Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T15:28:52.113Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

SUPPORT FOR GEOMETRIC POOLING

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 October 2020

JEAN BACCELLI
Affiliation:
MCMP, LMU MUNICH MÜNCHEN, GERMANY E-mail: [email protected]
RUSH T. STEWART*
Affiliation:
MCMP, LMU MUNICH MÜNCHEN, GERMANY E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Supra-Bayesianism is the Bayesian response to learning the opinions of others. Probability pooling constitutes an alternative response. One natural question is whether there are cases where probability pooling gives the supra-Bayesian result. This has been called the problem of Bayes-compatibility for pooling functions. It is known that in a common prior setting, under standard assumptions, linear pooling cannot be nontrivially Bayes-compatible. We show by contrast that geometric pooling can be nontrivially Bayes-compatible. Indeed, we show that, under certain assumptions, geometric and Bayes-compatible pooling are equivalent. Granting supra-Bayesianism its usual normative status, one upshot of our study is thus that, in a certain class of epistemic contexts, geometric pooling enjoys a normative advantage over linear pooling as a social learning mechanism. We discuss the philosophical ramifications of this advantage, which we show to be robust to variations in our statement of the Bayes-compatibility problem.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Aumann, R. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. The Annals of Statistics4(6), 12361239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, J., Mellers, B., Tetlock, P., Stone, E., & Ungar, L. (2014). Two reasons to make aggregated probability forecasts more extreme. Decision Analysis11(2), 133145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonanno, G., & Nehring, K. (1997). Agreeing to Disagree: A Survey. U.C.-Davis Department of Economics Working Paper No. 97-18.Google Scholar
Bonnay, D., & Cozic, M. (2018). Weighted averaging, Jeffrey conditioning and invariance. Theory and Decision85(1), 2139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonnay, D., & Cozic, M. (2019). Weighted averaging and Bayesian conditioning. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. (2006). Taking advantage of difference in opinion. Episteme3(3), 141155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, R. (2007). Reaching a consensus. Social Choice and Welfare29(4), 609632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, R. (2018). Learning from others: Conditioning versus averaging. Theory and Decision85(1), 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. (1947). On the application of inductive logic. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research8(1), 133148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (2009). Disagreement as evidence: The epistemology of controversy. Philosophy Compass4(5), 756767.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawid, P., DeGroot, M., & Mortera, J. (1995). Coherent combination of experts' opinions. Test4(2), 263313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawid, P., & Mortera, J. (2020). Resolving some contradictions in the theory of linear opinion pools. Theory and Decision88, 453456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeGroot, M. (1974). Reaching a consensus. Journal of the American Statistical Association69(345), 118121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. (2010). Bayesian group belief. Social Choice and Welfare , 35(4), 595626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. (2017). A theory of Bayesian groups. Noûs, 53(3), 708736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F., & List, C. (2016). Probabilistic opinion pooling. In Hájek, A., and Hitchcock, C., editors. Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, pp. 519541.Google Scholar
Easwaran, K., Fenton-Glynn, L., Hitchcock, C., & Velasco, J. (2016). Updating on the credences of others: Disagreement, agreement, and synergy. PhilosophersImprint 16(11), 139.Google Scholar
Elga, A. (2007). Reflection and disagreement. Noûs41(3), 478502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
French, S. (1985). Group consensus probability distributions: A critical survey. In Bernardo, J., DeGroot, M., Lindley, D., and Smith, A., editors. Bayesian Statistics, Vol. 2, Amsterdam, Netherlands: North Holland Publishing, pp. 183201.Google Scholar
French, S. (1986). Calibration and the expert problem. Management Science32(3), 315321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaifman, H. (1988). A theory of higher order probabilities. In Skyrms, B., and Harper, W., editors. Causation, Chance and Credence. New York, NY: Springer, pp. 191219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geanakoplos, J., & Polemarchakis, H. (1982). We can't disagree forever. Journal of Economic Theory28(1), 192200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Genest, C. (1984). Pooling operators with the marginalization property. Canadian Journal of Statistics12(2), 153163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Genest, C., McConway, K., & Schervish, M. (1986). Characterization of externally bayesian pooling operators. The Annals of Statistics14(3), 487501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Genest, C., & Schervish, M. (1985). Modeling expert judgments for Bayesian updating. The Annals of Statistics, 13(3), 11981212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Genest, C., & Zidek, J. (1986). Combining probability distributions: A critique and an annotated bibliography. Statistical Science1(1), 114135.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research63(1), 85110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Golub, B. and Jackson, M. (2010). Naive learning in social networks and the wisdom of crowds. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics2(1), 112–49.Google Scholar
Golub, B., & Sadler, E. (2016). Learning in social networks. In Bramoull, Y., Galeotti, A., and Rogers, B., editors. The Oxford Handbook of the Economics of Networks. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, pp. 594–542.Google Scholar
Good, I. (1967). On the principle of total evidence. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science17(4), 319321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (2004). Subjective Probability: The Real Thing. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K., & Wagner, C. (1981). Rational Consensus in Science and Society: A Philosophical and Mathematical Study. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. (1977). Direct inference. The Journal of Philosophy74(1), 529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindley, D. (1982a). The Bayesian approach to statistics. In Tiago de Oliveira, J., and Epstein, B., editors. Some Recent Advances in Statistics. New York, NY: Academic Press, pp. 6587.Google Scholar
Lindley, D. (1982b). The improvement of probability judgements. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society: Series A145(1), 117126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McConway, K. (1981). Marginalization and linear opinion pools. Journal of the American Statistical Association76(374), 410414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mongin, P. (1995). Consistent Bayesian aggregation. Journal of Economic Theory, 66(2), 313351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, P. (1974). Decision analysis expert use. Management Science20(9), 12331241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, S. (1995). The common prior assumption in economic theory. Economics & Philosophy11(2), 227253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1971, originally published in 1949). The Theory of Probability (second edition). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Romeijn, J.-W. (2019a). An Interpretation of Weights in Linear Opinion Pooling.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Romeijn, J.-W. (2019b). Extremizing: The Rationality of Audacious Forecasting. Google Scholar
Romeijn, J.-W., & Roy, O. (2018). All agreed: Aumann meets DeGroot. Theory and Decision85(1), 4160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, J. S., Hawthorne, J., & Buchak, L. (2015). Groupthink. Philosophical Studies , 172(5), 12871309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, K. (2012). Testimony as evidence: More problems for linear pooling. Journal of Philosophical Logic41(6), 983999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tetlock, P., & Gardner, D. (2016). Superforecasting: The Art and Science of Prediction. New York, NY: Penguin.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1984). Belief and the will. The Journal of Philosophy81(5), 235256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar