Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T19:31:22.605Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In Defense of “Physician-Assisted Suicide”: Toward (and Back to) a Transparent, Destigmatizing Debate

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 November 2024

Brandy M. Fox*
Affiliation:
Center for Biomedical Ethics, Stanford University, Stanford, CA, USA
Harold Braswell
Affiliation:
Albert Gnaegi Center for Health Care Ethics, Saint Louis University, St. Louis, MO, USA
*
Corresponding author: Brandy M. Fox; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Many bioethicists have recently shifted from using “physician-assisted suicide” (PAS) to “medical aid-in-dying” (MAID) to refer to the act of voluntarily hastening one’s death with the assistance of a medical provider. This shift was made to obscure the practice’s connection to “suicide.” However, as the charge of “suicide” is fundamental to arguments against the practice, “MAID” can only be used by its proponents. The result has been the fragmentation of the bioethical debate. By highlighting the role of human agency—as opposed to natural processes—in causing death, the term “PAS” makes it easier both to perceive potential risks to vulnerable populations and to affirm suicide as a potentially autonomous choice. As such, “PAS” thus more transparently expresses the arguments of both supporters and opponents of the “right to die,” while avoiding the unnecessary stigmatization of suicide and suicidal people which is a result of the usage of “MAID.”

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Contrary to its title, this article is not a defense of physician-assisted suicide. Nor is it an attack on the practice. In fact, it presents no opinion on the rightness or wrongness of physician-assisted suicide. What it does present is an opinion on the correct terminology with which to refer to the practice of voluntarily hastening the end of one’s life with the assistance of a medical provider. Our opinion is that the term that bioethicists should use to refer to this practice is, yes, “physician-assisted suicide.”

A few years ago this would not have been an argument that one would have to make— indeed, it would have made no sense to do so. In the United States, and elsewhere, supporters of physician-assisted suicide referred to the act as such.Footnote 1, Footnote 2 Indeed, they even advocated for doing so, so as to distance the act—both analytically and in the popular imagination—from “euthanasia,” a term many associated with Nazism.Footnote 3, Footnote 4, Footnote 5 Physician-assisted suicide was the dominant term used in discussions about the practice, including those concerning the Oregon Death with Dignity Act.Footnote 6, Footnote 7 This term was shared in general by both supporters and opponents of the practice—marking a rare truce in an otherwise contentious debate.Footnote 8 Indeed, this truce was the foundation of debate, for it established a consensus with regard to the very thing being debated. That “thing,” everyone understood, was physician-assisted suicide. All parties agreed that “causation and human agency [are] not in dispute,”Footnote 9 allowing room to discuss the ethical implications of the act.

But this situation has changed dramatically. Supporters of physician-assisted suicide (PAS) began replacing the term with a variety of other ones: aid-in-dying (AID), medical aid-in-dying (MAID), and assisted death (AD).Footnote 10, Footnote 11, Footnote 12 These three terms (AID, MAID, AD) are used to cover a variety of practices, depending on the jurisdiction the act takes place in. For example, in Canada, there are two types of MAID: A physician or nurse practitioner can either administer a substance that causes death, or (s)he can provide a drug that the patient then self-administers.Footnote 13 The first action is also known as euthanasia; scholars have argued that this bundling of terms is confusing in itself.Footnote 14 The only form of “aid-in-dying” legally available in the United States is for the medical provider to prescribe a substance to a terminally ill patient, who then ingests the substance with the intention of causing death.Footnote 15 These types of “aid” can also be applied to different populations: in the US, for example, this assistance is only accessible to people who are dying. In Canada it is available to people with long-term disabilities; such people are not “dying” in the sense that the term is generally used, yet they are eligible for “assistance in dying.”Footnote 16

What united these new disparate terms (AID, MAID, AD) was their common exclusion of one word: suicide. This exclusion was in large part politically motivated, as PAS supporters found that removing reference to “suicide” increased support for the practice.Footnote 17, Footnote 18, Footnote 19, Footnote 20 But supporters of the new terminology have also defended it on analytic grounds, arguing that there are valid philosophical reasons for excluding suicide from the definition of the act.Footnote 21, Footnote 22, Footnote 23 The effect has been that both the pro- and anti-PAS factions have further stigmatized the term “suicide” by emphasizing and perpetuating the idea that suicide should never be an option.

In this article, we argue against those reasons for excluding the term suicide. We begin by noting the radicality of the shift from “PAS” to “MAID.” While “PAS” refers to a death that is caused by human action, in “MAID” death is a fact of nature. The result is not simply a newer, more politically expedient term for the same phenomenon. It is a redescription that transforms the very nature of the phenomenon being discussed.

This redescription has been broadly accepted by “right to die” proponents. However, opponents, in contrast, have rejected it, generally still referring to the phenomenon being debated as “PAS.” This rejection is not coincidental. The premise of opponents’ argument is that the “right to die” represents a discriminatory double standard in the treatment of suicidal ideation. It is impossible to make such arguments if the phenomenon being debated is not classified as a form of “suicide.” The very terms of “debate” render the position of PAS opponents fundamentally excluded. The result has been the fragmentation of the “right to die” debate into two camps that do not agree on the basics of what is being discussed.

