Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T02:09:16.684Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Practice, Reason, Context: The Dialogue Between Theory and Experiment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 September 2008

Timothy Lenoir
Affiliation:
Department of HistoryProgram in History of Science, Stanford University

Extract

Experiment, instrumentation, and procedures of measurement, the body of practices and technologies forming the technical culture of science, have received at most a cameo appearance in most histories. For the history of science is almost always written as the history of theory. Of course, the interpretation of science as dominated by theory was the main pillar of the critique, launched by Kuhn, Quine, Hanson, Feyerabend, and others, of the positivist and logical empiricist traditions in the philosophy of science. Against Carnap, Hempel, Nagel, and Popper, who accorded observation reports an independent status either as a source of inductive support or as a basis for the falsification of scientific theories, Hanson and Kuhn emphasized the theory-ladenness of observation. They made this central point – that all observation is shaped by reference to theory – the cornerstone of a full-blown philosophy of science by buttressing it with two additional lines of argument: First, theories are always underdetermined by the data, several theories being compatible with the same set of data. Hence, choice between theories is never a matter of empirical support, but always turns around conceptual issues. Second, statements derived from theory never confront nature alone; they are always clothed in a web of interrelated beliefs. Thus, theories, their associated observation languages, and the entire technical culture they support must be accepted or rejected as wholes.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bourdieu, Pierre, 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy, 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Douglas, Mary, 1975. Implicit Meanings: Essays in Anthropology. London: Rout ledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter, 1987. How Experiments End. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian, 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holmes, Frederic L., 1985. Lavoisier and the Chemistry of Life: An Exploration of Scientific Creativity. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
Lenoir, Timothy, 1986. “Models and Instruments in the Development of Electrophysiology, 1845–1912,” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 17: 154.Google Scholar
Pickering, Andrew, 1984. Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Pickering, Andrew 1987. “Essay Review. Forms of Life: Science, Contingency and Harry Collins,” British Journal for the History of Science. 20: 213–21.Google Scholar
Pierce, S., 1960. “Some Consequences of Four Incapacities,” in Charles Sanders Pierce. Collected Papers, 6 vols., ed. Hartshorne, Charles and Weiss, Paul, 5: 156–89. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven and Schaffer, Simon, 1985. Leviathan and the Air Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wise, M. Norton and Smith, Crosbie, 1986. “Measurement, Work, and Industry in Lord Kelvin's Britain,” Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences. 17: 147–73.Google Scholar
– forthcoming. Energy and Empire: William Thomson, Lord Kelvin, 18281907. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Woolgar, S. and , B. Latour, 1986. Laboratory Life. The Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar