Article contents
The Mental States of Persons and their Brains
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 07 July 2015
Abstract
Cognitive neuroscientists frequently talk about the brain representing the world. Some philosophers claim that this is a confusion. This paper argues that there is no confusion, and outlines one thing that ‘the brain represents the world’ might mean, using the notion of a model derived from the philosophy of science. This description is then extended to make apply to propositional attitude attributions. A number of problems about propositional attitude attributions can be solved or dissolved by treating propositional attitudes as models.
- Type
- Papers
- Information
- Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements , Volume 76: Mind, Self and Person , May 2015 , pp. 253 - 270
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2015
References
1 Frith, Chris, Making Up the Mind (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell 2007),Google Scholar 128.
2 See Bennett, M.R. and Hacker, P.M.S., Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2003).Google Scholar
3 Ibid., 72.
4 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1953)Google Scholar, §281.
5 M.K. Bennett and P.M.S. Hacker, Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience, 3.
6 Stephen Mulhall, Stanton lectures 2014, University of Cambridge (unpublished).
7 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, §67.
8 Dennett, Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1969)Google Scholar 95.
9 Ibid., 95.
10 Dennett, Daniel C., ‘Philosophy as Naive Anthropology: Comment on Bennett and Hacker’ in Neuroscience and Philosophy (New York: Columbia University Press, 2007), 87–9.Google Scholar
11 Fodor, Jerry A., The Language of Thought (Hassocks: Harvester 1975)Google Scholar. For a critical overview, see Schneider, Susan, The Language of Thought (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 Fodor, Jerry A., LOT2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).Google Scholar
13 Frances Egan, http://www.3ammagazine.com/3am/meaning-as-gloss/.
14 Suppes, Patrick, ‘A Comparison of the Meaning and Uses of Models in Mathematics and the Empirical Sciences’ Synthese 12 (1960), 287–301 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Van Fraassen, Bas, The Scientific Image (Oxford Oxford University Press, 1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
15 See e.g., Giere, Ronald N., ‘Using Models to Represent Reality’ in Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery, (ed.) Magnani, L., Nersessian, N. J., and Thagard, P. (New York: Kluwer/Plenum, 1999), 41–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
16 See Stephen Downes, ‘The Importance of Models in Theorizing: a Deflationary Semantic View’ in Hull D, Forbes M, Okruhlik K (eds) PSA 1992, vol. 1. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing (1992), 142–153; and Thomson-Jones, Martin ‘Models and the Semantic View’ Philosophy of Science 73 (2006), 524–535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
17 Godfrey-Smith, Peter ‘The Strategy of Model-Based Science’ Biology and Philosophy 21 (2006), 725–740 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; 733.
18 See Downes, ‘The Importance of Models in Theorizing: a Deflationary Semantic View’, 145–6.
19 ‘Who is a Modeler?’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2007), 207–233 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; 208.
20 See Giere, ‘Using Models to Represent Reality’.
21 See Crane, Tim, The Mechanical Mind (London: Routledge, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar chapter 4, for an exposition of this argument.
22 For this distinction, see Searle, John R., Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
23 For defences of the latter thesis, see John Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind, and Galen Strawson, Mental Reality.
24 See Davidson, Donald, ‘Mental Events’ in Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982)Google Scholar. In chapter 4 of The Objects of Thought (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2013)Google Scholar I offer a critique of propositionalism which is independent of the present paper.
25 Fodor, Jerry A., ‘Propositional Attitudes’ The Monist 61 (1978) 501–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
26 Field, Hartry, ‘Mental Representation’ Erkenntnis 13 (1978) 9–61 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 10.
27 Cummins, Robert, Meaning and Mental Representation (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989)Google Scholar, 144.
28 For a recent contribution to this debate see King, Jeffrey C., The Nature and Structure of Content (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
29 Rumfitt, Ian, ‘Truth and Meaning’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 88 (2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, footnote 6.
30 Malcolm, Norman, ‘Thoughtless Brutes’ Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 46 (1973), 5–20 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; cf. Davidson, Donald, ‘Thought and Talk’ in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984).Google Scholar
31 See in particular, ‘Beyond Belief’.
32 Thanks to Ali Boyle, Dan Brigham, Katalin Farkas, Anthony O'Hear and Michael Weisberg for discussion, to members of the audience at the Royal Institute of Philosophy for helpful comments at the RIP meeting in February 2014, and to Stephen Mulhall for permitting me to quote from his unpublished work. An earlier version of this talk was given at the University of London's Institute of Philosophy in June 2012, at a workshop on Dennett's personal/sub-personal distinction; thanks to Dan Dennett for his comments on that occasion.
- 17
- Cited by