This fragmentation is, we believe, wholly unnecessary. PAS, we contend, is a term that, precisely because it highlights the role of human agency in causing death, more effectively expresses the best arguments for and against the practice. It highlights the potential risks to vulnerable populations of having their lives ended in a manner both violent and premature. Also, it also emphasizes the possibility that the decision to die can be an autonomous choice. Both these possibilities are, at best, muddled—and at worst obscured—by the usage of “MAID.” The term has thus diverted the course of the “right to die” debate, even as it undermines both of the positions that had previously given the debate structure. The result, in the words of the American College of Physicians, is to “obscure[ing] the ethics of what is at stake.”Footnote 24 This obfuscation should be rejected by both sides of the debate, as well as by the field charged with giving that debate structure: bioethics. For these reasons, we advocate a return to “PAS.” We begin by clarifying the nature of the shift that has taken place.

Two different things

Sam, a man with a terminal medical condition, goes to his doctor. Sam asks the doctor to prescribe a substance. The reason Sam wants this substance is because taking it will bring about the end of his life. The doctor knows this, and that is the reason why she prescribes it. Sam acquires the substance and later ingests it. He dies in a manner that is directly traceable to his having done so.

Sam’s action—his taking of this substance—can be described in two different ways. One is “physician-assisted suicide” (PAS). The other is “medical aid-in-dying” (MAID). The difference between these terms is seemingly semantic; they appear to be two different terms to describe the same thing. However, that is not the case. On the contrary, “PAS” and “MAID” describe two things that are radically different, even fundamentally opposed. Rather than describe Sam’s action, they splinter it into two separate actions that are fundamentally irreconcilable.

In “PAS,” Sam is a person who wants to die: his foreseeable future is unacceptable, and he wishes to end the possibility of that future before it is upon him. He is suicidal. When Sam tells the doctor that he wants to die, he confesses this suicidality. However, the doctor treats this suicidality differently than she would otherwise. Rather than discourage Sam, she prescribes him a substance that Sam can take to end his life. When Sam does so and subsequently die, that substance is the cause of his death, as is—somewhat more distantly—Sam himself. By prescribing Sam this substance, the doctor has “assisted” Sam’s suicide, though she has not directly caused it.

In “MAID,” Sam is not suicidal. He is dying. If he could, he would live. However, he will die. He merely wants to die sooner than would otherwise be the case. The substance the doctor prescribes him will bring about this death more quickly. However, this medication will not cause Sam’s death, nor will Sam himself. Rather, the cause of death is Sam’s disease. The prescribed substance merely “assists” it. Sam does not die of suicide. He dies a natural death.

These two actions bear no relation to each other. “PAS” is a death that is voluntary, medicalized, and caused by human action. “MAID” is an involuntary death, provoked by nature. In their relationship to death, PAS and MAID are opposite. The difference between them is semantic. However, here, semantics is destiny. This destiny does not just refer to the nature of the act itself. It also refers to the debate that can emerge around it. We will now describe how this debate has changed with the shift from “PAS” to “MAID.”

A good debate…

For a significant portion—perhaps most—of the past thirty years, the term used to describe Sam’s action would be “PAS.” This description was broadly agreed upon. However, this agreement on “PAS” did not mean that there was nothing to argue about. On the contrary, the agreement about the term “PAS” made possible a debate about the act of PAS.

PAS supporters thought that PAS was a form of suicide that could be justified. PAS opponents did not. Underlying this disagreement were questions both empirical and principled. For example, empirically, was the suffering attested to by individuals seeking PAS due to incurable medical conditions or to social contingencies that could be remedied via means less radical than the provocation of death?Footnote 25, Footnote 26 With regard to principles: Was self-killing always bad or could, in some instances, it be considered to be an act that was morally neutral or even laudatory?Footnote 27, Footnote 28, Footnote 29, Footnote 30, Footnote 31, Footnote 32

Both these empirical and principled questions were reasonable to disagree about. However, such disagreement would have to be attuned to the contingent nature of the topic in question. This was not just a matter of updating one’s data—however important—while leaving one’s principles untouched. Different data could impact the matters of principle, calling into question, for example, which position on PAS really supported “autonomy” or the “sanctity of life.”Footnote 33, Footnote 34, Footnote 35, Footnote 36, Footnote 37, Footnote 38, Footnote 39

The result was a debate that endured for at least 30 years, and arguably much longer. Not only endured—but improved. Participants in the PAS debate had, over time, to take into account a broader range of views that both opposed and supported their own. Over this time the debate became more interdisciplinary and interprofessional, drawing on resources across academic, legal, and health professions. It also came to contain a far broader range of political, religious, and philosophical perspectives than before.Footnote 40, Footnote 41, Footnote 42, Footnote 43

These perspectives themselves became, with time, more nuanced and robust. Viewpoints that once seem relatively unified have revealed themselves to be sites of rich contention: For example, while the debate was largely split along secular/religious lines, there emerged secular arguments against PAS and religious ones for it.Footnote 44, Footnote 45, Footnote 46, Footnote 47, Footnote 48, Footnote 49 This was true of any number of communities in the debate: feminists, disability rights activists, hospice professionals, etc. The PAS debate thus spawned a multitude of additional debates, each one of which enriched the larger discussion.

The result was not just a good debate. It was a model for what debate should be. This model reflected well on its participants: both the advocates and the opponents of PAS, the various philosophical and political groups engaged in it, and the field of bioethics, which acted as a self-appointed curator of the discussion, setting its basic terms. Ultimately, it reflected well on the societies in which it took place, and on the institutions of higher learning responsible for the scholarship that informed it. It was a debate that realized the larger goal of the university and even participatory democracy itself.

That debate is now distracted. Neither side has “won” the debate, at least not as that term might be conventionally understood. The issues underpinning this debate have not been resolved. However, they have been pushed from view. Indeed, the very framework that is now used to discuss the phenomenon being debated renders several of the debate’s important philosophical tenets fundamentally invisible. The name of that framework is “MAID.”

…And its fragmentation

It is tempting to view the term “MAID” as another worthwhile innovation in the PAS debate. This is the argument of proponents of the term, who claim that “MAID” or “PAD” more accurately represents the action it describes.Footnote 50, Footnote 51, Footnote 52 But the effect of “MAID” is not to improve the “right to die” debate. This result is inherent to the term itself.

“PAS’’ describes an act that could be debated. The reason why one could debate this act is because it was justifiable to agree or disagree about it. Participants in the debate could do so from either perspective without betraying their argument or their underlying principles. They could disagree on the merits of the act because they could all agree about the matter they were disagreeing about: that matter was suicide. “MAID” erases suicide from the discussion. This is, according to its proponents, the term’s purpose. Regardless, it is its effect. “MAID” transforms suicide into a natural death, shifting its cause from human behavior to underlying illness. One could debate whether this transformation accurately describes the phenomenon in question—and we will. However, before doing so, we want to highlight how adopting this term transforms not the act but rather the ethical debate about it.

When using the term “MAID,” it is possible to support the act. However, it is not possible to oppose it. If we were to agree that what is “really” happening in Sam’s case, described above, is a natural death hastened but not caused by human action, then there would be no cause for disagreement about whether that death was good or bad. His “natural death” would be an unquestioned good.Footnote 53 PAS opponents have never claimed to oppose hastening death by an action so negligible that it does not disrupt an underlying natural process; their claim is that the action, in this case, causes a disturbance so significant that it takes dying out of the realm of nature and into that of human causality. These arguments—all of them—begin with the premise that PAS is a form of killing. Footnote 54 , Footnote 55 , Footnote 56, Footnote 57, Footnote 58 “MAID” begins with a premise that is precisely the opposite of this: the sequence of events is not killing. Also, this is a premise that opponents of the act under discussion cannot accept. To do so, they would have to support the act. Opposition to self-killing is the core objection of PAS opponents. If the act being discussed is not killing, but rather a “negligibly hastened natural death” (the description implicit in MAID), then there is nothing to oppose.

One might argue against this point by saying that MAID adheres to a logic that is similar to that of the so-called “principle of double effect,” (PDE) which many opponents of PAS support. Like MAID, the principle of double effect justifies calling a death “natural” even if it was caused by a human—and, more pointedly, medical—action.Footnote 59, Footnote 60 It makes it possible, for example, for a doctor to give Sam a dosage of morphine that both relieves his pain and ends his life without being accused of killing him. How is this different, in its underlying logic, from calling deaths that result from MAID “natural?”

It is different because the justification for the principle of double effect is intention. PDE proponents argue that intentionality determines the nature of action. In the end-of-life scenario described above, Sam’s death can only be classified as “natural” if the action that provoked it was not intended to do so. For example, if the reason the physician gave Sam the morphine was primarily to alleviate his pain—with no intention of ending his life—then the principle of double effect would be satisfied. If the doctor’s intention was killing, then it would not, and the death would be considered the result of human action. This is different from MAID. The primary intention behind the administration of MAID is to end Sam’s life. The determination regarding whether the resulting death is “natural” or not is therefore not based on intention. “MAID” is based on an implicit interpretation of the relationship between nature and time: that there is some period of time—presumably six months or less, the duration of the terminally ill individual’s prognosis—by which an individual (Sam) can have his life deliberately shortened by a health care professional without that shortening “causing” death. The underlying logic used here is wholly different than that of “double effect.”

There are thus no grounds on which opponents of the “right to die” could participate in a debate about “MAID.” From some opponents’ perspective, as Kevin Yuill has put it, “to call what happens in Oregon and Washington… anything other than suicide is patently ridiculous.”Footnote 61 He is not the only one who has made this argument.Footnote 62, Footnote 63, Footnote 64 This conclusion can also be supported by empirical evidence. In Sheri Gerson’s study of hospice professionals’ understanding of the difference between MAID and suicide, though many healthcare providers recoiled at the word “suicide”, one physician stated, “I do not think it helps us to pretend that our patients are not actively taking their own lives.”Footnote 65

But the field of bioethics has largely moved to “MAID,” and this move’s impact has been profound. The result is, instead of one debate, we now have two separate “right to die” discussions. The terms framing each discussion—“PAS” and “MAID” respectively—are no longer primarily, or even relatively, descriptive; they are indicators of the normative assessments of the individuals using them. PAS opponents use “PAS” while MAID (or PAS) supporters use “MAID”—assessing sympathetically identifying with others who use whatever one considers to be the “right” term, and disregarding everyone else. This is neither thought nor intellectual exchange—and it does nothing to advance our understanding of what remains, in our view, an important issue that continues to be worth discussing.

In such an environment—in which the term one uses is taken, often accurately, as a window into one’s ethical analysis—it might seem a foreordained conclusion that we, advocates of the term “PAS,” oppose PAS the practice. This is not true: one of us opposes it and the other supports it. However, such possibilities, once common, are now difficult to conceive. This difficulty is not one that should be celebrated by “right to die” supporters. On the contrary, the loss of “PAS” has effaced pro-PAS arguments that are worthwhile in themselves, different from those put forward for MAID, and, in our opinion, significantly stronger. A return to “PAS” is thus not one that benefits only, or primarily, PAS opponents. It is better for everyone.

