Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T09:25:02.100Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The unreality of traditional Islamic theism's views on belief, providence, and eschatology: a rejoinder to Tabur

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2024

Imran Aijaz*
Affiliation:
Department of Language, Culture, and the Arts, The University of Michigan-Dearborn, Dearborn, MI, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In a previous work, I argue that traditional Islamic theism's understanding of the world, when juxtaposed with key facts of our world's religious diversity, is implausible. On this understanding, roughly, the truth of tawḥīd (Islamic monotheism) is universally evident, as is belief in its truth. Faithful Muslims act appropriately on knowledge of tawḥīd and are rewarded with heaven, whereas non-Muslims culpably refuse to do so and are eternally punished in hell. Such a view of the world, I argue, is not borne out by empirical observation and philosophical reflection. In a recent article, Ayşenur Ünügür Tabur criticizes this argument, presenting a number of objections to it. In this rejoinder, I argue that her objections, which primarily consist of misstatements and irrelevancies, fail to refute my argument. Since traditional Islamic theism's understanding of the world includes the view that some people will be eternally punished in hell, Tabur augments her discussion of my argument by attempting to solve the Problem of Hell. In my rejoinder to Tabur, I further argue that her proffered solution to this problem is woefully inadequate.

Type
Original Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

An air of unreality surrounds traditional Islamic theism's account of the demographics of religious belief in our world. By ‘traditional Islamic theism’, I mean the doctrinal core of Sunni orthodoxy as primarily understood in the Qurʾān, aḥādīth (reports of sayings and actions attributed to the Prophet Muhammad), and the general tenor in classical Muslim interpretations of these sacred texts. From this religious vantage point, the account of the global religious landscape, put simply, goes something like this:

Everyone in the world believes that Islamic monotheism is true. Only faithful Muslims practically adhere to this belief. Non-Muslims refuse to do so and are culpable rejecters of faith. There is no non-belief in the truth of Islamic monotheism because God has providentially ordered His creation to make its truth evident to all. Faithful Muslims, individuals who practically adhere to their belief in Islamic monotheism, are rewarded with heaven. Non-Muslims, individuals who refuse to adhere practically to their belief in Islamic monotheism and culpably reject faith, are punished in hell.

Among Muslim thinkers who defend traditional Islamic theism, there is, to be sure, substantive discussion and refinement of this account. Still, most of it is in the service of upholding its essence. For many outside Islam and some reflective Muslims, it is undoubtedly difficult to believe that this account accurately reflects reality. It strains credulity for several reasons, not least of which is the phenomenon of religious diversity. For instance, despite all appearances to the contrary, are we really to think that Buddhists in Cambodia, followers of Shinto in Japan, and secular humanists in Norway believe that Islamic monotheism is true, culpably reject it in their actions, and are bound for hell?

In ‘Belief, Providence and Eschatology: Some Philosophical Problems in Islamic Theism’ (Aijaz Reference Aijaz2008; hereafter abbreviated as ‘BPE’), I contend that viewing the world's religious diversity using traditional Islamic theism as a lens creates serious difficulties stemming from empirical observation and philosophical reflection. More specifically, I argue that many reasonable people, including plenty of Buddhists, Christians, Hindus, atheists, etc., do not believe that Islamic monotheism is true, and there are many to whom its truth is not evident, even after sustained reflection. I further argue that it is implausible to think such non-Muslims culpably reject Islamic faith and are bound for hell. I conclude my argument in BPE by stating that traditional Islamic theism's understanding of the demographics of religious belief in the world ought to be rejected. This rejection need not involve an outright dismissal of the Islamic religion. It can, instead, be seen as clearing the ground to investigate more plausible Islamic responses to religious diversity.

In response to my argument in BPE, Ayşenur Ünügür Tabur presents an Islamic apologetic that principally contests my analysis of how non-Muslims are perceived in traditional Islamic theism (Tabur Reference Tabur2023). Additionally, even though I do not include a direct assessment of the Problem of Hell as part of my argument, she extends her apologetic efforts to show that God's existence is compatible with the eternal suffering of some people in hell. In this article, I argue that Tabur's Islamic apologetic fails to accomplish its intended aims. I will first reply to her criticisms of my core argument in BPE. Then, I will address her attempt to solve the Problem of Hell.

My core argument in BPE

In BPE, I present an argument against traditional Islamic theism that hinges on the concepts of belief, providence, and eschatology found in the Qurʾān. Here, I will give a summary of the argument.

A straightforward reading of the Qurʾān, which takes its apparent meanings at face value, gives us a picture of the world in which the concepts of belief, providence, and eschatology feature prominently (BPE, 233–242). In this picture, all human beings believe that tawḥīd (frequently and roughly translated into English as ‘Islamic monotheism’), arguably the most essential doctrine in Islam, is true. This includes human beings who have ʾīmān (faith) as well as those who do not; the Qurʾān refers to the latter as individuals who are guilty of kufr, a term that it uses throughout its verses as the antonym of ʾīmān. Central to the Qurʾānic notion of kufr is the act of intentionally ‘concealing’ or ‘covering up’ what one knows to be true. The reference to knowledge here is significant. If S knows that p, then S also believes that p (since believing that p is a necessary condition for knowing that p, a point generally agreed upon by epistemologists). In the Qurʾān, the kāfir, one who is guilty of kufr, knows that many religious propositions are true, including those about the truth of tawḥīd, but culpably rejects them in practice. Since the kāfir knows that tawḥīd is true, he or she also believes that it is true, as does the one who has ʾīmān, the mu'min. Knowing that tawḥīd is true does not, however, entail believing in tawḥīd, where ‘believing in’ is understood in a fiducial sense.Footnote 1 Herein lies a crucial difference between the kāfir and the mu'min. The mu'min practically adheres to the knowledge of tawḥīd by conforming to the fundamental divine imperative to worship God alone. In contrast, the kāfir does not, violating this imperative in some blasphemous manner.Footnote 2 Although the Qurʾān details significant practical differences between the two, these responses are nevertheless conceptually connected to epistemic and doxastic states shared by the mu'min and kāfir: knowledge and belief that tawḥīd is true. ʾImān and kufr, both of which entail the belief that tawḥīd is true, jointly exhaust the possible stances mentioned in the Qurʾān that one can adopt about God. It follows from this that, according to the Qurʾān, everyone believes that tawḥīd is true.

The Qurʾānic explanation for the universality of belief in the truth of tawḥīd is that God has created a providentially unambiguous world. Our world exhibits ‘signs’ or ʾāyāt, which are ubiquitous, unambiguously present for all, and evince the truth of tawḥīd. The faithful (Muslims) respond appropriately to religious knowledge obtained through these signs, while the rejectors of faith (non-Muslims) do so inappropriately. Whether the formation of religious knowledge in these cases is inferential or non-inferential appears incidental to the Qurʾānic narrative, as its primary emphasis in discussing the signs of God is that all human beings know that tawḥīd is true.

Since all human beings possess knowledge of tawḥīd, there is no inculpable non-compliance with it due to factors such as ignorance, conscientious rejection, etc. If one is not a mu'min (a Muslim) who responds appropriately to this knowledge by practically adhering to it (e.g. through worshipping God alone), one must be a kāfir (a non-Muslim) who culpably refuses to adhere to it in practice (e.g. choosing to worship an idol instead of, or alongside, the true God). In the Qurʾānic account of eschatology, such culpable rejection is a characteristic feature of non-Muslims eternally punished in hell. On the other hand, faithful Muslims rewarded with entry into heaven are described as having practically adhered to their knowledge of tawḥīd. How one responds to the knowledge of tawḥīd undergirds the salvific exclusivism derived from a plain reading of the Qurʾān.

In BPE, I argue that this basic Qurʾānic picture of the world featuring the concepts of belief, providence, and eschatology is false. My criticisms include the following three points, which are interconnected. First, belief in the truth of tawḥīd is evidently not universal. Second, our world is not providentially unambiguous but, instead, is religiously ambiguous. Third, one cannot reasonably maintain that all non-Muslims know the truth of tawḥīd, culpably refuse to act on its truth, and merit eternal punishment in hell (BPE, 242–247). Given its strong association with the basic Qurʾānic picture I discuss in BPE, I also present these criticisms as a critique of traditional Islamic theism. As my criticisms are directed against a particular interpretation of Islam, even if a traditionalist one, I conclude my discussion in BPE by exploring how one might reinterpret the Qurʾānic concepts of belief, providence, and eschatology in a way that is congruent with our understanding of the world and at least some aspects of the Islamic religion (BPE, 247–249).

An assessment of Tabur's criticisms of my core argument in BPE

Tabur's criticisms of my core argument in BPE rest, by my count, on five main objections that can be distilled from her discussion. In assessing her criticisms, I will list each objection and my response.

