Published online by Cambridge University Press: 15 February 2011
Adaptive preference formation is the unconscious altering of our preferences in light of the options we have available. Jon Elster has argued that this is bad because it undermines our autonomy. I agree, but think that Elster's explanation of why is lacking. So, I draw on a richer account of autonomy to give the following answer. Preferences formed through adaptation are characterized by covert influence (that is, explanations of which an agent herself is necessarily unaware), and covert influence undermines our autonomy because it undermines the extent to which an agent's preferences are ones that she has decided upon for herself. This answer fills the lacuna in Elster's argument. It also allows us to draw a principled distinction between adaptive preference formation and the closely related – but potentially autonomy-enhancing – phenomenon of character planning.
1 Elster, J., Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality (Cambridge, 1983)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
2 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 109.
3 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 20. Others have made the same claim, e.g. Christman, John in ‘Autonomy and Personal History’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1991), pp. 1–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Zimmerman, David in ‘Making Do: Troubling Stoic Tendencies in an Otherwise Compelling Theory of Autonomy’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (2000), pp. 25–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar, esp. 27–30.
4 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 30.
5 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 15.
6 Elster, Sour Grapes, pp. 15–17.
7 Elster, Sour Grapes, pp. 21–2.
8 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 24.
9 Elster, Sour Grapes, pp. 111–24.
10 Elster, Sour Grapes, pp. 117–19.
11 Elster, Sour Grapes, pp. 118–19.
12 e.g. Rickard, M., ‘Sour-grapes, Rational Desires and Objective Consequentialism’, Philosophical Studies 80 (199), p. 279–303CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 284.
13 Others besides Elster have tried to characterize the distinction. For the most part their distinctions tend to map onto one or other of the proposals for interpreting Elster that I discuss here, so I do not mention them separately. One exception is Luc Bovens, who says that the two types of phenomenon differ in respect of the semantic content of the preferences we end up with: adaptive preference formation involves adjusting one's preference for tokens without engaging in reasoning about the desirability of types, whereas ‘a typical case of character planning is the more involved project in which I can adjust my reasons for the ranking at hand’. See Bovens, L. ‘Sour Grapes and Character Planning’, The Journal of Philosophy 89 (1992), pp. 57–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 74. I do not consider Bovens's proposal here, for the same reasons as those given by Zimmerman, who complains that its focus on the content of preferences is misplaced, and leads Bovens to ignore some important variants of adaptive preference formation (see his ‘Sour Grapes, Self-abnegation and Character Building’, The Monist 86 (2003), pp. 220–41, at 228–35).
14 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 117.
15 Elster, Sour Grapes, pp. 109–10.
16 For further discussion of Elster's distinction construed this way, see Sandven, Tore in ‘Intentional Action and Pure Causality: A Critical Discussion of Some Central Conceptual Distinctions in the Work of Jon Elster’, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (1995), pp. 286–317CrossRefGoogle Scholar; ‘Autonomy, Adaptation, and Rationality – A Critical Discussion of Jon Elster's Concept of “Sour Grapes” Part I’, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 29 (1999), pp. 3–31; and ‘Autonomy, Adaptation, and Rationality – A Critical Discussion of Jon Elster's Concept of “Sour Grapes” Part II’, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 29 (1999), pp. 173–205.
17 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 117. See also Zimmerman ‘Sour Grapes’, p. 221.
18 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 117.
19 Friedman, M., ‘Autonomy and the Split-Level Self’, Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (1986), pp. 19–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
20 Frankfurt, H., ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’, Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971), pp. 5–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
21 Dworkin, G., The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge 1988), p. 20CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Dworkin's book was published after Elster's, so the latter cannot have had in mind the precise formulation just quoted. However, Dworkin expressed a broadly similar idea earlier, e.g. in ‘Autonomy and Behaviour Control’, Hastings Centre Report 6 (1976), pp. 23–8; and ‘The Concept of Autonomy’, Science and Ethics, ed. R. Haller (Amsterdam, 1981), pp. 203–13.
22 Watson, G., ‘Free Agency’, Journal of Philosophy 72 (1975), pp. 205–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Thalberg, I., ‘Hierarchical Analyses of Unfree Action’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1978), pp. 211–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
23 Friedman, ‘Autonomy and the Split-Level Self’.
24 There are more such arguments in Friedman, ‘Autonomy and the Split-Level Self’, Thalberg ‘Hierarchical Analyses’, and Oshana, M., ‘How Much Should We Value Autonomy?’, Social Philosophy and Policy 20.2 (2003), pp. 99–126CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Some defences can be found in Bratman, M., ‘Autonomy and Hierarchy’, Social Philosophy and Policy 20.2 (2003), pp. 156–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
25 Raz, J., The Morality of Freedom (Oxford, 1986), p. 370Google Scholar. Similar notions of autonomy can be found in Hurka, T., Perfectionism (Oxford, 1993), p. 148Google Scholar; and Wall, S.Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint (Cambridge, 1998), p. 128CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
26 Colburn, B., Autonomy and Liberalism (New York, 2010), p. 19Google Scholar.
27 Dworkin, Theory and Practice of Autonomy, p. 18.
28 There is, of course, a further question whether the lack of covert influence is not merely necessary, but also sufficient for independence. Since an answer to that question is not needed for my purposes here, I do not seek to address it.
29 Crisp, R., ‘Persuasive Advertising, Autonomy, and the Creation of Desire’, Journal of Business Ethics 6 (1987), pp. 413–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
30 Crisp, ‘Persuasive Advertising’, pp. 414–15.
31 Crisp, ‘Persuasive Advertising’, p. 415.
32 Crisp, ‘Persuasive Advertising’, p. 416. We can assume that the unconscious link is indeed risible, and hence won't stand up to scrutiny.
33 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 117.
34 Elster, Sour Grapes, p. 118. Interestingly, the means of character planning employed might be covert, even if the crucially significant decision to engage in the process is not. So, for example, if I fail at overt character planning, I might decide to put myself in the hands of someone who is a master at covert preference change, in the hope that his covert techniques might be successful. My thanks to an anonymous referee for the example.
35 For instructive discussion of this, see Zimmerman (‘Making Do’, pp. 35–7, and ‘Sour Grapes’, pp. 225–6), who worries that on Elster's view we can't distinguish character planning from the much more troubling phenomenon of self-abnegation, whereby an agent consciously seeks to eliminate desires that lead to unhappiness due to dramatically curtailed option-sets.
36 Of course, we might think there is still something wrong with her situation, from the point of view of autonomy or otherwise.
37 My thanks to Harry Adamson, Daniel Elstein, Lorna Finlayson, Hallvard Lillehammer and Serena Olsaretti for discussion on arguments in this article.