Why “PAS” is better for everyone

As we have tried to emphasize throughout, the shift from “PAS” to “MAID” is not a small one. It is fundamental, as are the implications that it has for long-standing aspects of the “right to die” debate. Here we focus on its implications for what we consider to be the most central—or certainly among the most central—concerns of both PAS supporters and opponents: the protection of vulnerable populations and the exercise of individual autonomy. Although these concerns are often pitted against one another—with there being a presumptive tension between the affirmation of suicidal autonomy and the protection of vulnerable populations—here we find that the term “MAID” damages both of these concerns. For this reason, the “MAID” terminology undermines arguments both in favor of and opposed to the “right to die.” It is from a shared acknowledgment of the validity of “PAS” that one can most effectively support or oppose the act itself.

Protection of vulnerable populations

The strongest argument, in our opinion, against PAS has come from advocates for disability rights. This argument considers PAS to be a discriminatory double standard in the application of suicide prevention: while suicide is condemned in able-bodied people, people who are terminally ill and, in some cases, chronically sick and disabled are denied routine interventions to alleviate suicidal ideation. This is a double standard, and it is discriminatory because it is based on the assumption that the lives of terminally and chronically ill people are worth so much less than able-bodied people that they are arguably not worth living.

This discriminatory double standard would be bad enough in the abstract. However, it does not occur in the abstract. It occurs, rather, in the context of a society that is already explicitly and implicitly discriminatory against terminally and chronically ill people. This discrimination includes the denial of routine services, physical segregation in institutions or negligent home environments, and ceaseless devaluation of cultural products.Footnote 66, Footnote 67, Footnote 68, Footnote 69, Footnote 70 This broader social discrimination has been shown to drive terminally ill and disabled people to want to take their lives.Footnote 71, Footnote 72, Footnote 73 But PAS, rather than recognizing the discrimination underlying suicidal ideation, either ignores it or, arguably, affirms the bias.

Opponents argue that PAS is thus not just bad in the abstract. It is bad because it furthers existing systemic discrimination of the sort that drives terminally ill individuals into the “forced choice” to end their lives.Footnote 74, Footnote 75 PAS, thus, is a discriminatory double standard in the treatment of suicidal ideation in a group of people who experience precisely the sort of discrimination that drives people to suicide.

“MAID” does not alleviate this double standard. On the contrary, it exacerbates it. It creates two categories of suicides: one, which is described as a “suicide”; and another which is considered a “natural death.” The effect of this distinction is to make it almost impossible for those terminally ill—and potentially chronically disabled—people who seek “MAID” to complete suicide. This excludes them from suicide prevention, an exclusion which, in itself, is discriminatory. Also, it is additionally discriminatory in its implication that their lives are of so little value that they cannot complete suicide, to begin with. Determining that their suicides were “rational” might carry a similar implication,Footnote 76 but it would be notably less severe than the denial that they had completed suicide at all.

Excluding the word “suicide” from describing the act of hastening one’s own death also contributes to the stigmatization of suicidal people. Strict avoidance of the word “suicide” furthers a specific type of discrimination identified by Alexandre Baril as “suicidism.” Suicidism is “an oppressive system (stemming from non-suicidal perspectives) functioning at the normative, discursive, medical, legal, social, political, economic, and epistemic levels in which suicidal people experience multiple forms of injustice and violence.”Footnote 77 One of suicidism’s primary operations is to promote “compulsory aliveness,” a vitalist view that values continuing life above all else.Footnote 78 We stand with Dr. Baril and include the word “suicide” in the act of PAS because we wish to add our voices to the project of reclaiming “suicide” from entirely negative connotations and allow alternative narratives about the state of wanting to bring about one’s own death sooner than that death would occur naturally to be heard.Footnote 79 It is possible for a suicidal act to be undertaken as an assertion of autonomy, the most extreme declaration of liberty, or as a response to oppression.Footnote 80, Footnote 81 We wish to include the word suicide to reclaim and re-emphasize these myriad of meanings.

In contrast to suicide, “MAID” erases the role of human action in the provocation of death. Since discrimination would, presumably, come through human action, this makes it much more difficult to examine the potential for bias. This is true of both proximal discrimination—such as that coming from the suicidal individual, as well as the health care workers and family members they interact with—as well as distal discrimination, grounded in the structure of society. One can note the possibility and even the presence of such discrimination while supporting PAS; indeed, this was in part the premise behind the arguments of disability rights advocates, like Andrew Batavia and Lennard Davis, who have supported the practice in the past.Footnote 82, Footnote 83 But “MAID” makes it much more difficult to acknowledge these factors, since doing so requires recognizing that the individual wants to die to begin with. “MAID” erases this desire, and its key role in the causation of death, under the cloak of nature. The cause of death in such circumstances is listed as the terminal health condition.Footnote 84, Footnote 85 This seems particularly ironic, considering that patients chose PAS precisely to ensure that they did not die from their disease. With the inclusion of the word suicide, we wish to center the intention and agency of those who wish to hasten their own death.

“MAID” thus carries immensely greater risks than “PAS” for vulnerable groups and those who are concerned about protecting them. Perhaps such risks could be justified were “MAID” to dramatically expand individual autonomy. However, in this respect also, “PAS” is a much better term.

Valuing autonomy

There was a time in which PAS advocates argued that suicide was a fundamental right. PAS, in this view, was the epitome of the individual’s control over her life, a control that, naturally, would culminate in the decision to bring—or not—that life to an end. Suicide can be seen as a radical re-orientation against a world where one’s preference not to live is interpreted as inherently irrational and pathologized. Suicidal individuals are often stigmatized and oppressed. By re-inserting the word “suicide,” we seek to unlink the act of voluntarily ending one’s life from “pathologization, alienation, [and] stigmatization” that is rampant under the current regime of suicidism.Footnote 86 PAS was not previously just another instance of “patient autonomy.” It was the instance of autonomy itself: a special instance, one that represented an underlying idea of freedom that defined human progress and even human nature itself.Footnote 87, Footnote 88, Footnote 89, Footnote 90, Footnote 91 No more. PAS was the apex of autonomy. MAID is an act of nature. Unlike physician-assisted suicide, MAID does not describe an individual act of self-killing. It describes instead a culmination of a biological process: dying. Human action—the prescription and ingestion of a fatal substance—does not alter this process.Footnote 92 The action facilitates death, working with nature rather than against it.Footnote 93 MAID does not then refer to a human-driven act; it is an act of nature.

MAID is thus not, contrary to the claims of its proponents, a “choice.” It is, rather, a capitulation: a recognition that there are, in fact, harsh limits on human choice and that the choice to die is the most fundamental among them. MAID does not thus give individuals the “freedom” to die. Rather, it indicates that they never had this freedom. In the process, it implies that the desire to have this freedom—the desire to die—is morally wrong: that suicide, in itself, is inherently bad. This places a hard limit on autonomy while furthering the stigmatization of those people—suicidal people—who would seek to surmount it. Also, it diminishes the choices made by those who seek “MAID”: it strips them of agency over their deaths.

However, suicide can be an autonomous choice. This, at least, was the argument of those who supported PAS. Also, this argument tied this support to PAS to a larger conversation about the ethics of rational suicide itself. This was intellectually worthwhile: suicide is worth debating, and PAS should be a part of that debate. Also, it was something that both supporters and opponents of PAS could appreciate. Indeed, one could even accept that PAS furthers autonomy while opposing the act—a position that is impossible in the era of “MAID.”

Ultimately, “PAS” makes it possible for those who seek it to affirm their choice to die as the fullest expression of themselves. “MAID” significantly weakens their ability to do so, and, in the process, limits the extension of human autonomy itself. In the process, it stigmatizes suicidal individuals, who, from the perspective of “MAID,” continue to use their autonomy in a manner implicitly irrational and unethical.Footnote 94, Footnote 95, Footnote 96 The term “MAID” should thus be opposed, on analytic grounds, even by “right to die” supporters. The best justification for the term is not analytical but political: it makes it easier to garner support for what is in reality PAS. It is this political argument that we address in our conclusion.

Conclusions

We want to return to Sam. If we describe Sam’s action as “PAS,” it opens up a range of possibilities: the possibility that he might have been driven to suicide by discriminatory social factors that could be alleviated via means much less drastic than a self-inflicted death, as well as the possibility that his desire to die is a rational reflection of his will and that he is justified in taking his life. These possibilities could be explored and, based on one’s findings, could inform the normative conclusions that one might draw about both Sam’s particular act of suicide as well as the larger topic itself.

But “MAID” opens up no such possibilities for Sam—or anyone. “MAID” strips him of his choice to die. It also strips him of the basic protections provided by the ability of society and those involved in his death to scrutinize what drove him to make this choice. Indeed, there is no “choice” to scrutinize because Sam’s death, as an example of “MAID,” is a manifestation of nature itself. His death, as a result, means nothing, except that nature was, in the end, in control. However, this is not true: nature was not in control in Sam’s death. Sam was. Also, this acknowledgment can and should form the basis of any argument in favor of his having such control. This can be true for defenses of PAS. However, we also think that it provides a foundation for the best defense of the term “MAID.”

The best argument in favor of “MAID” is that it is the term that, politically, can do the most to extend the control that dying people have over the ends of their lives. This is because to use the term “suicide” to refer to Sam’s action would make the creation of a legal and medical context in which he might take such an action significantly more difficult, perhaps particularly in the United States today. This is the political argument for “MAID,” one that supporters of the term have often considered to be secondary, but that we believe to be superior. In this political argument, the overall good that would come from legalizing PAS under the rubric of “MAID” would overwhelm any objection to the use of inaccurate or misleading terminology. This is a compelling point if one believes—as both PAS and “MAID” supporters do—that giving individuals the right to die is a significant, perhaps even fundamental, good. The usage of “MAID” has almost certainly built the political support necessary to extend access to PAS to millions of people. It thus, in theory, does a great good and one might even argue that using “MAID,” even misleadingly, in such a context becomes a moral necessity in that it makes this good possible.

One could further this point by noting that in the public sphere, opponents of PAS often have seemingly very little qualms with making misleading arguments about the motives of PAS supporters and the impact of the practice itself. Politics is, as the saying goes, a dirty game. Also, it is not fair to hold PAS supporters to a standard that is significantly higher than that of PAS opponents, indeed, one that might make their cause difficult if not impossible to achieve.

