In 1992, Herbert Mehrtens wrote an appendix to a paper he had published sixteen years earlier about the applicability of Kuhn’s theory to the history of mathematics. Mehrtens’ appendix was published as part of an edited volume entitled Revolutions in Mathematics. While his original article had been published when he was just making his way into the field, his appendix was written after the publication of his groundbreaking book, Moderne—Sprache—Mathematik. The historiography of mathematics had expanded since 1976, including a substantial literature on the social history of mathematics, but to some degree, Mehrtens reflected, it was still weighed down by old concerns. Whereas the “debate on the relative importance of ‘internal’ and ‘external’ factors in the development of science has faded away,” Mehrtens wrote, “the history of mathematics … appears to be somewhat behind the trend”(Mehrtens Reference Mehrtens and Gillies1995, 42). Despite these changes, he added, “I hear once in a while from historians of mathematics, that their field is too isolated from and too little recognized by colleagues in the history of natural sciences” (ibid.). Indeed, two years before he wrote his appendix, historian of mathematics Ivor Grattan-Guinness complained that the history of mathematics is “a classic example of a ghetto subject.” Karen Hunger Parshall and David Rowe repeated the complaint two years after Mehrtens wrote his appendix in their 1994 book, The Emergence of the American Mathematical Research Community. “The history of mathematics,” they wrote, has “been relatively neglected in the last several decades by American historians of science” (Parshall and Rowe Reference Parshall and Rowe1997, x).
Such concerns over the marginalization of the history of mathematics within the history of science did not end in the 1990s. Almost two decades later, in 2011, Isis published a “focus” section on the history of science and the history of mathematics. In the introductory essay, Amir Alexander still complained about the dearth of work in the history of mathematics and its marginalization within the history of science. “Mathematics was hardly ever interrogated, historicized, or contextualized in the way that scientific theories and practices are. It was more or less accepted as a useful but ahistorical construct, of which not much more could be said” (Alexander Reference Alexander2011, 477).
What might explain the orphaned position of the history of mathematics? For Grattan-Guinness the answer was simple. The history of mathematics was “too mathematical for historians and too historical for mathematicians” (Grattan-Guinness 1990, 158). For him, it was the technical nature of the field that explained why it was practically neglected. Perhaps, but, considering that many other fields of science are highly technical, his explanation is unlikely. Parshall and Rowe, for their part, lay some of the blame at the feet of historians of mathematics who, they write, “have tended to pursue their work independently of the trends that have shaped and altered the historiography of the history of science”(Parshall and Rowe Reference Parshall and Rowe1997, xii). In particular, the history of mathematics, they explain, was (wrongly) perceived to be less amenable to types of investigations popular in the history of science, which (following Alexandre Koyré and Thomas Kuhn) attended to ways philosophical and religious ideas impacted the development of scientific thought. This is a view with which Amir Alexander seems to agree, as he writes that the severing of the history of mathematics from the history of science is a “casualty of the social and cultural turn in the history of science”(Alexander Reference Alexander2011, 476). It is in consequence of this split, Alexander explains, that historians of mathematics turn to internalist studies.
The internalist-externalist debate that emerged in the 1970s was, of course, not unique to mathematics. Historians of medicine struggled with similar questions at the time (Reverby and Rosner Reference Reverby and Rosner2004). However, whereas in other fields these early debates eventually quieted down and new historiographic approaches to the history of science emerged, as Parshall and Rowe noted, this was not the case for the history of mathematics. In her 1995 critical reappraisal of the state of the field, Joan Richards seemed to concur, noting that while the internalist-externalist debate has been declared dead in the history of science, “the division between the two camps is not only a but the critical problem in the history of mathematics” (Richards Reference Richards1995, 123–124). While there is much merit in this view and the debates were undoubtedly lively within the history of mathematics, the explanation is peculiar considering that some of the most popular accounts of the history of mathematics that appeared in the preceding decades offered a deeply cultural and social analysis of the field.