Tabur's first objection begins by noting that my discussion of the Qurʾānic account of kufr focuses only on a necessary but not sufficient condition for kufr to occur. This necessary condition is having knowledge of tawḥīd. From this correct observation, she misattributes an inference to me, stating I ‘[conclude] that all non-Muslims are deemed to be kâfir in the Quran for their rejection of tawhīd in their actions’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 4). In BPE, I argue that an analysis of Qurʾānic verses in which kufr, the kāfir, and the kuffār are discussed reveals that knowledge of tawḥīd is a necessary condition for the applicability of these concepts. I do not, however, present any argument to conclude that, in the Qurʾān, those who practically reject tawḥīd are eo ipso guilty of kufr. Instead, I look at Qurʾānic data that either explicitly identifies cases of kufr (e.g. the case of Satan in 2:34) or else implies it (e.g. the case of Abraham's condemnation of idol worship in 21:51–70 strongly suggests that devotion to idols is kufr). When such confirmed cases of kufr obtained from Qurʾānic data are analysed, it is clear that possessing knowledge of tawḥīd is common among them. Tabur's claim that my analysis of kufr is ‘self-referentially incoherent’ due to foregoing an investigation of the sufficient conditions for kufr to obtain is, therefore, ill-considered (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 4). In BPE, I focus on knowledge of tawḥīd as a necessary condition for kufr to support two key points: (1) according to the Qurʾān, belief in the truth of tawḥīd is universal – even the kāfir believes that it is true (BPE, 240); and, (2) one cannot legitimately apply the Qurʾānic account of kufr to non-Muslims in our world who do not believe that tawḥīd is true (BPE, 246–247).

In the Qurʾānic narrative, as I note in BPE, the only alternative to being a mu'min (Muslim) is being a kāfir (non-Muslim). Tabur's second objection is that I do not offer any textual justification for this claim other than a passage from Toshihiko Izutsu's The Concept of Belief in Islamic Theology. In this book, Izutsu explains that the Qurʾān assigns humanity into two categories through a simple disjunction: a person is either Muslim or kāfir (Izutsu Reference Izutsu1965, 7–8). Tabur does not contest Izutsu's analysis but claims it only distinguishes between those who accept Islam and those who reject it, not between those who act on tawḥīd and those who do not (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 4–5). But this point is neither here nor there, as it leaves intact my point that the Qurʾān portrays only the Muslim as a mu'min and only the non-Muslim as a kāfir. The mu'min-kāfir dichotomy pervades the Qurʾānic narrative and is made clear in several verses, such as Qurʾān 64:2: ‘It is He who created you, and among you is the disbeliever [kāfir], and among you is the believer [mu'min]. And Allah, of what you do, is Seeing’ (emphasis mine).Footnote 3 Elsewhere, Izutsu explains that this dichotomy is plain to see in the Qurʾān:

That kufr is the exact antithesis of ‘belief’ [ʾīmān] is a point which requires no laboring . . . [I]t is this basic antithesis between īmān and kufr that furnishes the ultimate yardstick by which all human qualities are divided, in Islamic outlook, into two radically opposed moral categories . . . Everywhere in the Qur’ān this fundamental opposition is perceptible. (Izutsu Reference Izutsu2002, 187)Footnote 4

As indicated previously, the mu'min practically adheres to the knowledge of tawḥīd, whereas the kāfir does not.

Tabur raises a third objection to my argument in BPE, motivating it by (mis)using my analysis of tawḥīd. She begins this particular objection by repeating the claim she misattributes to me in her first objection, viz., that ‘the Quran labels all non-Muslims kâfir solely based on their practical rejection of tawhīd’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5; emphasis mine). As I have explained in response to that objection, this is not what I claim or argue. Tabur alleges that my position is ‘self-refuting’ given my understanding of tawḥīd. Why? Because, she says, there are several Jews and Christians who believe in the existence of an omnipotent, omniscient, and morally perfect Creator of the universe (a belief that Tabur claims ‘corresponds to belief in tawhīd’ as described by me) and act on it. This fact, Tabur goes on to object, means that such individuals should be referred to as Muslims, according to my analysis (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 4). Not at all. Let me explain what has gone wrong here for Tabur. She mistakenly thinks that I am committed to the following conditional:

  1. (1) If S practically rejects the knowledge of tawḥīd, then S is a kāfir (non-Muslim).

Using (1), Tabur compounds her mistaken understanding of my position by thinking that I must, in virtue of a supposed logical consequence, be further committed to another conditional:

  1. (2) If S does not practically reject (i.e. acts on) the knowledge of tawḥīd, then S is not a kāfir (i.e. is a Muslim).

Tabur thinks that since many Jews and Christians meet the description contained in the antecedent of (2), it follows that they are Muslims. She submits that this conclusion is problematic for my analysis. Unfortunately, there are several errors here. To begin with, (2) does not validly follow from (1), being a clear case of the fallacy of denying the antecedent. In any case, as I have already explained, I am not committed to (1). Furthermore, Tabur badly misrepresents my analysis of tawḥīd by discarding the theological meaning of the term I use and instead substituting it with one that refers to generic monotheism. The classical theological understanding of tawḥīd, at least in Sunni orthodoxy, sees it as comprised of three inextricable elements: (1) tawḥīd al-rubūbīyah (the oneness of God); (2) tawḥīd al-ulūhiyyah (nothing other than God has any right to be worshipped); and, (3) tawḥīd al-asmā’ wa’ṣ ṣifāt (God's names and qualities are unique to Him). Instead of discussing this understanding of tawḥīd, which I make explicit in BPE (233–244), she takes tawḥīd to mean belief in the existence of an omnipotent, omniscient, and morally perfect Creator. When tawḥīd is properly understood in its classical theological sense, however, one cannot, from the perspective of traditional Islamic theism, maintain that Jews and Christians act appropriately on it. The Qurʾān is clear on this point. Here are a few examples:

They have certainly disbelieved who say that Allah is Christ, the son of Mary. (5:17)

They have certainly disbelieved who say, ‘Allah is the third of three.’ And there is no god except one God. And if they do not desist from what they are saying, there will surely afflict the disbelievers among them a painful punishment. (5:73)

The Jews say, ‘Ezra is the son of Allah’; and the Christians say, ‘The Messiah is the son of Allah.’ That is their statement from their mouths; they imitate the saying of those who disbelieved [before them]. May Allah destroy them; how are they deluded? They have taken their scholars and monks as lords besides Allah, and [also] the Messiah, the son of Mary. And they were not commanded except to worship one God; there is no deity except Him. Exalted is He above whatever they associate with Him. (9:30–31)

The fundamental Qurʾānic complaint against Jews and Christians is that they commit the unpardonable offence of shirk (associating other things with God in worship):

Indeed, Allah does not forgive association with Him, but He forgives what is less than that for whom He wills. And he who associates others with Allah has certainly fabricated a tremendous sin. (4:48)

Consequently, Tabur's third objection to my argument is off the mark because of her compounded misstatements and errors in describing my account of tawḥīd.

Tabur misstates another aspect of my argument in BPE to advance a fourth objection. She alleges I incorporate, as a premise for my argument, the view that belief in tawḥīd is non-inferential, according to Islam. I do not, Tabur objects, support this view by referencing Islamic sources (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5). But nowhere in my discussion do I commit myself to a specific Islamic view of the causal process giving rise to belief in the truth of tawḥīd.Footnote 5 I merely note that all human beings have evidence for its truth, according to the Qurʾān. Deciding whether the Qurʾān regards the truth of tawḥīd as basically (i.e. non-inferentially) or inferentially evident is not necessary for my argument, as it is tangential to the point I want to emphasize. In the Qurʾān, the universality of belief in the truth of tawḥīd is connected to the universality of God's signs in the world (BPE, 241). Still, I will engage with Tabur's response to the position she misattributes to me, as doing so will reveal additional insights useful for the present discussion.

Tabur maintains that the mainstream Islamic view – informed by the Qurʾān and its interpreters in the Ashʿarī and Māturīdī schools – regards belief in the truth of tawḥīd to be inferentially evident. More specifically, it is derived from the evidence provided by creation. But this derivation, she further maintains, may not be possible or incumbent for some individuals. She thinks this position is warranted in light of Al-Ashʿarī's and Al-Māturīdī's views about religious knowledge (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5). ‘Despite accepting its metaphysical possibility’, writes Tabur, ‘the Ashʿārī view rejects [the] necessity [of reasoning to the truth of tawḥīd] and therefore the culpability of any person without her access to the divine message sent through prophets’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5). Describing it this way, however, doesn't make clear that what is being rejected is the moral necessity (i.e. moral obligation) of reasoning to the truth of tawḥīd. What is not being rejected is epistemic necessity, which Boris Kment provides a helpful conception of (in relation to empirical evidence):

[A] proposition P is epistemically necessary for an agent A just in case the empirical evidence A possesses and ideal reasoning (i.e. reasoning unrestricted by cognitive limitations) are sufficient to rule out ~P. (Kment Reference Kment2021)

Understood in this way, a proposition P can be epistemically necessary for an agent A without A having any moral obligation to believe that P. Aisha's belief that shadows are caused by a body coming between light and a surface, for example, may be epistemically necessary for her without Aisha having any moral obligation to acquire this belief. This distinction between epistemic necessity and moral necessity (or moral obligation) is made clear by Al-Shahrastānī, whom Tabur references in describing Al-Ashʿarī's position, in the following remarks:

Ashʿarī [says] that whatever is of obligation is so because of revelation. Reason does not impose any obligation, nor does it declare anything good or bad. Knowledge of God is, indeed, acquired by reason, but it is through revelation that it becomes of obligation to know him. (Al-Shahrastānī Reference Al-Shahrastānī2014, 86; emphasis mine)

Perusing Al-Ashʿarī's writings, we can see that he is committed to the epistemic necessity of belief in the truth of tawḥīd based on the empirical evidence provided by creation. Here is how Abdullah Saeed describes the argument for the existence and nature of God that we find in the opening chapter of Al-Ashʿarī's Kitāb al-Lumaʾ:

[W]hen human beings reflect on the way they were conceived, how they grew from one state to another until they reached perfection, and realized that they could not have instigated or performed this, they will be in no doubt of a creator who is all-powerful, all-knowing, willing, wise and all-merciful. The human being who has a sound intellect, according to al-Ash‘ari, would find it inconceivable that these acts were brought about by chance or autonomously, since their manifestly deliberate choice and perfection would deny that claim, pointing instead to their creator. (Saeed Reference Saeed2006, 67; emphasis mine)Footnote 6

For Al-Ashʿarī, knowledge of tawḥīd is secured by reflecting on oneself and the world. There is no suggestion whatsoever in his writings that one may reasonably remain ignorant of God's existence and nature after such reflection or that contrary viewpoints on these matters can be rationally accepted (even as a serious possibility) after doing so. His position on tawḥīd, therefore, presents no obstacle to and aligns with my account of the Qurʾān's description of the world as providentially unambiguous.