We disagree with this argument. We believe that it is not practically impossible to garner significant public support for PAS, and that doing so, in fact, might even have residual benefits—such as provoking a broader, less stigmatizing conversation about the ethics of suicide and creating a greater awareness of disability rights—that should figure into any ethical calculation. We also believe that transparency in political discourse is a worthwhile virtue and that betraying it comes with costs that, though seemingly subtle, can be quite profound. We think that the overall benefit to PAS supporters, opponents, and, particularly, those undecided on the practice, of using “PAS” outweighs the instrumental value of the move to “MAID.” And we think that we owe at least this much to Sam: to be candid with him and to recognize and honor—perhaps, even in disagreement—the choice he made.

We believe this—and we may be wrong. However, we at least want someone to tell us that we are wrong, and to do so in a scholarly manner befitting of bioethical debate. It is that lack of such arguments—arguments in favor of the term “MAID”—in bioethics journals that we find particularly concerning. PAS and MAID are topics pertaining to one of our field’s core issues—euthanasia—and the need to thoroughly debate them is equivalent to a raison d’etre. That the move to “MAID” has occurred without any rigorous debate is alarming, for it undermines the putative justification for bioethics itself. However, unlike some of the other effects of this shift, this consequence can be remedied, and it is partly with that goal in mind that we have written this article.

Competing interest

None declared.

References

Notes

1. Manns H. The Fear That Dare Not Peak Its Name: How Language Plays a Role in the Assisted Dying Debate. 2017 Nov 5. Waltham, MA: The Conversation US, Inc. [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at http://theconversation.com/the-fear-that-dare-not-speak-its-name-how-language-plays-a-role-in-the-assisted-dying-debate-86308.

2. Thomasma, D. Euthanasia: Toward an Ethical Social Policy. New York, NY: Continuum; 1990 Google Scholar.

3. Mishara, BL and Weisstub, DN. Legalization of euthanasia in Quebec, Canada as “medical aid-i- dying”: A case study in social marketing, changing mores and legal maneuvering. Ethics, Medicine and Public Health 2015;1(4):450–5. doi:10.1016/j.jemep.2015.10.021 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4. See note 2, Thomasma 1990.

5. Vamos, MJ. Physician-assisted suicide: Saying what we mean and meaning what we say. Australian & New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 2012;46(2):84–6. doi:10.1177/0004867411432069 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

6. Chin, AE, Hedberg, K, Higginson, GK, Fleming, DW. Legalized physician-assisted suicide in Oregon—The first years’ experience. New England Journal of Medicine 1999;340(7):577–83. doi:10.1056/NEJM199902183400724 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

7. Fenn, DS, Ganzini, L. Attitudes of Oregon psychologists toward physician-assisted suicide and the Oregon Death With Dignity Act. Professional Psychology: Research and Practice 1999;30(3):235. doi:10.1037/0735-7028.30.3.235 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

8. Duncan, OD, Parmelee, LF. Trends in public approval of euthanasia and suicide in the US, 1947–2003. Journal of Medical Ethics 2006;32(5):266–72. doi:10.1136/jme.2004.011072 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9. Ashby, M. “The danger of words:” Language games in bioethics. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 2023;15. doi:10.1007/s11673-023-10248-5 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

10. Callahan, D. Organized obfuscation: Advocacy for physician-assisted suicide. The Hastings Center Report 2008;38(5):30–2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

11. Compassion & Choices. Medical Aid in Dying Is Not Suicide, Assisted Suicide or Euthanasia. 2024. Littleton, CO: Compassion & Choices Google Scholar [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at https://compassionandchoices.org/resource/not-assisted-suicide/

12. Saad L. US Support for Euthanasia Hinges on How It’s Described. 2013 May 29. Washington, DC: Gallup [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at https://news.gallup.com/poll/162815/support-euthanasia-hinges-described.aspx

13. Health Canada. Medical Assistance in Dying: Overview. 2024 Jul 18. Ottawa, ON, Canada: Health Canada [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at https://www.canada.ca/en/health-canada/services/medical-assistance-dying.html

14. Riisfeldt, TD. Overcoming conflicting definitions of “euthanasia,” and of “assisted suicide,” through a value-neutral taxonomy of “End-Of-Life Practices.” Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 2023;20(1).120 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15. Buchbinder, M. Access to aid-in-dying in the United States: Shifting the debate from rights to justice. American Journal of Public Health 2018;108(6):754–9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

16. Marquardt, DS. Medical assistance in dying and disability rightsSocial Work & Policy Studies: Social Justice, Practice and Theory 2021;4(1):19.Google Scholar

17. Ostrom C. Just Do not Call It Suicide, Initiative’s Backers Say. 2008 Jan 9. Seattle, WA: The Seattle Times [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at https://www.seattletimes.com/seattle-news/just-dont-call-it-suicide-initiatives-backers-say/.

18. See note 12, Saad 2013.

19. Singer, P. Voluntary euthanasia: A utilitarian perspective. Bioethics 2003;17(5–6):526–41. doi:10.1111/1467-8519.00366 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

20. Yount, L, ed. Euthanasia: Contemporary Issues. New York, NY: Greenhaven Press; 2002 Google Scholar.

21. See note 11; Compassion & Choices 2024.

22. Creighton C, Cerel J, Battin M. Statement of the American Association of Suicidology: “Suicide” Is Not the Same as “Physician Aid in Dying.” 2017 Oct 30. Hummelstown, PA, US: American Association of Suicidology [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at https://ohiooptions.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/02/AAS-PAD-Statement-Approved-10.30.17-ed-10-30-17.pdf.