The best two examples were Dirk Struik’s A Concise History of Mathematics, which was published in 1948 and reprinted in 1967, and E. T. Bell’s 1951 Mathematics: Queen or Servant of Science. An avowed Marxist, Struik offered a materialist reading of the history of mathematics. Compared to “oriental mathematics,” Struik wrote, the Greeks’ adaptation of the deductive method can partially be explained by the rise of a “politically conscious merchant class” (Struik, Reference Struik1948, 40).Footnote 1 According to Struik, “the new social order created a new type of man,” who as a result of slave labor could find time to “philosophize about this world of his.” In this new environment, modern mathematics, he explains, “helped find order in chaos, to arrange ideas in logical chains, to find fundamental principles” (Struik Reference Struik1948, 40–1).Footnote 2
Struik did not limit his Marxist analysis to ancient mathematics. In 1937, he wrote to George Sarton that he agrees that scientists make decisions that are not impacted by any other “force than what seems to them their own volition. … But this, I think, is not the whole story. The general cultural conditions demand certain scientific or artistic activity, or at any rate create the opportunity for it.”Footnote 3 Struik’s views that scientific and mathematical production is impelled by both personal freedom and social conditions fit neatly with the social turn in the history of science.Footnote 4
E. T. Bell extended this type of analysis to modernity. Noting that the demands of World War II occasioned new mathematical discoveries, Bell explained that the Napoleonic Wars galvanized a similar moment of mathematical activity. “It would be interesting to debate which one—war or economic necessity—has been the more influential in the development of mathematics. … My own opinion is that war has outranked economics at least two to one. As this is written much research in pure mathematics is being financed by the military” (Bell Reference Bell1951, 3–4). Far from offering an internalist account of mathematics, Bell understood both economic and military demands as foundational for the development of mathematics.
Struik and Bell are worth singling out because their books were widely read and translated to many languages. David Rowe suggested that “since its initial appearance,” Struik’s Concise History “has probably done more to promote interest in and appreciation for the rich diversity of mathematical ideas and cultures than any other single volume on the history of mathematics.”Footnote 5 Their scholarship makes it readily apparent that mathematicians were accustomed to the notion that social and cultural conditions had a profound impact on the development of mathematics. This is not to suggest that mathematicians were steeped in social or cultural history. Rather, history of science’s divorce from the history of mathematics in the last quarter of the twentieth century cannot be explained by claiming that the history of mathematics was not receptive to social and cultural analysis. In what follows, I want to suggest that this explanation is partial at best. The history of mathematics remained marginalized not because historians of mathematics could not agree to what degree social history impacted the development of mathematics, but because on the whole they adopted mathematicians’ own definition of what mathematics was.
In his 1992 essay, Mehrtens similarly laid the blame at the feet of historians of mathematics. The problem, he wrote, was not the “inaccessibility of mathematics, but rather the inability of its historians to relate to the issues of interest in general history of science” (Mehrtens 1995, 42). Yet, it seems to me that what Mehrtens had in mind was slightly different than what his colleagues at the time were concerned about. He was not worried about the adoption of social and cultural analysis in the history of mathematics, which I believe he took as a given. Rather, what he was arguing for was the recognition that “history of mathematics is an integral part of intellectual history” (Mehrtens Reference Mehrtens and Gillies1995, 48). It was up to the historian, he argued, to draw the necessary connections between the “epistemological ruptures” in mathematics and other intellectual concerns of the time. The problem, and the reason I believe the marginalization of the history of mathematics continues to be a concern two decades later, is that historians of mathematics have refrained from drawing such connections, for fear of no longer writing a history of “mathematics.” Perhaps, stated somewhat differently, when historians did indeed consider the history of mathematics as part of intellectual history, their work no longer belonged squarely within the “history of mathematics.”
The history of mathematics professionalized at a particularly fraught moment for American mathematicians, a time in which they were deeply concerned with the questions: what is mathematics? And what are its social and intellectual boundaries? The reason mathematicians were so invested in these questions was that, in the three decades after World War II, the mathematical landscape had completely changed. Europe’s devastation coincided with the Golden Age of American academia, a convergence that placed American mathematicians in a singular position within the international scholarly community. Mathematics was growing in both scale and scope as new areas of research, from operations research to control theory, were pushing the bounds of mathematical theory further and further. Moreover, mathematical modes of thinking were becoming increasingly prevalent not only in the physical, but the biological and social sciences as well (Steingart Reference Steingart2023).