Granted that Al-Ashʿarī holds tawḥīd to be epistemically necessary for human beings, there remains the question of whether he also thinks the acquisition of knowledge about it is morally necessary (obligatory) for us without revelation. Tabur believes he does not. While I grant that this is a plausible interpretation of Al-Ashʿarī's position, it is misleading to refer to it, as Tabur does, simply as ‘the Al-Ashʿarī view’. Several thinkers from the Ashʿarī school affirm that human beings have a fundamental moral obligation to reflect on the signs of God that lead to knowledge about Him. Al-Bāqillānī is one example (see, e.g. Abrahamov Reference Abrahamov1998, 60–62; Mihirig Reference Mihirig2022, 435). As Richard Frank shows, although there is general agreement among the Ashʿarītes that knowing God is obligatory, there is no consensus among them regarding the character of this knowledge or its prior conditions and requirements (Frank Reference Frank1989, 47, 45, 45 n. 21).

As for Al-Māturīdī, Tabur acknowledges that he maintains human beings are both able to derive and responsible for deriving knowledge of God from the evidence of creation (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5). She thinks this is incongruent with my argument, as Al-Māturīdī's position ‘does not correspond to Aijaz's conception of the necessity of belief in tawhīd mainly because it does not consider the formation of the belief in God's existence to be non-inferential’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5). As previously noted, however, my discussion is not cemented to this particular interpretation of Islamic religious epistemology.

The main reason for Tabur's insistence that knowledge of tawḥīd is inferential according to mainstream Islam is to show that there is conceptual space within Islamic theology to allow inculpable non-compliance with its truth; a person may be unable to reason about God or have no moral obligation to do so (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5). The only evidence she provides to support this view is an appeal to the Ashʿarīte school of theology. As I have pointed out, however, not all Ashʿarīte thinkers hold the same view regarding one's obligation to reflect on creation. Al-Māturīdī does not assist Tabur either since his position is consistent with my portrayal of the Qurʾānic worldview. In fact, as Abdurrahman Ali Mihirig observes, the obligation to reason about God appears to be the norm among all the major schools of Islamic theology (kalām):

Since believing without proof was nearly universally condemned by the theological schools of Islam, it was a moral obligation on every capable person to reflect rationally and provide a proof for the existence of God . . . According to all of the major schools of Islamic theology (Ashʿarī, Māturīdī, Muʿtazilī, etc.), human beings are obligated to inquire into the doctrines of revelation and to believe them with proof. One of those beliefs, of course, is the belief that God exists. This means that everyone who meets the criteria for moral obligation (any sane adult capable of reasoning) must reflect on all of their beliefs and come to have knowledge of them, that is, to know why they are true. (Mihirig Reference Mihirig2022, 431, 433; emphasis mine)

Mihirig's observation here is true more broadly speaking in classical Sunni thought. In Abū Jaʿfar Aḥmad Al-Ṭaḥāwī's acclaimed and widely accepted Sunni creed, for instance, one finds the following:

[T]he majority of Muslims argued that knowing Allah is obligatory. They differed, however, over the means to acquiring this knowledge . . . The vast majority of theologians opined that the only way to know Allah Most High is by means of contemplation and deduction, as knowledge of His Most High's existence is not self-evident and therefore requires evidence . . . It is . . . necessary to adduce rational proofs . . . The way to prove His Most High's existence is either by [deducing from] the possibility of the existence of the universe, or its origination, or both; each of which relates to substances or accidents. (Al-Ṭaḥāwī Reference Al-Ṭaḥāwī2020, 10; emphasis mine)

To refute my argument in BPE, Tabur must show a basis in traditional Islamic theism for a person being reasonable in not acquiring knowledge of tawḥīd or having no moral obligation to do so. This would also provide her with a basis to reject my claim that traditional Islamic theism adopts salvific exclusivism: only Muslims (who practically adhere to the knowledge of tawḥīd) will end up in heaven, while non-Muslims (who do not practically adhere to the knowledge of tawḥīd) will be eternally consigned to hell (BPE, 241–242). As I point out in my brief discussion of salvation in Islam, the Qurʾān contains some passages that suggest an inclusivist attitude on this topic, but the dominant Islamic view is that these verses have been abrogated by Qurʾān 3:85 (BPE, 242). This verse states:

And whoever desires other than Islam as religion – never will it be accepted from him, and he, in the Hereafter, will be among the losers. (Qurʾān 3:85)

So far, as I have shown, nothing in Tabur's objections indicates that traditional Islamic theism allows a person to fail in acquiring knowledge of tawḥīd reasonably or inculpably. There is, I grant, some recognition in mainstream Islam that a person may be excused for failing to acquire this knowledge due to insanity or being a child, despite neither of these conditions being mentioned in the Qurʾān.Footnote 7 This does not, however, have any significant impact on my argument. All its key points remain unaffected if we adjust the category of people to whom it is relevant by focusing only on mentally competent adults.

In what I will classify as her fifth objection to my argument in BPE, Tabur presents a discussion centred on Jews and Christians (whom the Qurʾān refers to as Ahl al-kitāb or ‘People of the Book’) as a potential counterexample to my framing of the Qurʾānic picture. Her main points in this discussion are the following: (1) the Qurʾān separates the People of the Book into two categories: those who have faith and those who are kuffār; (2) only the kuffār among the People of the Book will be eternally punished in hell; (3) verse 3:85 in the Qurʾān must be understood contextually as addressing only the kuffār among a specific faction of the People of the Book in the historical past and not all of humanity; (4) the reference to ‘Islam’ in Qurʾān 3:85 is not a reference to the historical religion brought by the Prophet Muhammad but instead to a broader, transhistorical term that refers to the religion of all the prophets; and, (5) Al-Ghazālī defends a model of salvific inclusivism in which some people who do not accept the Qurʾānic message can be saved from eternal punishment in hell (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 7–9).

Central to points (1) and (2) is Tabur's claim that the Qurʾān depicts some individuals among the People of the Book as people of faith. As I concede in my discussion, there are a few Qurʾānic verses, such as 5:69, which suggest salvation is open to people from other religions because of their faith in God. Tabur cites 5:69 as well:

Indeed, those who have believed [in Prophet Muhammad] and those [before Him] who were Jews or Sabeans or Christians – those [among them] who believed in Allah and the Last Day and did righteousness – no fear will there be concerning them, nor will they grieve. (Qurʾān 5:69)

The consensus among classical Qurʾānic exegetes is that this verse refers to faith understood as the appropriate response to the unadulterated monotheism at the heart of humanity's primordial religion – Islam. Saiyad Fareed Ahmad and Saiyad Salahuddin Ahmad elaborate on this understanding of ‘Islam’ as follows:

[T]o follow religion is to . . . submit to and know our Creator, the One and Only God . . . [F]or God there has only been and will only be one eternal, primordial, and revealed religion – that of Islam, or peaceful submission to the Will of God. Whether it is Adam, Noah, Solomon, Abraham, Ishmael, Isaac, Moses, David, Joseph, Jesus or Muhammad, they are all part of one great family – that of Muslims, or those who practice Islam. (Ahmad and Ahmad Reference Ahmad and Ahmad2004, 130–131)

Taken this way, ‘Islam’ is not identical to the historical and reified Islam preached by the Prophet Muhammad. Rather, as the Ahmads explain, it is God's only true religion, which predates, but also includes, Muhammad's advocacy of it in seventh-century Arabia. Those who follow this primordial religion, which consists of peaceful submission to the Will of God, are called ‘Muslims’, as are followers of Muhammad's religion. Several Qurʾānic verses attest to this as a legitimate interpretation of ‘Islam’. Here are just two:

He has ordained for you of religion what He enjoined upon Noah and that which We have revealed to you, [O Muhammad], and what We enjoined upon Abraham and Moses and Jesus – to establish the religion and not be divided therein. (Qurʾān 42:13)

Abraham was neither a Jew nor a Christian, but he was one inclining towards truth, a Muslim [submitting to Allah]. And he was not of the polytheists. (Qurʾān 3:67)