23. Dauber, M. An analysis of New York state’s medical aid in dying act (A. 2383A S. 3151). Voices in Bioethics 2018;4(4):16. http://www.voicesinbioethics.net/voices-in-bioethics/2018/5/3/an-analysis-of-new-york-states-medical-aid-in-dying-act-a-2383a-s-3151.Google Scholar

24. Snyder Sulmasy, L, Mueller, PS. Ethics and the legalization of physician-assisted suicide: An American College of Physicians position paper. Annals of Internal Medicine 2017;167(8):576–8. doi:10.7326/M17-0938 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

25. Byock I. Physician-Assisted Suicide Won’t Atone for Medicine’s “Original Sin.” 2018 Jan 31. Boston, MA: Stat [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at http://irabyock.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/01/Byock-I-Medicines-original-sin-STAT-First-Opinion-01-31-18.pdf

26. Longmore, PK. Policy, prejudice, and reality: Two case studies of physician-assisted suicide. Journal of Disability Policy Studies 2005;16(1):3845 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27. Battin, MP. Suicide and ethical theory. Suicide & Life-Threatening Behavior 1983;13:231–9. doi:10.1111/j.1943-278x.1983.tb00021.x CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

28. Hacking, I. The suicide weapon. Critical Inquiry 2008;35(1):132. doi:10.1086/595626 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29. McClelland, L, Reicher, S, Booth, N. A last defence: The negotiation of blame within suicide notes. Journal of Community & Applied Social Psychology 2000;10(3):225–403.0.CO;2-1>CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30. Schramme, T. Rational suicide, assisted suicide, and indirect legal paternalism. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 2013;36(5–6):477484. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2013.06.008 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

31. Sjöstrand, M, Sandman, L, Karlsson, P, Helgesson, G, Eriksson, S, Juth, N. Ethical deliberations about involuntary treatment: Interviews with Swedish psychiatrists. BMC Medical Ethics 2015;16:112. doi:10.1186/s12910-015-0029-5 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

32. Werth, JL. Using rational suicide as an intervention to prevent irrational suicide. Crisis 1998;19(4):185–92. doi:10.1027/0227-5910.19.4.185 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

33. Fadem, P, Minkler, M, Perry, M, Blum, K, Moore, L Jr, Rogers, J, Williams, L. Attitudes of people with disabilities toward physician-assisted suicide legislation: Broadening the dialogue. Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 2003;28(6):9771002. doi:10.1215/03616878-28-6-977 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

34. Gill, Carol. The false autonomy of forced choice: Rationalizing suicide for persons with disabilities. In: Werth, J, ed. Contemporary Perspectives on Rational Suicide. Ann Arbor, MI: Taylor & Francis; 1999:171–80Google Scholar.

35. Hannig, A. Author (iz) ing death: Medical aid-in-dying and the morality of suicide. Cultural Anthropology 2019;34(1):5377. doi:10.14506/ca34.1.0 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36. Mendelson, D, Bagaric, M. Assisted suicide through the prism of the right to life. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 2013;36(5–6):406–18. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2013.06.012 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

37. See note 30, Schramme 2013.

38. Szasz, T. Suicide Prohibition: The Shame of Medicine. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press; 2011 Google Scholar.

39. Yuill, K. The unfreedom of assisted suicide: How the right to die undermines autonomy. Ethics, Medicine and Public Health 2015;1(4):494502. doi:10.1016/j.jemep.2015.10.003 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40. See note 35, Hannig 2019.

41. Keown, D. Suicide, assisted suicide and euthanasia: A Buddhist perspective. Journal of Law and Religion 1998;13(2):385405. doi:10.2307/1051472 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

42. Monforte‐Royo, C, Villavicencio‐Chávez, C, Tomás‐Sábado, J, Balaguer, A. The wish to hasten death: A review of clinical studies. Psycho‐Oncology 2011;20(8):795804. doi:10.1002/pon.1839 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43. van Wijngaarden, E, Leget, C, Goossensen, A. Disconnectedness from the here-and-now: A phenomenological perspective as a counteract on the medicalisation of death wishes in elderly people. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2016;19:265–73. doi:10.1007/s11019-016-9687-4 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

44. Bishop, JP. Framing euthanasia. Journal of Medical Ethics 2006;32(4):225–8. doi:10.1136/jme.2005.013847 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

45. See note 15, Buchbinder 2018.

46. Gorsuch, N. The Future of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; 2006 Google Scholar.

47. See note 36, Mendelson & Bagaric 2013.

48. See note 30, Schramme 2013.

49. Tutu D. Desmond Tutu: A Dignified Death Is Our Right – I Am in Favour of Assisted Dying. 2014 Jul 12. London, UK: The Guardian [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/jul/12/desmond-tutu-in-favour-of-assisted-dying.