Faced with these transformations, mathematicians approached the question “what is mathematics” as both an epistemological and a political query. Concerns over the boundaries of the field and about the relation between “pure” and “applied” mathematics were, of course, not new. Amir Alexander has demonstrated how mathematicians’ turn towards increased rigor during the early nineteenth century altered not only mathematical practice, but the persona of the mathematician as well (Alexander Reference Alexander2006, Reference Alexander2011).Footnote 6 What was unique about the post-World War II moment was that these debates were taking place within a new institutional terrain.Footnote 7 Propelled by national defense and government funds, the number of publications rose steeply, the number of mathematical departments grew, as did the number of students who needed training.Footnote 8 Yet a coherent national policy for mathematics could not be built upon the disciplinary matrix that defined the growth of the field before the war. It was to achieve that goal that American mathematicians turned to drawing borders around what constituted “proper” mathematics. The history of mathematics, coming along in these turbulent times, adopted this restricted conception of what mathematics is.
A turn to history
The clearest indication of mathematicians’ concern with the question “what is mathematics” was their renewed interest in the postwar period in the history of mathematics. While interest in the history of mathematics had been alive and well in the nineteenth century, the postwar turn to history came on the heels of a profound transformation in the meaning of mathematics.Footnote 9 The growth of mathematics in the previous decades represented a series of epistemological problems for mathematicians: Were new areas of research such as game theory, control theory, and computing part of mathematics or were they allied fields? What united these disparate activities? What was the relation between pure and applied mathematics? To answer these questions and others, mathematicians turned to history.Footnote 10
Historical writing by mathematicians took on different forms—from short historical surveys to more systematic studies by historically minded mathematicians such as Struik, Bell, Salomon Bochner, Max Dehn, Morris Kline, and Carl B. Boyer (Bochner Reference Bochner1966; Boyer Reference Boyer1968; Kline Reference Kline1959, Reference Kline1964).Footnote 11 These writings differed in their level of technicality and in expected audience, but all tried to offer an answer (if only a partial one) to the question of what mathematics “is” by identifying either a method, a way of thinking, or core ideas that connected the mathematics of the past with that of the present. In other words, while they offered different answers, all these works turned to history in order to identify an essentialized character of mathematics that connected the past to the present. A good example was a special issue entitled “Mathematics in the Modern World,” which appeared in Scientific American in 1964. An essay by Richard Courant opened the magazine, setting the tone for the special issue. Aimed at the general public, contributors presented an illustrated guide to recent developments in the mathematical sciences, with the goal of teaching readers about modern mathematics. The image that accompanied the text, however, was not of a computer, a communications control room, or even a seminar room filled with young aspiring mathematicians. Rather, facing the text was a photograph of the Rhind Papyrus, one of the earliest extant sources of mathematical thinking from the second century BC. Discovered in the nineteenth century, the Rhind Papyrus compiles Egyptian problems on the measurement of land. It is, needless to say, a prime example of ancient, not modern, mathematics.
This was not just a stylistic choice on the part of Scientific American editors. Several of the articles included in the special issue offered a longue durée account explaining contemporary mathematics by reaching back to ancient mathematics. For example, in his article on “Number,” mathematician Philip Davis began with Babylonian mathematics, then moved to negative numbers, complex numbers, and, finally Cantor’s transfinite cardinals (Davis Reference Davis1964). Morris Kline similarly covered a long period in his article on “Geometry.” The history the authors narrate is one of constant change, in which the meaning of both number and geometry is continually under revision, while at the same time remaining remarkably singular by retaining an essential, yet unspecified, quality. History, for them, offered a way to make sense of the present.
In his 1966 The Role of Mathematics in the Rise of Science, Bochner tackled the question head on. The volume begins by posing the question: “what is mathematics?” “What indeed is mathematics?,” Bochner continues, “This question, if asked in earnest, has no answer, not a satisfactory one; only part answers and observations can be attempted” (Bochner Reference Bochner1966, 13). In lieu of an answer, Bochner offered history—starting with the Greeks and moving in fits and starts to the present. Bochner identified abstraction as the dominant feature of mathematical knowledge, noting that while it had its inception with the Greeks, it only took off in the nineteenth century. Modern mathematics, for him, was defined by “untrammeled escalation of abstraction, that is, abstraction from abstraction, abstraction from abstraction from abstraction, and so forth” (Bochner Reference Bochner1966, 18).