To keep things clear, I will use ‘IslamP’ to refer to Islam understood as humanity's primordial religion, and ‘IslamH’ to refer to the reified, historical version of IslamP preached by the Prophet Muhammad. If Qurʾān 5:69 is seen within the framework of IslamP, then it does not provide evidence that Jews and Christians conventionally understood have faith in God. The Jews and Christians mentioned in this verse are among the faithful followers of humanity's primordial religion. They are really ‘Muslims’, not in the sense that they follow IslamH, but because they respond appropriately to the knowledge of tawḥīd that is foundational to IslamP. Tabur may think otherwise, holding that the positive reference is to conventional Judaism and Christianity. In that case, she then has to explain why the Qurʾān explicitly condemns Jewish and Christian practices (e.g. saying that God has a son, taking scholars and monks as lords besides God, etc.) and states that they constitute disbelief (see my earlier discussion of Tabur's attempt to argue that Jews and Christians practically conform to tawḥīd). Muslim literature penned by advocates of traditional Islamic theism is replete with explanations of how Christians and Jews are culpable for their non-compliance with tawḥīd. Christians are frequently criticized for their profession of the doctrine of the Trinity, whereas Jews are rebuked for contaminating the commitment to tawḥīd by deifying their religious leaders. Such points are often nested in the more general Muslim polemic against the People of the Book, alleging that they follow corrupted forms of God's primordial religion (see, e.g. Ahmad and Ahmad Reference Ahmad and Ahmad2004, 141–149). Given all of this, Tabur has not shown that the Qurʾān approves of the faith of conventional Jews and Christians.

Another difficulty facing those who think that the Qurʾān positively endorses non-Islamic faiths, such as Judaism or Christianity, is the problem of accounting for verse 3:85:

And whoever desires other than Islam as religion – never will it be accepted from him, and he, in the Hereafter, will be among the losers. (Qurʾān 3:85)

In BPE, I explain that according to a long-established tradition in Islamic thought, this Qurʾānic verse is believed to have abrogated other verses suggesting salvific inclusivism (BPE, 242). Tabur appears unaware of this well-known point among Muslim thinkers when she claims my reference to this tradition is ‘so-called’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 7). In her discussion of Qurʾān 3:85, Asma Asfaruddin points out that exegetes who favour exclusivism interpret the reference to ‘Islam’ in the verse narrowly (in accordance with what I have called IslamH). On the other hand, those who favour inclusivism interpret it more broadly as referring to submission to God, characteristic of all faithful monotheists (in accordance with what I have called IslamP) (Asfaruddin Reference Asfaruddin2015, 193). Asfaruddin explains that the exclusivists' interpretation was favoured by most pre-modern exegetes (Asfaruddin Reference Asfaruddin2015, 193). Unfortunately for Tabur, whichever of these two interpretations we go with, there is no avoiding the conclusion that the Qurʾān regards Jews and Christians, conventionally understood, as culpable for not complying with tawḥīd, the indispensable core of IslamH and IslamP. Because they engage in religious practices that compromise commitment to tawḥīd, such individuals cannot be Muslims even concerning IslamP. As Ismaʻīl Rājī al-Fārūqī explains,

There can be no doubt that the . . . essence of Islam is al tawḥīd, the act of affirming Allah (SWT) to be the One, the absolute, transcendent Creator, the Lord and Master of all that is . . . [T]o violate al tawḥīd is to doubt that Allah (SWT) is the One and only God. But to do so means to assume that other beings may share in His divinity . . . Without al tawḥīd . . . there can be no Islam. (Al-Fārūqī Reference Al-Fārūqī1992, 17–19)Footnote 8

Thus, even some of the seemingly ‘inclusivist’ passages in the Qurʾān based on IslamP do not lend themselves to endorsing the practices of Jews and Christians as far as tawḥīd is concerned. Nor do they suggest that these practices may lead to salvation for them. The centrality of tawḥīd to IslamP also negates points (3), (4), and (5) in Tabur's fifth objection. Suppose in making point (3) she is correct that Qurʾān 3:85 specifically addresses the kuffār among a specific historical faction of the People of the Book. This does not mean that the requirement to comply with tawḥīd only applies to this faction, obviously, and especially so if tawḥīd is part of IslamP. As for point (4), Tabur questions the salvific exclusivism implied by Qurʾān 3:85 by endorsing Ibn Taymiyyah's and Ibn Abī al-ʻIzz's interpretations of it, both of which take ‘Islam’ in a broad sense to refer to IslamP. But since tawḥīd is an essential component of IslamP, this broader interpretation does not have the ecumenical import Tabur thinks it does, one that would allow for the salvation of faiths that do not adhere to tawḥīd.

Point (5) in Tabur's discussion of the People of the Book is that some among them may inculpably fail to accept the Qurʾānic message, as Al-Ghazālī allows for in his discussion of salvific inclusivism. Here, I will concentrate only on the underlying problem in Tabur's use of Al-Ghazālī and shall leave aside its other difficulties, such as the complication of how to interpret him on this topic and how compatible his views on it are with the Ashʿarīte and Sunni orthodoxy that he is typically seen to represent. The issue at hand is whether at least some Jews and Christians may, from the perspective of traditional Islamic theism, reasonably and inculpably fail to comply with tawḥīd. The aspects of Al-Ghazālī's discussion of salvific inclusivism Tabur cites are not primarily related to this issue but rather to concerns about the fate of those who do not accept the Prophet Muhammad and his Qurʾānic message (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 9). In other words, Tabur looks at what Al-Ghazālī says about the fate of those who do not accept IslamH. As we have seen, though, the Qurʾān upholds the requirement to comply with tawḥīd even before the advent of the Prophet Muhammad since it is an integral part of IslamP. That being so, failing to hear about the Prophet Muhammad and the Qurʾān does not mean that a person can reasonably and inculpably be ignorant about God and, as a result, fail to respond appropriately to tawḥīd. As mentioned previously, the obligation to reason about God is widely endorsed among the major schools of Islamic theology. In mainstream Sunni thought, as exemplified by Al-Ashʿarī and Al-Māturīdī, knowledge of God's existence and nature is believed to be acquired by rational reflection on the world. Through reason, we know not just that God exists but also that God is unlike His creatures, one, incorporeal, etc. (see, e.g. Al-Ashʿarī Reference Al-Ashʿarī1953, 6–19; Al-Māturīdī Reference Al-Māturīdī2019, 30–36, 74–84). The relationship between Al-Ghazālī's views and the broader Ashʿarīte tradition to which he belongs is complex. Nevertheless, in his discussion of salvific inclusivism that Tabur incorporates into her own, Al-Ghazālī acknowledges that one may, on Qurʾānic grounds, plausibly deem as an unbeliever a person who does not acknowledge the existence or oneness of God (Al-Ghazālī Reference Al-Ghazālī2002, 130).

Because of the problems I've identified with points (1)–(5), Tabur's fifth objection to my argument also fails. The Qurʾānic discourse concerning Jews and Christians does not provide scriptural evidence for holding that they can reasonably and inculpably fail to acquire knowledge of tawḥīd, that they have no moral obligation to do so, or that their practices may lead to salvation. With this, my defence of the core argument I present in BPE comes to an end.

Contra Tabur on the problem of hell in traditional Islamic theism

In BPE, my discussion of salvific exclusivism in Islam does not involve an evaluation of the Problem of Hell. There, I simply note that God's existence seems incompatible with the eternal suffering of some people in hell (BPE, 246). Even so, I grant in that discussion, purely for the sake of argument, that the eternal suffering in hell of people who culpably refuse to act appropriately on knowledge of tawḥīd is compatible with God's existence. For, even if true, one cannot use this view as a premise to argue that non-Muslims who do not believe that tawḥīd is true, whether they are Buddhists, Christians, Hindus, atheists, etc., are destined for hell (BPE, 246–247). My argument in BPE focuses primarily on the plausibility of traditional Islamic theism's views about the doxastic and epistemic aspects of Islamic monotheism, not so much on the general reasonableness of its soteriological and eschatological views, which include the doctrine of hell.

Bertrand Russell, in his essay Why I am not a Christian, takes issue with some of Christ's teachings, citing, as ‘one very serious defect’, Christ's belief in hell. He confesses he ‘[does] not . . . feel that any person who is really profoundly humane can believe in everlasting punishment’ (Russell Reference Russell2004, 13). Russell's remarks about the inhumanity of eternal punishment, although they are directed at Christian theology, seem to apply, a fortiori, to Islamic theology, given how much more frequently hell is mentioned, discussed, and emphasized in the Qurʾān and aḥādīth. It is unsurprising then that, in addition to responding to my core argument in BPE, Tabur extends her apologetic to attempt the challenging task of solving the Problem of Hell. In the remainder of this article, I will argue that she fails to do so and that the weaknesses exposed by her unsuccessful solution highlight further significant problems for traditional Islamic theism. Before turning to its gist, I will identify three preliminary problems with Tabur's defence.

First, leaning on Al-Ghazālī's discussion of salvific inclusivism and without citing any primary references from the Islamic sacred texts, she maintains that eternal punishment in hell is ‘limited to a small group of people’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 10). Putting aside the controversial matter of whether Al-Ghazālī's views justify the conclusion that only a small minority will be punished forever in hell, it is difficult to reconcile Tabur's claim with the Qurʾān and aḥādīth.Footnote 9 For example, the Qurʾān states that, although some will be saved from hell through His mercy, God will ‘surely fill Hell with jinn and men all together’ (Qurʾān 11:119). Even then, hell can accommodate more (Qurʾān 50:30). In the aḥādīth, we read that ninety-nine out of every group of a hundred people, the offspring of Adam, will enter hell (Sahih al-Bukhari Reference Sahihn.d.2). Hell is so deep that it takes seventy years for a stone thrown into it to reach the bottom (Riyad as-Salihin Reference Riyadn.d.). On the day of judgment, hell will be brought forth with 70,000 bridles, with 70,000 angels dragging each bridle (Sahih Muslim Reference Sahihn.d.). These references (and one can easily provide more) call into question the claim that only a small number of people will eternally inhabit hell.

Second, Tabur entirely omits from her defence any description of the nature of eternal punishment in hell. On what he calls the ‘Mainstream View’ of hell in Sunni Islam, according to which hell is a place of real existence (not something figurative or imaginary), Safaruk Chowdhury explains that this punishment ‘involves a demonstrable affliction of suffering and agony through subjecting the body to a comprehensive set of tortures’ (Chowdhury Reference Chowdhury2021, 119). Jane Idleman Smith and Yvonne Yazbeck Haddad list many of these tortures in their summary of the Qurʾānic account of punishment in hell:

The Qur'ān offers a number of rather specific indications of the tortures of the Fire: its flames crackle and roar (S 25:14); it has fierce, boiling waters (S 55:44), scorching wind, and black smoke (S 56:42–43); it roars and boils as if it would burst with rage (S 67:7–8). The people of the Fire are sighing and wailing, wretched (S 11:106), their scorched skins are constantly exchanged for new ones so that they can taste the torment anew (S 4:45), they drink festering water and though death appears on all sides they cannot die (S 14:16–17), people are linked together in chains of 70 cubits (S 69:30–32) wearing pitch for clothing and fire on their faces (S 14:50), boiling water will be poured over their heads, melting their insides as well as their skins, and hooks of iron will drag them back should they try to escape (S 22:19–21). To these terrifying details the ḥadīths could add only more elaboration and more specifics. (Smith and Haddad Reference Smith and Haddad2002, 85–86)

For many not religiously affiliated with Islam and unfamiliar with the Qurʾānic description of hell, this summary alone no doubt comes across as shocking and obscene. Among Muslims, there are those for whom the traditional understanding of Islamic hell as a place of corporeal tortures makes for uncomfortable and perhaps even embarrassing discussions with people who question it, appealing to the revulsion it causes given our fundamental moral sensibilities. To succeed in her defence of traditional Islamic theism's view of hell, Tabur needs to show that God's existence is compatible with Him tormenting people eternally in a grotesquely exaggerated cosmic version of a medieval torture chamber. In evaluating the force of the Problem of Hell, as with the standard Problem of Evil of which it is a variant, matters concerning the scope and nature of suffering are relevant considerations.

Third, the internal coherence of Tabur's defence is doubtful through its reliance on free will. Despite making it the core of her solution to the Problem of Hell, Tabur does not explain what she means by ‘free will’. Most attempts to resolve the Problem of Evil and the Problem of Hell hinge on a libertarian conception of free will, according to which people sometimes act freely and responsibly without being causally determined to do so (Palmer Reference Palmer2014, 4). Such a view of free will is generally rejected in Sunni theology, however, as seen in the works of several classical Muslim thinkers. Al-Ghazālī, for instance, in his exposition of Islamic doctrine, explains that God not only creates our actions, but He also wills them such that

He is the cause (minhu) of good and evil, benefit and harm, Islam and infidelity, acknowledgement and denial [of God], success and failure, rectitude and error, obedience and rebellion, association of other gods with Him and belief [in Him alone]. (Al-Ghazālī Reference Al-Ghazālī1965, 109–111)

This view raises serious doubts about whether libertarian free will exists and implies the unpalatable conclusion that God compels people to do things for which He also eternally punishes them in hell. Because of this unattractive implication, it is understandable why Tabur may choose to steer clear of a traditional Sunni interpretation of free will of the sort described by Al-Ghazālī. But her opting for a libertarian alternative, if that is indeed what she interprets free will to mean, is at odds with what many traditional Sunni thinkers maintain.Footnote 10

With these preliminary problems noted, let me explain the gist of Tabur's proposed solution to the Problem of Hell before I evaluate it. She holds that hell will be eternally populated, but only by the kuffār. Using the Qurʾān's description of Satan's proclivities and misdeeds as a paradigmatic example, Tabur articulates her defence by stating that it is the attitude of the kāfir that justifies his or her eternal punishment in hell:

The paradigmatic example of the kâfir is Iblis (Satan), the first rational free agent to reject God's summon as narrated in the Quran . . . Iblis appears in the Quran as an open enemy of God and human beings, being the embodied form of evil. His case is a paradigmatic case of kufr in showing that a rational free agent can reject the truth out of perverse reasons and evil motivation despite his close acquaintance with it and being aware of the consequences of his actions, namely, the eternal punishment in hell . . . [T]his attitude, which is also a general attitude of the kâfir, renders the eternity of hell reasonable at least for some persons, by illustrating that some souls are irrevocable due to their volitional insistence on the unrightfulness. (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 6)

Also relevant, says Tabur, are the kāfir's character and actions. She does not explain what she means by ‘character’ and how it is different from attitude (or intention), so I will interpret it to include a combination of attitude (or intention) and (freely chosen) actions. This seems to be what Tabur has in mind when she writes that ‘[t]he kâfir forms a character by his free actions throughout his lifetime that makes him deserve an eternal punishment after his death’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 11). More specifically, the kāfir is motivated by evil to freely perform actions that result in an irrevocable character, formed by an insistent fight against the truth, which he or she would never voluntarily stop (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 11). The fundamental feature of this irrevocable character that justifies eternal punishment in hell, according to Tabur, is the kāfir's inability to repent genuinely of his or her sin (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 11). Given this irremediable defiance, God cannot fulfil the requirements for retributive justice through finite punishment and must, therefore, punish the kāfir by eternal damnation in hell (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 11–15).

There is much that I find problematic and unpersuasive in Tabur's discussion of her proposed solution. In proceeding to argue that her solution is unsuccessful, I will limit my criticisms of it only to its most apparent failings. I will begin with an appraisal of her depiction of the kāfir, who remains resolute in sinfully defying God. After this, I will assess her views about God's treatment of such a person.

In Tabur's account of the traits of the kāfir, the connection between these traits and the inability to repent genuinely is unclear. Is this inability inherently part of what it means to be a kāfir? If it is not, might not external circumstances arise where the kāfir sincerely repents of his or her sin? Consider, as an example, the conversion to Islam by ʿUmar ibn al-Khaṭṭāb, a figure revered in Sunni Islam as a faithful Muslim, dedicated companion of the Prophet Muhammad, and second ruler of the Rashidun Caliphate. Before his conversion, ʿUmar was one of Islam's fiercest opponents, a violent man, devoted to the gods of pagan Arabia (a mushrik, one who culpably refuses to act on tawḥīd), and who even set out to murder Muhammad. On his journey to do so, and after physically assaulting his brother-in-law and sister, who were early followers of the Prophet, he became remorseful. Shortly afterwards, he read, for the first time, a script containing some Qurʾānic verses. This resulted in a change of heart, leading ʿUmar to seek the Prophet to profess his faith in Islam (Lings Reference Lings2006, 85–86). Reflecting on this Islamic example (among several others available), we can make the more general point that, perhaps given the correct set of external circumstances, a kāfir can be genuinely remorseful.

In response, Tabur may say that even if some among the kuffār genuinely repent for their sins given a particular configuration of external circumstances, others may remain defiant in their sinfulness no matter what. Alternatively, she might claim that the inability to repent genuinely is inherently part of being a kāfir (perhaps also entertaining the ad hoc suggestion that ʿUmar was never truly a kāfir). Both replies converge on the point that external circumstances, however they may line up, cannot affect the kāfir's irrevocable sinful defiance. If this is so, a puzzle begins to emerge. In the present dialectical context, we can rule out on both theological and philosophical grounds the possibility that irrevocable sinful defiance is woven into the very essence of human beings and jinn, the two main beings recognized in Islamic thought as capable of being kuffār. Theologically speaking, as seen in the Qurʾān, not all human beings are kuffār; similarly, not all jinn are kuffār (see, e.g. Qurʾān 72:1–2). Moreover, there is no doctrine of original sin in Islamic theology. In a well-known ḥādīth, the Prophet Muhammad is reported to have said that every child is born in a state of fiṭrah, a human being's natural disposition to worship God alone (Sahih al-Bukhari Reference Sahihn.d.1; see also Qurʾān 30:30). Philosophically speaking, to hold that irrevocable sinful defiance is intrinsically part of the God-given nature of human beings and jinn would contravene Tabur's commitment to libertarian free will, which maintains people sometimes act without being causally determined to do so. Consequently, we are left with the puzzle of accounting for the kāfir's resolute sinful defiance without appealing to human/jinn nature or external circumstances.