50. See note 22, Creighton et al. 2017.

51. Smith, DM, Pollack, D. A psychiatric defense of aid in dying. Community Mental Health Journal 1998;34:547–56. doi:10.1023/a:1018754816369 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

52. Tucker, KL, Steele, FB. Patient choice at the end of life: Getting the language right. The Journal of Legal Medicine 2007;28(3):305–25CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

53. Richards, N. Assisted suicide as a remedy for suffering? The end-of-life preferences of British “suicide tourists.” Medical Anthropology 2017;36(4):348–62. doi:10.1080/01459740.2016.1255610 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

54. Parker, M. Defending the indefensible? Psychiatry, assisted suicide and human freedom. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 2013;36(5–6):485497. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2013.06.007 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

55. See note 53, Richards 2017.

56. Stauch, M. Causal authorship and the equality principle: A defence of the acts/omissions distinction in euthanasia. Journal of Medical Ethics 2000;26(4):237–41. doi:10.1136/jme.26.4.237 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

57. Sulmasy, DP. Physician-assisted suicide and the perils of empirical ethical research. JAMA Network Open 2019;8:e198628 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58. Wittwer, H. The problem of the possible rationality of suicide and the ethics of physician-assisted suicide. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 2013;36(5–6):419–26. doi:10.1016/j.ijlp.2013.06.009 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

59. Lavi, S. The Modern Art of Dying: A History of Euthanasia in the US. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; 2005 Google Scholar.

60. See note 54, Parker 2013.

61. See note 39, Yuill 2015, at 497.

62. Byock, I. Words matter: It is still physician-assisted suicide and still wrong. Maryland Medicine 2017;17(4) [accessed 2024 Aug 2]. http://irabyock.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/06/Byock-Maryland-Medicine-vol-17-4-January-2017.pdf Google Scholar.

63. Pies R. Brittany Maynard and the Loose Language of Suicide. 2014 Nov 19. Newark, NJ: WebMD LLC [accessed 2024 Aug 2]; available at https://www.medscape.com/viewarticle/835014.

64. Reed, P. Is “aid in dying” suicide? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 2019;40(2):123–39. doi:10.1007/s11017-019-09485-w CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

65. Gerson, SM, Preston, NJ, Bingley, AF. Medical aid in dying, hastened death, and suicide: A qualitative study of hospice professionals’ experiences from Washington State. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 2020;59(3):679–86. doi:10.1016/j.jpainsymman.2019.10.021 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

66. Braswell, H. From disability rights to the rights of the dying (and back again). Laws 2017;6(4) 31 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

67. Braswell, H. The Crisis of US Hospice Care: Family and Freedom at the End of Life. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press; 2019 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

68. Coleman, D. Assisted suicide laws create discriminatory double standard for who gets suicide prevention and who gets suicide assistance: Not Dead Yet Responds to Autonomy, Inc. Disability and Health Journal 2010;3(1):3950. doi:10.1016/j.dhjo.2009.09.004 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

69. Gill, CJ. No, we don’t think our doctors are out to get us: Responding to the straw man distortions of disability rights arguments against assisted suicide. Disability and Health Journal 2010;3(1):31–8. doi:10.1016/j.dhjo.2009.10.003 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

70. Golden, M, Zoanni, T. Killing us softly: The dangers of legalizing assisted suicide. Disability and Health Journal 2010;3(1):1630. doi:10.1016/j.dhjo.2009.08.006 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

71. See note 66, Braswell 2017.

72. See note 67, Braswell 2019.

73. See note 26, Longmore 2005.

74. See note 69, Gill 2010.

75. See note 70, Golden & Zoanni 2010.

76. Den Hartogh, G. Two kinds of suicide. Bioethics 2016;30(9):672–80. doi:10.1111/bioe.12287 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

77. Baril, A. Suicidism: A new theoretical framework to conceptualize suicide from an anti-oppressive perspective. Disability Studies Quarterly 2020;40(3). doi:10.18061/dsq.v40i3.7053 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

78. Baril, A. Undoing Suicidism: A Trans, Queer, Crip Approach to Rethinking (Assisted) Suicide. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press; 2023 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

79. See note 78, Baril 2023.

80. Amery, J. On Suicide: A Discourse on voluntary Death. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press; 1999 Google Scholar.

81. Marsh, I. Suicide: Foucault, History and Truth. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 2010 Google Scholar.

82. Batavia, AI. Disability and physician-assisted suicide. New England Journal of Medicine 1997;336(23):1671–3CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

83. Davis, L. The End of Normal: Identity in a Biocultural Era. Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press; 2013 Google Scholar.

84. See note 22, Creighton et al. 2017.

85. See note 24, Snyder Sulmasy & Mueller 2017.

86. See note 78, Baril 2023, at 8.

87. Battin, MP. Terminal sedation: Pulling the sheet over our eyes. The Hastings Center Report 2008;38(5):2730. doi:10.1353/hcr.0.0057 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

88. Diekstra, RFW. The significance of Nico Speijer’s suicide: How and when should suicide be prevented? Suicide and Life‐Threatening Behavior 1986;16(1):13–5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

89. Lieberman, L. Leaving You: The Cultural Meaning of Suicide. Chicago, IL: Ivan R. Dee Press; 2003 Google Scholar.

90. See note 51, Smith & Pollack 1998.

91. Van Brussel, L. Autonomy and dignity: A discussion on contingency and dominance. Health Care Analysis 2014;22(2):174–91. doi:10.1007/s10728-012-0217-0 Google ScholarPubMed.

92. See note 91, Van Brussel 2014.

93. See note 23, Dauber 2018.

94. Friesen, P. Medically assisted dying and suicide: How are they different, and how are they similar? The Hastings Center Report 2020;50(1):3243. doi:10.1002/hast.1083 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

95. See note 78, Baril 2023.

96. See note 38, Szasz 2011.