:98, italics mine; see Strawson Reference Strawson1994, 23n8; Reference Strawson2010, 42). This quote, however, does not clearly support SP1 because it does not highlight a link that requires responsibility for character as a ground for responsibility for action.

Nevertheless, I locate a passage in the Religion that supports SP1: ‘This [fundamental evil] disposition too, however, must be adopted through the free power of choice, for otherwise it could not be imputed. But there cannot be any further cognition of the subjective ground or the cause of this adoption (although we cannot avoid asking about it), for otherwise we would have to adduce still another maxim into which the disposition would have to be incorporated, and this maxim must in turn have its ground’ (Reference Kant, Di Giovanni, Wood and Di Giovanni1996c: 6:25). This passage appears to indicate that to be morally responsible for an action (or maxim), we need to be morally responsible for its ground – the character from which the action (or maxim) is chosen.

One problem with this interpretation is that it ascribes something uncharitable to Kant – namely, an arbitrarily stopped regress of free choices. For if we must posit a timeless free choice to explain being morally responsible for the character that explains free choices in time, we would have to posit yet another timeless choice to stand behind the first timeless free choice – ad infinitum. Strawson (Reference Strawson1994, Reference Strawson2010) himself uses SP1 and SP2 to generate such a regress in his argument for the impossibility of moral responsibility. The principle of charity suffices to motivate us to look for alternative interpretations.

13. Andrew Latus (Reference Latus2000, 167) offers the following canonical counterexample: it is outside of my control that the sun rose today, and so the lack of control definition implies that it is lucky for me that it rose. Intuitively, however, it is not lucky for me that the sun rose, and so the lack of control definition fails (cf. Riggs Reference Riggs, Church and Hartman2019).

References

Adams, RM (1999) Original sin: A study in the interaction between philosophy and theology. In Ambrosio, FJ (ed), The Question of Christian Philosophy Today. New York: Fordham University Press, 80110.Google Scholar
Allison, HE (1990) Kant’s Theory of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, HE (2002) On the very idea of a propensity to evil. The Journal of Value Inquiry 36, 337348. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1016112805381CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, HE (2020) Kant’s Conception of Freedom: A Developmental and Critical Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, MB (2019) Moral luck as moral lack of control. Southern Journal of Philosophy 57, 529. https://doi.org/10.1111/sjp.12317CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Athanassoulis, N (2005) Morality, Moral Luck, and Responsibility: Fortune’s Web. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D and Marmor, A (2007) The case against moral luck. Law and Philosophy 26, 405436. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-006-9001-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, EM (2012) Kant: Radical evil. In Fraser, J, and Onof, C (eds), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/rad-evil/.Google Scholar
Hartman, RJ (2014) How to apply molinism to the theological problem of moral luck. Faith and Philosophy 31, 6890. https://doi.org/10.5840/faithphil2014265CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, RJ (2017) In Defense of Moral Luck: Why Luck Often Affects Praiseworthiness and Blameworthiness. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, RJ (2019a) Kant does not deny resultant moral luck. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 43, 136150. https://doi.org/10.1111/misp.12109CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, RJ (2019b) Moral luck and the unfairness of morality. Philosophical Studies 176, 31793197. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1169-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, RJ (2024) Circumstantial and constitutive moral luck in Kant’s moral philosophy. European Journal of Philosophy 32, 353359. https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12844CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, RJ (forthcoming) Moral luck and the imperfect duty to spare blame. Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-024-00907-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahn, S (2021) Kant’s philosophy of moral luck. Sophia 60, 365387. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-020-00802-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I (1996a) Critique of Practical Reason. In Gregor, MJ (trans and ed), Practical Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 133272.Google Scholar
Kant, I (1996b) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. In Gregor, MJ (trans and ed), Practical Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 39108.Google Scholar
Kant, I (1996c) Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, Di Giovanni, G (trans). In Wood, AW and Di Giovanni, G (eds), Religion and Rational Theology. New York: Cambridge University Press, 39216.Google Scholar
Kant, I (1996d) The Conflict of the Faculties, Gregor, MJ and Anchor, R (trans). In Wood, AW and Di Giovanni, G (eds), Religion and Rational Theology. New York: Cambridge University Press, 233327.Google Scholar
Kant, I (1996e) The Metaphysics of Morals. In Gregor, MJ (trans and ed), Practical Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 353604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I (1998) Critique of Pure Reason. In Guyer, P, and Wood, AW (trans and eds). New York: Cambridge University Press 81-704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohl, M (2015) Kant and ‘ought implies can’. The Philosophical Quarterly 65, 690710. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqv044CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latus, A (2000) Moral and epistemic luck. Journal of Philosophical Research 25, 149172. https://doi.org/10.5840/jpr_2000_21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mele, A (2006) Free Will and Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, K (2019) Immanuel Kant on moral luck. In Church, IM and Hartman, RJ (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy and Psychology of Luck. New York: Routledge, 5769.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T (ed), (1979) Moral luck. In Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2438.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D (2006) Kant on transcendental freedom. Philosophy & Phenomenological Research 73, 537567. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00548.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D (2019) Modal accounts of luck. In Church, IM and Hartman, RJ (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy and Psychology of Luck. New York: Routledge, 115124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rescher, N (2019) The probability account of luck. In Church, IM and Hartman, RJ (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy and Psychology of Luck. New York: Routledge, 136147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riggs, W (2019) The lack of control account of luck. In Church, IM and Hartman, RJ (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy and Psychology of Luck. New York: Routledge, 125135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Statman, D (2019) The definition of luck and the problem of moral luck. In Church, IM and Hartman, RJ (eds), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy and Psychology of Luck. New York: Routledge, 195205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stern, R (2004) Does ‘ought’ imply ‘can’? And does Kant think it does? Utilitas 16, 4261. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0953820803001055CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G (1994) The impossibility of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies 75, 524. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00989879CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G (2010) [1986] Freedom and Belief, revised edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press. References are to the revised version.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaida, IC (2014) The problem of agency and the problem of accountability in Kant’s ethics. European Journal of Philosophy 22, 110137. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2011.00480.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Inwagen, P (2002) Free will remains a mystery. In Kane, R (ed), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 158177.Google Scholar
Williams, B (ed) (1981) Moral luck. In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2039.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, AW (ed) (1984) Kant’s compatibilism. In Self and Nature in Kant’s Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 73101.Google Scholar