Even the French group Bourbaki included historical surveys, at times going all the way back to Babylonian mathematics in their monographs. Moreover, they too used history to answer the question, “what is mathematics.” The answer, not surprisingly, was that mathematics was the study of abstract structures. As Leo Corry has showed, Bourbaki’s historical writing “has been strongly connected with their overall conception of mathematics” (Corry Reference Corry2004, 331). Corry quotes Dieudonné as stating that “today when we look at the evolution of mathematics for the last two centuries, we cannot help seeing that since about 1840 the study of specific mathematical objects has been replaced more and more by the study of mathematical structures” (Corry Reference Corry2004, 332). Such an assertion, Corry demonstrates, is doubtful at best, but the point is not whether Dieudonné’s analysis is accurate or not, but rather the fact that history served as justification for the present.
Mathematicians’ search for some inherent characteristic of mathematics was not just an intellectual quandary. The postwar institutional and funding regime that supported the growth of mathematics at the time put additional pressure on mathematicians to define the boundaries of their field. During a 1966 conference on the education of applied mathematicians, mathematician Lipman Bers, for example, suggested that more historical research is necessary to better direct the future of the field:
Let us stimulate research in the history of modern mathematics … let us try to find “what did really happen.” I think if we do we will find that the traditional picture of problems coming from the outside into mathematics, being solved there and then going back, is exceedingly oversimplified. … The true history of the interplay between applications and pure mathematics is highly interesting and should be studied and taught. (Greenberg Reference Greenberg1967, 315)
Bers’ appeal was not hypothetical. Having recently moved to Columbia University after spending fifteen years as a professor of mathematics at the Courant Institute at NYU, Bers was put in charge of a national effort by the mathematical community to study the state of American mathematics and put forward policy recommendations for federal and military agencies. The final report, which was published in 1968, further elucidated how mathematicians sought to draw boundaries around the “proper” domain of the field.
Bounding mathematics
On the face of it, the Committee on Support of Research in the Mathematical Sciences (COSRIMS) presented the most expansive view of mathematics. The committee included representatives from the various mathematical fields—statistics, probability, computing, applied and pure mathematics—and represented a massive undertaking by the mathematical community. It produced surveys on the state of undergraduate education, graduate education, and employment opportunities, as well as a detailed analysis of national changes in the mathematical curriculum. In addition to these national surveys, which were published independently, the committee established several individual panels to study and produce reports on specific topics. Besides the eleven members of the standing committee, approximately forty-five additional, highly respected mathematicians took part in the work of these panels.Footnote 12
As a national policy document, the report unsurprisingly emphasized the ubiquity of mathematics. Mathematics, the report begins, had long played a role in scientific and technological developments. Yet such an assertion “hardly begins to convey or account for the current explosive penetration of mathematical methods into other disciplines, amounting to a virtual ‘mathematization of culture’” (National Research Council 1968, 3). The use of mathematical techniques is not limited to academic domains. Government, business, and industry, the report continues, are becoming progressively dependent on mathematics and computers to solve problems of resource and time allocation. The message was clear: mathematics was everywhere. The authors proclaimed, “it is no exaggeration to say, therefore, that the fundamental problems of national life depend now, more than ever before, upon the existence and the further growth of the mathematical sciences and upon the continuing activities of able people skilled in their use” (National Research Council 1968, 47).
Almost every aspect of daily life was affected by mathematics. As examples, the authors noted that mathematics was an “absolute necessary condition” for developments in electronics, and that the growth of information theory, network synthesis, and feedback theory was “unthinkable” without mathematics.Footnote 13 They added that telephone and radio communication also depend on mathematics, as well as the transmission of pictures, and the “collection, classification, and transmission of data in general” requires mathematics. If that was not enough, transportation both on the ground and in the air is demonstrated to require mathematics in consideration of traffic control problems. Mathematics, the authors thus proved, was implicated in the life of the nation.Footnote 14
This sweeping conception of mathematics, however, is misleading, for it came with a subtle but crucial change in terminology. The report considered the state of the “mathematical sciences”—not mathematics. This was a new term of art that emerged in the 1960s as a response to the growing use of mathematics across myriad domains. “Mathematics” was no longer an inclusive enough category to describe all the new areas of research that had emerged over the preceding two decades. The “mathematical sciences” was a means by which to reflect the plurality of new areas of research that now laid claim to the mathematical terrain. Rejecting the common division between pure and applied mathematics, the report divided the field into “core mathematics” and the “applied mathematical sciences,” which consisted of four major areas of research: computer science, operation research, statistics, and physical mathematics (classical applied mathematics). The goal of the authors was to offer a unified vision of the field, but in effect the growth of the mathematical sciences only served to cordon off the domain of pure mathematics. Put somewhat differently, as the “mathematical sciences” turned increasingly outward, “mathematics” could safely turn inwards.
This inward move is exemplified by the changes instituted throughout the 1960s, in Mathematical Reviews (MR), the leading reviewing journal of the mathematical community. As the number of mathematical publications ballooned, an ad hoc committee was established in 1962 to study the coverage of the Mathematical Reviews. Their final report stated that “the increased rate of mathematical production causes headaches for MR.” The problem, however, was not just the increase in size. “Of greater impact,” the committee continued, “is the change of character of various fields.”Footnote 15 Symbolic logic, computing, and operation research, the committee noted, had expanded the scope of the Mathematical Reviews. Whereas in the past, the tendency was to be as inclusive as possible, the committee suggested that in the future “only mathematical papers should be reviewed and reviewing should be from a mathematical point of view. The importance of a paper of applications or teaching, and the fame of an author, are irrelevant for MR.”Footnote 16 To ensure prompt coverage and to better serve the mathematical community, coverage, the committee suggested, had to be more selective.
Four years later, as the production of mathematical research continued to grow, the selection for inclusion became even stricter. Starting in 1967, the Mathematical Review followed a coverage policy that specifically sought to exclude “routine applications of known mathematics.”Footnote 17 The effects of this new policy were immediately noticeable. Whereas in 1965 and 1966 the percentage of reviews in the “applied” sections was about 33%, in the last volume of 1967 it dropped to 14%.Footnote 18 Noting the effect of this new policy, the editorial committee for Mathematical Review admitted that, in some cases, making the distinction between pure and applied was quite difficult. Section 93 (Control Theory), they noted, “always contained quite a few papers in ‘pure’ mathematics.” In conclusion, they observed that “none of the dividing lines are sharp, but the net effect is discernible in the general trend of the figures: a larger total number of reviews, a smaller proportion of applied mathematics, very little of what could be called physics.”Footnote 19 Acknowledging that any attempt to distinguish pure from applied was by definition artificial, mathematicians were nonetheless drawing new boundaries around their discipline. In the case of the Mathematical Reviews this was done in part due to the unprecedented expansion in the production of research papers, but these boundaries were also being marked into the field’s institutional formation, with the rise of new departments in statistics, computer science, and operation research, independent from the traditional mathematical departments.
In 1970, mathematician Saunders MacLane was ready to dispense altogether with the new terminology. In a memorandum, which he circulated among a small number of mathematicians, MacLane suggested that a new organization representing mathematicians’ demands was necessary. “I submit that there is a real need for a strong mathematical posture on questions of national science policy and that this need will grow greater with the shortage of funds and the inevitable wider application of mathematical methods.” MacLane held that existing organizations representing mathematics on the national level were broken, and urged his colleagues to form a new national organization. One of the “essential” conditions for such an organization, he added, was that “it is concerned with mathematics (which has existed for millennia) and not with that novelty ‘mathematical sciences.’”Footnote 20 It is against this background that historians of mathematics and historically inclined mathematicians found themselves debating one another in the 1970s. Their disagreement was less about the applicability of social and cultural history to mathematics, but about what mathematics was. It is in reaction to the proliferation of mathematical applications that many American mathematicians sought to draw borders around what constituted “proper” mathematics.
A history of mathematics
By the early 1970s, mathematicians were no longer the only ones interested in this history of mathematics. As the history of science began professionalizing as an academic discipline, the history of mathematics emerged as a distinct subfield. No longer the sole purview of elder mathematicians, papers and dissertations on the history of mathematics began to be published by young scholars trained in the history of science and historical methods more broadly. First, however, they had to contend with the mathematicians. In 1974, mathematicians and historians of mathematics convened at a workshop on the evolution of modern mathematics, hosted under the auspices of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. The workshop was organized by a committee that included Garrett Birkhoff (chair), I. B. Cohen, Thomas Hawkins, Kenneth May, and Felix Browder. This membership alone demonstrates the changing nature of the history of mathematics as a recognizable academic field in its own right. Birkhoff and Browder were celebrated mathematicians, May was a mathematician turned historian, and Hawkins was a younger historian of mathematics. The workshop brought together more than forty scholars interested in the history of modern mathematics. It included, among others, the celebrated mathematicians Alan Baker, Jean Dieudonné, Churchill Eisenhart, and Antoni Zygmund, as well as mathematically trained historians Morris Kline and Carl Boyer, and historians William Aspray, Michael Crowe, Ivor Grattan-Guinness, Judith Grabiner, and Frederick Gregory.
Garret Birkhoff explained that its goal was “to direct into constructive channels the rising tide of interest on the part of mathematicians in the history and philosophy of their subject” (Birkhoff and Cohen Reference Birkhof and Cohen1975). Indeed, the mathematicians outnumbered the historians by nearly three to one. The conference marks an important juncture point in the professionalization of the history of mathematics in the United States, not because it gave rise to a new research tradition, but because it symbolizes the difficult disciplinary position in which American historians of mathematics found themselves in the early 1970s. By the mid-1970s, the history of science was expanding as an academic profession, and Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions was more than a decade old. Historians of mathematics had to find their place among mathematicians, who were deeply invested in their own history.
This tension between the two groups was palpable throughout the conference. In his opening speech, I. B. Cohen reported that the historians had met the previous night to discuss their objectives for the workshop.Footnote 21 Consequently, the historians’ two motivating questions were: first, to what degree should the presentation of historical material depend on the intended audience? and second, what is the relation of history of mathematics “not only to mathematics but to general history and the history of science?”Footnote 22 The latter of the two was the perennial question occupying historians of mathematics throughout the decade and, as the workshop makes evident, historians were unwilling to break ties with mathematicians. In a nod of deference to the mathematicians in the audience, Cohen noted, for example, that all of the historians in attendance agreed that active mathematicians brought to the study of history “a special kind of insight that goes beyond the power of the historians.”Footnote 23 Collaboration with mathematicians was especially necessary for studying recent history, for which the historian’s mathematical knowledge might be lacking. The problem was that aligning themselves with mathematicians implied alienating themselves from historians of science. Trying to speak to both mathematicians and historians of science partially explains the separation of the history of mathematics from the history of science.
The publication of Historia Mathematica in 1974 similarly points to the growing interest in the history of mathematics at the time and the difficult disciplinary position it presented. In the second issue of the journal, the editor of the journal Kenneth May published an article titled, “Should we be Mathematicians, Historians of Science, Historians, or Generalists?” (May Reference May1974). The answer, according to May, was all of the above. May insisted that every center for the history of science (of which there were by then a few) must include a historian of mathematics, but recognized that the most common and obvious place for historians of mathematics was within the mathematical community. “From the beginning, history of mathematics has been a part of mathematical activity, and its practitioners a part of the mathematical community” (May Reference May1974). Most historians of mathematics, May added, earn their living as part of the mathematical community, which is also their main audience. “The mathematicians have a real need for the historians of mathematics, especially in periods like the present, when there is considerable disarray over matter of science policy” (May Reference May1974).
May’s article came as a response to the academic job crisis of the early 1970s. The history of mathematics, he believed, could at the very least help direct educational programs. By arguing that historians of mathematics should be all of the above (historians, generalists, etc.), May was hoping to point towards additional academic positions that young PhDs might assume. However, such a multifaceted definition of what the history of mathematics entailed came with its own difficulties.
May, who was one of the participants in the conference, clearly recognized the tension between the groups. He began his talk by chastising mathematicians for being willing to forgive the mistakes of their colleagues but having zero tolerance for those of non-mathematicians: “mathematicians forgive a good mathematician for his blunders, but they tend to be outraged by the clumsy intrusions of outsiders” (May Reference May1975, 453). The historians, however, were not blameless. “The historian finds hilarious such naïve historical mistakes as assuming that words have fixed meanings or that a brilliant mathematician of past centuries must have understood a concept or had a proof because these would be evident to lesser lights today” (ibid.). The best history, May insisted, was one that tried to be sensitive to both the mathematics and the history. This, however, was easier said than done.