Tabur may now argue that there is no puzzle since the kāfir's sinful defiance can be fully accounted for by his or her possession of libertarian free will. As already noted, the heart of her proposed solution to the Problem of Hell, which she gleans from the Qurʾānic narrative about Satan, is that ‘a rational free agent can reject the truth out of perverse reasons and evil motivation despite his close acquaintance with it and being aware of the consequences of his actions, namely, the eternal punishment in hell’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 6; emphasis mine). While this may be a theologically acceptable interpretation of the kāfir in traditional Islamic theism, it is philosophically problematic if utilized to defend the idea of persistent sinful defiance. As Thomas Talbott persuasively argues, a necessary condition of free choice is a minimal degree of rationality to distinguish it from utterly random events or chance occurrences (Talbott Reference Talbott1999, 185). God, as he explains, fundamentally wants for us what we want for ourselves – supreme happiness (Talbott Reference Talbott1999, 185). If this is correct, why then would a person freely disobey and oppose God? To answer this question, Talbott introduces a distinction between a fully informed and less than fully informed decision to reject God. The latter involves impediments like ignorance, misinformation, deception, etc., which are absent from the former (Talbott Reference Talbott1999, 186). The idea that a person can make a fully informed decision to reject God freely, Talbott argues, is incoherent because such rejection exhibits irrationality incompatible with free choice.Footnote 11 To reject God is to go against one's interests (Talbott Reference Talbott1999, 186). Elements in this line of reasoning have antecedents in ancient Greek thought. In the Meno (Plato Reference Plato1967), among other Platonic dialogues, Socrates defends the view that no one knowingly does evil since this means choosing misery for oneself. Those who may give the impression of knowingly desiring and acting on evil are, in fact, motivated by a mistaken conception of the good (77c–78b). As Aristotle (Reference Aristotle1934) observes in the first book of his Nicomachean Ethics, although most people agree that the greatest good for us is happiness, what happiness consists of – whether wealth, pleasure, honour, etc. – is a matter of dispute among people (1095a).

These points collectively suggest that the very idea of a kāfir – understood as a person who freely (rationally) makes a fully informed decision to reject God – is incoherent. The coherent alternative to this – the view that a person may make a less than fully informed decision to reject God – implies hindrances distorting one's perception of what is being rejected. Indeed, even with Satan, who is regarded in Islam as the prototypical kāfir, a reasonable case can be made that such hindrances exist. Consider the Qurʾānic account of Satan's fall, which is described in verses such as the following:

[So mention] when your Lord said to the angels, ‘Indeed, I am going to create a human being from clay. So when I have proportioned him and breathed into him of My [created] soul, then fall down to him in prostration.’ So the angels prostrated – all of them entirely. Except Iblees (Satan); he was arrogant and became among the disbelievers. [Allah] said, ‘O Iblees, what prevented you from prostrating to that which I created with My hands? Were you arrogant [then], or were you [already] among the haughty?’ He said, ‘I am better than him. You created me from fire and created him from clay.’ (38:71–76)

In his work, Al-Qisţās al-Mustaqīm (The Correct Balance), Al-Ghazālī discusses several ways in which Satan is animated by erroneous thinking. Commenting specifically about Satan's fall described in the Qurʾānic verses above, he writes:

[Satan] justified the prevention of bowing by his being better, and then confirmed the ‘betterness’ by the fact that he was created from fire. And when one explicates all the parts of his argument, one finds that his balance is correct in structure, but false in matter. Its full form is that he says: ‘I am better than he; but the better does not bow; therefore I do not bow.’ (Al-Ghazālī Reference Al-Ghazālī1980, 312)

Although Satan's refusal to prostrate to Adam is predicated on a valid argument (i.e. one where the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion), the argument is ultimately unsound, Al-Ghazālī observes, because both premises are dubious. The second premise, for instance, can be reasonably rejected because obligation and merit are by command, not by ‘betterness’ (Al-Ghazālī Reference Al-Ghazālī1980, 312–313). If Al-Ghazālī's analysis is correct, then, plausibly, Satan's response to God's command was based on delusional thinking and, therefore, constituted a less than fully informed decision to disobey God. With this analysis of the concept of a kāfir in hand, I will now address Tabur's views about God's treatment of those who remain resolute in their sinful defiance of Him.

God, as Tabur explicitly accepts in her formulation of the Problem of Hell, is omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 10). In her proposed solution to the problem, however, there is hardly any discussion of these omni-attributes of God or what they imply. In gauging the success of defences and theodicies purporting to resolve the more general Problem of Evil, these attributes are critically relevant and cannot be ignored. In his classic presentation of the problem, J. L. Mackie explains that, in its simplest form, the Problem of Evil arises out of three constituent propositions: ‘God is omnipotent; God is wholly good; and yet evil exists’ (Mackie Reference Mackie1955, 200). In surveying possible responses to it, Mackie identifies the general form in what he calls ‘fallacious solutions’ to the problem:

[I]n order to solve the problem one (or perhaps more) of its constituent propositions is given up, but in such a way that it appears to have been retained, and can therefore be asserted without qualification in other contexts. Sometimes there is a further complication: the supposed solution moves to and fro between, say, two of the constituent propositions, at one point asserting the first of these but covertly abandoning the second, at another point asserting the second but covertly abandoning the first. (Mackie Reference Mackie1955, 202–203)

It is precisely this sort of problem – the failure to consistently uphold God's omnipotence, omniscience, and omnibenevolence (perfect goodness) in accounting for the eternal suffering of some people in hell – that renders Tabur's proposed solution to the Problem of Hell fallacious, as I will now show.

Let's take omnipotence first. If God is all-powerful, couldn't He actualize a possible world in which no one eternally suffers in hell? For an omnipotent God, there are, surely, several possible worlds that can be actualized in which this can occur. These worlds may include those in which hell, or a more humane version of it, exists. In such worlds, some people are punished in hell for various sins, but no one resides there for eternity. Since rejection of God is always less than fully informed, in these possible worlds, God could, using His omnipotence, rectify people's misunderstandings about Him, whether in this life or the afterlife. One might object that for God to take such corrective action would violate people's libertarian free will. It is generally agreed among philosophers of religion that God's omnipotence is not diminished by His power being ‘limited’ to bringing about states of affairs that are logically possible. Philosophers of religion also generally agree that, on a libertarian conception of free will, God cannot directly make someone do something freely, as that is logically impossible. While I accept these two points, I do not think they threaten, in the least, my point about God taking steps to correct misunderstandings about Him. With His omnipotence, God can, without exercising direct causal control over an agent (i.e. without puppeteering him or her), providentially arrange external conditions so that an individual will freely accept Him over some finite period, during which all hindrances to the knowledge of God are removed. But suppose this is wrong, and there are some possible worlds in which even God's omnipotence cannot guarantee that all individuals will eventually freely accept Him. What seems uncontroversial is that it is within the purview of God's omnipotence to refrain from actualizing such possible worlds. Should an omnipotent God wish to create a world, He has an abundant variety of possible worlds for His choosing to actualize. Among these possible worlds are those where there are no creatures of the sort that can exercise creaturely freedom to sustain irrevocable disbelief. In such worlds, perhaps no persons exist, or perhaps, instead of humans and jinn, there are other sorts of creatures who do not fall into irrevocable disbelief. The Qurʾān intimates that God can easily create such worlds: ‘If He wills, He can do away with you and bring forth a new creation. And that is for Allah not difficult’ (Qurʾān 35:16–17).

Next, let's consider omniscience. Tabur forgoes any consideration of God's omniscience in her proposed solution to the Problem of Hell despite including it in her formulation of the problem. I will offer a few critical remarks on God being all-knowing. If God is omniscient, He knows how to providentially engineer His creation using His omnipotence so that all creatures possessing libertarian free will accept Him. The understanding of God's omniscience in traditional Islamic theism includes foreknowledge. In Sunni orthodoxy, belief in al-qaḍāʾ wa l-qadar (‘divine will and decree’) is one of the six articles of faith (arkān al-ʾīmān). This is understood to imply that, from eternity, God foreordained and knew everything that would happen, including human choices (Murad Reference Murad2006, 81–83). Although this doctrine does not seem compatible with libertarian free will, let me shelve this concern for now and continue to operate on Tabur's assumption that we have free will in this sense. Regardless of whether individuals have this sort of freedom, it is notable that the doctrine of divine will and decree implies God knew from eternity how they would behave. Thus, even if some creatures possessing libertarian free will never accept God, thwarting His omnipotent efforts to ensure they do, God knew this would happen before they were created.

Finally, we come to omnibenevolence. Let's assume Tabur is correct and that the notion of a free and fully informed rejection of God, accompanied by persistent sinful defiance, is coherent and instantiated in God's creation. Why would, indeed how could, an omnibenevolent God consign individuals who maintain this attitude to a place where they must endure – for eternity – horrific forms of torment, such as having their skins roasted, boiling water poured over their heads, etc.? One might justifiably ask whether this amounts to ‘overkill’, but that would not be quite the right way to phrase the question since the inhabitants of hell cannot die (Qurʾān 14:17). Tabur thinks God's retributive justice provides the answer here, but justice is only one facet of divine omnibenevolence. God, as the Qurʾān states, is Just (4:40), but He is also Ar-Raḥmān (the Beneficent) and Ar-Raḥīm (the Most Merciful), as repeated in virtually every Sūrah (Chapter) of the Islamic Scripture. The Qurʾān contains numerous descriptions of several other divine attributes that are relevant to a consideration of God's omnibenevolence, also referring to Him, for example, as Al-Ghafūr (the All-Forgiving) (e.g. Qurʾān 41:32). Ignoring such divine attributes results in a myopic analysis of God's omnibenevolence. As a connected point, it is unreasonable to believe that God's omnibenevolence is exhausted or even based on lex talionis, especially when, according to the Qurʾān, God Himself urges us non-omnibenevolent, ordinary, and weak mortals to aspire to higher moral standards: ‘Repel [evil] by that [deed] which is better; and thereupon the one whom between you and him is enmity [will become] as though he was a devoted friend’ (Qurʾān 41:34).

Even if we confine ourselves to God's justice and further assume that it is best construed as retributive, as opposed to redemptive and restorative, Tabur's answer is unconvincing. One of the core principles of retributive justice is that the punishment given to an individual must be proportionate to the wrongdoing done by him or her. Such proportionality seems wildly distorted in God's eternally and horrifically torturing individuals who are irrevocable in their disbelief and never genuinely repent. God, after all, cannot be harmed by this attitude. Is He then so affronted by the stubbornness of such small and frail creatures that He thinks the fitting response is to subject them to vicious molestation in hell forever? Couldn't God resort to other, less horrific forms of punishment? Indeed, one can make a reasonable case that there would not be much for God to do when dealing with those who reject Him in this manner. Suppose, per impossible, there exist individuals who, although fully informed about God, freely reject Him irrevocably; Video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor (‘I see the better way and approve it, but I follow the worse way’) each of them says, like Ovid's Medea (Metamorphoses 7.20; Ovid Reference Ovid1922). For God to sustain this state for them throughout eternity without inflicting additional corporeal torment seems like sufficient punishment. God may, out of His compassion and respect for their autonomy, refrain from overriding their freedom and decide to let them be – perhaps quarantining them in some place away from heaven and the blessedness of those who inhabit it.Footnote 12 In this scenario, about which Socrates would be wrong, some choose to be ‘miserable and ill-starred’ (cf. Meno, 78a). They decide, that is, to remain miserable in perpetuity, knowing that their misery stems from clinging to counterfeit forms of happiness while rejecting genuine happiness that is found only in conforming to God's will. This would be self-inflicted mental torment, akin to Ibn Sīnā's heterodox Islamic understanding of punishment in the afterlife as psychological, not somatic (Heath Reference Heath1992, 68–69).

Let's proceed further, conceding to Tabur that God is justified in tormenting (psychologically and/or somatically) for all eternity those individuals who persist in their disbelief. A world in which this happens is still not a good world, all things considered. Here are just a few of its unsavoury features. It is a world forever plagued by the terrible suffering of some of God's creatures. It is also a place where God's ultimate purpose in creating human beings and jinn, to worship Him (Qurʾān 51:56), is never fully realized. And, perhaps most disturbingly, the existence of such a world means that, ultimately, Satan had some measure of victory against God when he said that he would lead everyone astray except God's chosen servants (Qurʾān 15:39–40; 36:62 says that Satan led a great multitude of people astray). If God is omniscient, He would have known about these features of this world before creating it. Since He is omnipotent, God had the power to refrain from bringing it into existence. If God is also omnibenevolent, He would not have wanted to create this world, being aware that actualizing it would entail the eternal endurance of several bad states of affairs, including those that go against His will. Even Ibn Taymiyyah, one of the great champions of Sunni orthodoxy, is swayed by aspects of this reasoning, incorporating them into his defence of an interpretation of hell that contradicts Muslim consensus (Ijmāʿ). God's mercy and wisdom, he says, preclude the creation of a world in which God's chastisement does not serve the higher purpose of cleansing sins and purifying souls (Hoover Reference Hoover2009, 189). Compared to Tabur's position, this seems a much more plausible conclusion to infer from an analysis of God's omnibenevolence, omniscience, and omnipotence.

Tabur's proposed solution to the Problem of Hell is a complete failure because it fundamentally neglects to take God's omni-attributes seriously. One could only begin to entertain the plausibility of her proposal if working with impoverished notions of divine power, knowledge, and especially goodness. Heavily discounted notions of these attributes might be suitable for thinking about an anaemic deity, but, as Muslims frequently say, ʾAllāhu ʾakbar (God is the Greatest).

Conclusion

According to traditional Islamic theism, as I explain in BPE and here, our world is a Manichean theatre in which drama unfolds according to how human beings (and jinn) respond to God's primordial religion, Islam, the sum and substance of which is tawḥīd. Knowledge of tawḥīd is evident to all. Muslims respond appropriately to this knowledge through their religious practices, whereas non-Muslims culpably fail to do so. Non-Muslim followers of other religions are not adherents of self-contained belief systems, as many think today, but are deviants who practice corrupted forms of Islam. The corruption in these forms may be gauged by the degree to which they stray from commitment to tawḥīd. As the Ahmads write, ‘[Islam] . . . contends that all other religions, in their current forms, have deviated from or are entirely removed from Divine Revelation as a source and have severely compromised the Unity of God’ (Ahmad and Ahmad Reference Ahmad and Ahmad2004, 135; emphasis mine). Those who are eternally punished in hell have compromised God's Unity. As Smith and Haddad note in their discussion of Islamic views regarding human responsibility to God, there is a consensus among classical Muslim thinkers that ‘the one unpardonable sin, that for which the pain of the Fire is assured, is refusal to testify to the tawḥīd of God’ (Smith and Haddad Reference Smith and Haddad2002, 22). All the inhabitants of hell who abide there forever, non-Muslims, have in some way compromised their commitment to tawḥīd.

Is this understanding of our global religious landscape plausible when viewed independently from commitment to religious dogma? In BPE, I argue that it is not, making my case principally using the incompatibility between this view of the world and what are eminently plausible facts of religious diversity. Not everyone believes that tawḥīd is true. Among those who do not believe it to be true, there are many reasonable people for whom its truth is not evident. Moreover, it is unreasonable to think that the average non-Muslim culpably refuses to act in accordance with knowledge of tawḥīd and is bound for hell (to appreciate the force of this point, I invite Muslims to consider it not in the universal abstract but in light of particular non-Muslim individuals they are intimately acquainted with – perhaps an agnostic parent, a Buddhist sibling, a Christian spouse, a dear Hindu friend, etc.).

I have argued that Tabur's apologetic on behalf of traditional Islamic theism fails to refute my core argument in BPE. Her extension of this apologetic to solve the Problem of Hell within an Islamic context also fails. I will end this article with what I hope are two constructive comments directed at Muslims who may feel disquieted by my discussion. First, my criticisms of traditional Islamic theism's understanding of the world's religious diversity do not rest on any claims about how Muslims in general (particularly those who are not philosophers or theologians) perceive non-Islamic religions and their non-Muslim followers. Thus, the fact that there are, for instance, many Muslims who have close Hindu friends and do not see them as perversely rejecting God and bound for hell is perfectly consistent with my criticisms. Second, as I have previously explained, my criticisms of traditional Islamic theism are directed at a particular interpretation of Islam. They are by no means intended to be a ‘refutation of Islam’ or anything of the sort. Surveying and evaluating the plausibility of alternative Islamic interpretations of the world's religious diversity is, however, a task I will leave for some other time.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Zain Ali, Robert McKim, Swami Medhananda, Oliver Leaman, Mohammad Saleh Zarepour, and the anonymous referee for their helpful comments and feedback on previous drafts of this article. The views expressed here are my own, as are any shortcomings.

Footnotes

1. See Helm (Reference Helm2000, 11) for a relevant discussion of how ‘believing in’ God is distinct from ‘believing that’ God exists.

2. As the Islamic philosopher Shabbir Akhtar explains, the main feature of kufr is negligence in practice: ‘Kufr is not metaphysical disbelief in the reality of a divine power; it is practical neglect of divine imperatives informing daily life and its priorities’ (Akhtar Reference Akhtar2008, 248). A full discussion of the nature and scope of this practical neglect as maintained by the kāfir is beyond the scope of this article.

3. This quotation and subsequent quotations from the Qurʾān are from the Sahih International English translation.

4. See the full discussion in Izutsu (Reference Izutsu2002, 187–188) for additional Qur’ānic evidence in support of the mu'min-kāfir dichotomy.

5. In commenting on the view that belief in the truth of tawḥīd can be caused non-inferentially, Tabur says it is ‘not even among the main Islamic views in the Islamic tradition’ (Tabur Reference Tabur2023, 5). She is simply wrong about this. See, for example, Jamie Turner (Reference Turner2019) and (Reference Turner2022) for a discussion of how Ibn Taymiyyah develops the idea of fiṭrah (our innate nature or disposition), an important tenet of Islamic theology, as yielding non-inferential knowledge of God. As Turner shows, this idea is fully compatible with Alvin Plantinga's Reformed epistemology, which has become prominent in contemporary discussions of religious epistemology. The essence of Plantinga's Reformed epistemology is perhaps best characterized as the view that one can have knowledge of God's existence (and other religious truths) without relying on arguments.

6. For Al-Ashʿarī's full discussion of the arguments for God's existence and nature, many of which are motivated by explicit references to the Qur’ān, see Al-Ashʿarī (Reference Al-Ashʿarī1953, 6–19).

7. Often, Islamic scholars who mention these conditions in discussions of religious epistemology cite this ḥādīth: ‘It was narrated from ‘Aishah that the Prophet said: “The pen has been lifted from three: From the sleeper until he wakes up, from the minor until he grows up, and from the insane until he comes back to his senses or recovers”’ (Sunan an-Nasa'i Reference Sunann.d.). Although this ḥādīth suggests that children are not accountable, there are other reports in the collection of aḥādīth suggesting otherwise. In particular, the fate of non-Muslim children who die young is controversial in Sunni Islam (see, e.g. Al-Munajjid Reference Al-Munajjid2009).

8. See Al-Fārūqī (Reference Al-Fārūqī1992, 21–23) for a discussion of how, according to him, Judaism and Christianity violate tawḥīd.

9. In his great theological work Iḥyāʾ ʿulūm al-dīn (Revival of the Religious Sciences), Al-Ghazālī warns even believers to be fearful of hell: ‘Your coming unto it [hell] is certain, while your salvation therefrom is no more than conjecture.’ He advises them to ‘fill up [their hearts], therefore, with the dread of that destination’ (as quoted in Lange Reference Lange and Lange2016, 9).

10. See, for example, the account of destiny and God's Will in Ahmad ibn Naqib al-Misri's ʿUmdat as-Salik (Reliance of the Traveller), a classic and authoritative handbook of Sunni jurisprudence (Al-Misri Reference Al-Misri1997, 813–814, 819–820). In this account, notwithstanding the mention of people ‘choosing’ their actions, the heavy emphasis on Divine Sovereignty seems to preclude any notion of libertarian free will.

11. In giving his own defence of this point, David Bentley Hart is as forceful as he is eloquent:

What, then, of the claim that hell could be the ultimate free choice of a rational spiritual nature? It is meaningless. To the very degree that a rational creature might reject the one transcendent reality that can alone satisfy its deepest needs and desires, that creature is in bondage. An injured, damaged, and deluded person might behave in such a manner, but never a free person. Freely, sanely, deliberatively to elect misery forever rather than bliss would be a form of madness. To call that madness freedom, in order to soothe our consciences and to continue to reconcile ourselves to a picture of reality that is morally absurd, is to talk gibberish. (Hart Reference Hart2022)

12. For the record, I think this is also an inadequate solution to the Problem of Hell. Still, I find it better than solutions that attempt to defend the traditional Islamic understanding of hell with all its somatic tortures for the damned.

References

Abrahamov, B (1998) Islamic Theology: Traditionalism and Rationalism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Ahmad, SF and Ahmad, SS (2004) God, Islam, and the Skeptic Mind. Kuala Lumpur: Blue Nile Publishing.Google Scholar
Aijaz, I (2008) Belief, providence and eschatology: some philosophical problems in Islamic theism. Philosophy Compass 3, 231253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Akhtar, S (2008) The Quran and the Secular Mind. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Al-Ashʿarī, A (1953) Kitāb al-Lumaʾ, McCarthy RJ (trans.), in The Theology of Al-Ashʿarī. Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, pp. 5116.Google Scholar
Al-Fārūqī, IR (1992) Al Tawḥīd: Its Implications for Thought and Life. Herndon, VA: The International Institute of Islamic Thought.Google Scholar
Al-Ghazālī, AḤ (1965) Al-Risāla al-Qudsiyya (The Jerusalem Epistle), A. L. Tibawi (trans. and ed.), ‘Al-Ghazali's tract on dogmatic theology’. The Islamic Quarterly 9, 62122.Google Scholar
Al-Ghazālī, AḤ (1980) Al-Qisţās al-Mustaqīm (The Correct Balance), McCarthy RJ (trans.), in Freedom and Fulfillment. Boston, MA: Twayne Publishers, pp. 287332.Google Scholar
Al-Ghazālī, AḤ (2002) Faysal al-Tafriqa Bayna al-Islām wa al-Zandaqa, Jackson SA (trans.), in On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 85141.Google Scholar
Al-Māturīdī, AM (2019) Kitāb al-Tawḥīd. Māturīdī Publications.Google Scholar
Al-Misri, AIN (1997) ‘Umdat as-Salik wa ‘Uddat an-Nasik, Keller NHM (trans.), in Reliance of the Traveller. Beltsville, MD: Amana Publications, pp. 47825.Google Scholar
Al-Munajjid, M (2009) The fate of the children of believers and the children of mushrikeen who die young. Islam Question & Answer. Available at https://islamqa.info/en/answers/118103/the-fate-of-the-children-of-believers-and-the-children-of-mushrikeen-who-die-young.Google Scholar
Al-Shahrastānī, M (2014) Kitāb al–Milal wa al-Nihal, Kazi AK and Flynn JG (trans.), in Muslim Sects and Divisions. New York, NY: Routledge, pp. 8176.Google Scholar
Al-Ṭaḥāwī, AJA (2020) Imam Al-Ṭaḥāwī's Creed of Islam: An Exposition. Mahmood A (trans.). Heritage Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1934) Aristotle in 23 Volumes, vol. 19. Rachkam H (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press http://data.perseus.org/citations/urn:cts:greekLit:tlg0086.tlg010.perseus-eng1:1094a.Google Scholar
Asfaruddin, A (2015) Contemporary Issues in Islam. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Chowdhury, S (2021) Islamic Theology and the Problem of Evil. Cairo: The American University in Cairo Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frank, R (1989) Knowledge and Taqlîd: the foundations of religious belief in classical Ashʿarism. Journal of the American Oriental Society 109, 3762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, DB (2022) The obscenity of belief in an eternal hell. Australian Broadcasting Corporation. Available at https://www.abc.net.au/religion/david-bentley-hart-obscenity-of-belief-in-eternal-hell/13356388.Google Scholar
Heath, P (1992) Allegory and Philosophy in Avicenna (Ibn Sina). Philadelphia, PA: University of Philadelphia Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helm, P (2000) Faith with Reason. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hoover, J (2009) Islamic universalism: Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya's Salafi deliberations on the duration of hell-fire. Muslim World 99, 181201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Izutsu, T (1965) The Concept of Belief in Islamic theology. Tokyo: The Institute of Cultural and Linguistic Studies; Yurindo Publ.Google Scholar
Izutsu, T (2002) Ethico-Religious Concepts in the Qurʾān. Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kment, B (2021) Varieties of modality. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/modality-varieties.Google Scholar
Lange, C (2016) Introducing hell in Islamic studies. In Lange, C (ed.), Locating Hell in Islamic Traditions. Leiden: Brill, pp. 128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lings, M (2006) Muhammad: His Life Based on the Earliest Sources, 5th edn. Rochester, VT: Inner Traditions.Google Scholar
Mackie, JL (1955) Evil and omnipotence. Mind, New Series 64, 200212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mihirig, AA (2022) The existence of arguments in classical Islamic thought: reply to Hannah Erlwein. Sophia 61, 429444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murad, MR (2006) The Meaning of Articles of Faith, 3rd edn. Riyadh: Cooperative Office of Call and Guidance Al-Sulay.Google Scholar
Ovid, (1922) Metamorphoses. More B (trans.). Boston, MA: Cornhill. Available at http://data.perseus.org/citations/urn:cts:latinLit:phi0959.phi006.perseus-eng1:7.1-7.158.Google Scholar
Palmer, D (2014) Libertarian Free Will: Contemporary Debates. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plato, (1967) Plato in Twelve Volumes, vol. 3. Lamb WRM (trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Available at http://data.perseus.org/citations/urn:cts:greekLit:tlg0059.tlg024.perseus-eng1:70a.Google Scholar
Riyad, as-Salihin (n.d.) The Book of Miscellany. Available at https://sunnah.com/riyadussalihin:404.Google Scholar
Russell, B (2004) Why I am not a Christian. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Saeed, A (2006) Islamic Thought. New York, NY: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sahih, al-Bukhari (n.d.1) Funerals (Al-Janaa'iz). Available at https://sunnah.com/bukhari:1358.Google Scholar
Sahih, , al-Bukhari (n.d.2) To Make the Heart Tender (Ar-Riqaq). Available at https://sunnah.com/bukhari:6529.Google Scholar
Sahih, Muslim (n.d.) The Book of Paradise, its Description, its Bounties and its Inhabitants. Available at https://sunnah.com/muslim:2842.Google Scholar
Smith, JI and Haddad, YY (2002) The Islamic Understanding of Death and Resurrection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunan, an-Nasa'i (n.d.) The Book of Divorce. Available at https://sunnah.com/nasai:3432.Google Scholar
Tabur, ÜA (2023) Is God's prescription of eternal hell for kâfirūn (infidels) in the Quran evil? Contesting Aijaz's understanding of kufr (infidelity) and an analysis of eternal punishment in the Quran. Religious Studies, 59, S51S66. doi: 10.1017/S0034412523000240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbott, T (1999) The Inescapable Love of God. Parkland, FL: Universal Publishers.Google Scholar
Turner, J (2019) An Islamic account of reformed epistemology. Philosophy East and West 71, 767792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, J (2022) Ibn Taymiyya on theistic signs and knowledge of God. Religious Studies 58, 583597.CrossRefGoogle Scholar