After Thomas Hawkins’ talk, Morris Kline felt the need to defend the historians in the audience. “They came today, not to tell us the history of mathematics, but to discuss the problems of history” (Hawkins Reference Hawkins1975, 565). Commenting that the mathematicians’ talks were very detailed, he added, “the purpose of this meeting was not so much to get the history down from the mathematicians, who would be the best source, but rather to discuss more the problems of how we can all co-operate” (ibid., 565–66). Birkhoff reiterated Kline’s point, but with a caveat, “discussion between mathematicians and historians of mathematics should be related to specific examples, with a minimum of philosophical superstructure” (ibid., 566). Birkhoff’s advice came as response to the constant references throughout the workshop to the work of Kuhn. Despite mathematicians’ general aversion to the topic, the historians in the group questioned again and again the appropriateness of Kuhn’s ideas to the history of mathematics.
In particular, they questioned whether revolutions happened in mathematics. M. J. Crowe, one of the young historians who presented at the conference, took the most decisive position, stating as a “law” that “revolutions never occur in mathematics” (Crowe Reference Crowe1975). Crowe argued that for an event to count as a revolution something needed to be discarded. However, a mathematical theorem, once proven, stands forever. A year after the conference, Crowe’s paper, along with the rest of the proceedings, was published in Historia Mathematica. After reading the paper, Herbert Mehrtens submitted “T.S. Kuhn’s Theories and Mathematics: A Discussion Paper on the ‘New Historiography’ of Mathematics” to the journal. In his paper, Crowe explained that in formulating his “law,” the preposition “in” was crucial. Revolution, he explained, may occur in mathematical nomenclature, symbolism, metamathematics, and methodology, but not in mathematics. In addition to his analysis of Kuhn’s ideas, Mehrtens’ response also homed in on Crowe’s use of the preposition “in”. As Mehrtens explained, only by cordoning off an aspect of mathematics that is distinct from nomenclature, symbolism, metamathematics, methodology, and historiography was Crowe able to argue that revolutions never occurred in mathematics. But what exactly, he asked, was this part of mathematics? What did it consist of? What was the “content” or “substance” of mathematics which supposedly remained the same despite great transformations? “There is a danger,” he added, “for the historian of mathematics in this preposition in” (Mehrtens Reference Mehrtens1976, 301–2). By adopting the distinction between that which is in mathematics and that which is not, historians of mathematics inadvertently adopt mathematicians’ definition of what should and should not belong in the history of mathematics. I would add that that they are also in danger of following mathematicians’ own definitions of its boundaries.
Wonderful, insightful, and rich books in the history of mathematics have been written since the 1970s, but these works always feel like an exception rather than the rule. A few authors have managed to please both the mathematicians and the historians of science, but their work stands out. This is why, despite all of these works, historians of mathematics periodically feel compelled to bemoan that history of mathematics is tuned to a minor key compared to the history of science. At stake, I believe, is not the old internalist-externalist debate, but the fact that historians of mathematics have followed mathematicians too closely in deciding what counts as the history of mathematics. Acknowledging that the image of mathematics as an abstract and insular field of study is one which mathematicians constructed not only because of intellectual convictions, but also due to social and political concerns, should give historians of mathematics freedom to write against the grain. Accepting the notion that “proper” mathematics is independent of its applications risks accepting the essentialized conception of the field that mathematicians have advanced. What if historians of mathematics followed the COSRIMS report, not in cordoning off mathematics, but in recognizing that such divisions are up to us to make? The history of invariant theory is obviously part of the history of mathematics, but what about the history of information theory or axiomatics? Postwar mathematicians spent much time and energy demarcating mathematics. Historians, like mathematicians, must decide what mathematics is before they can agree on what comprises the history of mathematics. Perhaps the field has been flourishing all along.Footnote 24
Alma Steingart, an assistant professor in the Department of History at Columbia University, researches the interplay between American politics and mathematical rationalities. Professor Steingart’s current project, Accountable Democracy, examines how mathematical thought and computing technologies impacted electoral politics in the United States in the twentieth century. It follows on her first book, Axiomatics: Mathematical Thought and High Modernism (2023). Steingart’s work has appeared in Social Studies of Science, Grey Room, and the Los Angeles Review of Books. Her work is supported by a CAREER Award from the National Science Foundation.