Introduction
Contemporary analytic treatments of meaning in life in the English-speaking world have largely proceeded from the atheistic and naturalistic assumptions common to the sciences. But would it make a (meaningful) difference if God actually existed? Well, as this article demonstrates, it depends on what is meant by ‘God’. With the recent publication of Seachris and Goetz's God and Meaning (Reference Seachris and Goetz2016), T. J. Mawson's God and the Meanings of Life (Reference Mawson2016), and Thaddeus Metz's God, Soul and the Meaning of Life (Reference Metz2019), more analytic philosophers might be drawn to (re)examining what role, if any, God might play in life's meaning. This should be welcomed by those in the field of meaning in life, but it is not a trivial fact that the extant treatments of the issue generally limit their focus to an understanding of ‘God’ that is derived from the Abrahamic faiths. Broadening the discussion to include other salient concepts of ‘God’ might offer valuable insights.
I examine a concept of ‘God’ most clearly described in the Advaita Vedānta Footnote 1 school of Indian philosophy, and offer a preliminary case for the claim that those activities we apprehend as ‘meaningful’ are so in relation to how closely they bring us towards the goal of realizing (and eventually transcending) the cosmic meaning-making structure of this ‘God’. My discussion will require introducing the field to the outlines of a Dharmic theory of meaning, a key part of which may be called ‘meaning-as-remembering’ – because, as I discuss, the ‘God’ of Advaita Vedānta is . . . you.
The concept of God found in Advaita Vedānta has been discussed in great depth in various schools of Eastern philosophy over the course of millennia, and is familiar to no less than billions of individuals. On this view, ‘God’ is (Nirguna) Brahman: the (attributeless) Absolute, the inscrutable ground of Being. Crucially, the world as we know it is Brahman manifested as Ātman: the all-pervading ‘Self’ common to all beings. In other words, Brahman is not ontologically distinct from the world – let alone any individual person, mistakenly apprehending him- or herself as an ontologically distinct entity. In short: you are Brahman, and the aim of Advaitic practice is to realize this.
I should clarify that although there are six major orthodox schools of Indian philosophy, I limit my discussion to Vedānta, and, more specifically, its most famous sub-school: Advaita Vedānta.Footnote 2 Note that I do not attempt to prove that Advaita Vedānta is true; instead, I aim only to show that the view is philosophically interesting in a manner that, I hope, will capture the attention of the field – even if only as an ‘intuition pump’ (see Dennett Reference Dennett2013).
I should further clarify my strategy here, and the overall aim of this article. For those analytic philosophers of meaning who are interested in exploring theistic approaches to meaning, a natural place to start their investigations would be at the intersection of the fields of meaning in life and the philosophy of religion. There, they will encounter the fascinating, bourgeoning discussion on the axiology of theism (which I draw upon here). But they will not yet find there the extraordinary Indian account of ‘God’ as Brahman; thus, what Indian philosophy can contribute to understanding life's meaning may continue to be overlooked. I hope this article will help end this long-standing neglect by analytic philosophers of meaning by laying the groundwork for understanding Brahman's possible impact upon their investigations. (For reasons of space, a more direct focus on Brahman's impact upon the axiology of theism discussion will be undertaken in future work.) This overall aim is important because, if one is interested in the possible role God could play in life's meaning, one really ought to pay close attention to how ‘God’ is defined.
This article is divided into three major sections. First, I discuss how God features in the analytic Anglo-American-Australasian literature on meaningfulness. Second, I discuss how ‘God’ is understood in the non-dual/non-theistic (as I defend it) philosophical system of Advaita Vedānta, appealing to contemporary trends in metaphysics (viz. Perennialism and cosmopsychism) to guide readers. Here, I advance the broad outlines of an underexploredFootnote 3 theory of meaning derived from Advaita Vedānta, which I shall call the Dharmic theory of meaning. Third, I suggest how views like Advaita Vedānta could advance analytic discussions of meaning in life by challenging certain long-standing assumptions.
God in the contemporary meaning in life tradition
This section offers a brief overview of how God features in the analytic Anglo-American-Australasian literature on meaningfulness. I will assume that readers are familiar with the way ‘meaning’ (and related terms like ‘meaningfulness’ and ‘meaning in life’) is usually understood in the literature, namely as an ultimately non-instrumental value that is conceptually distinct from happiness or welfare in general.Footnote 4 Due to space constraints, I do not aim at a comprehensive overview, instead limiting myself here to a question that has recently gained attention at the intersection of the fields of philosophy of religion and meaning in life, namely the axiological question of how God's existence would or does matter.Footnote 5
Setting aside for now the esoteric religious traditions, ‘God’ in the exoteric Abrahamic faithsFootnote 6 is traditionally understood as the creator and sustainer of the universe – a perfect being with the classical divine attributes of omnipotence, omniscience, omnipresence, etc. Following the ontological argument offered by Anselm in the Proslogion (1077–1078), God in these faiths is most usually defined as ‘that than which no greater can be thought’. To be clear, I am referring here to the God of ‘classical’ or ‘traditional theology’. Analytic philosophers of meaning who are interested in how God might impact upon life's meaning are likely to encounter this understanding of God. Limitations of space prevent me from offering an in-depth exploration of this well-known understanding of God, but at least two aspects of it should be kept in mind for our purposes here.
First, it is, on the face of it, dualistic. While some sort of eventual communion with God may be possible, our flesh-bound relationship to Him is thought to be characterized by a fundamental ontological separateness.Footnote 7 Second, the divine attributes of omnipotence, etc. – and even the belief that He is perfect – are notably at odds with another very influential understanding of the Absolute, as I will discuss later.Footnote 8
In approaching the aforementioned axiological question, it will be useful to begin by considering the divide between supernaturalists and naturalists.Footnote 9 Historically, the former believed that meaning requires something beyond the purely physical – namely, a meaning-conferring spiritual realm. The latter denied that the physical realm necessarily would lack meaning in this way – in other words, meaning still could be possible without the spiritual. Contemporary moderate supernaturalist positions offer a qualified view in which maximal meaning would not be possible without the spiritual (see Williams Reference Williams2020). Their naturalist opponents, on the other hand, argue that the existence of the spiritual may detract from the meaning available to us (see, for example, Metz Reference Metz2021). As I discuss shortly, such views can be further refined.
The question of whether we should want God to exist first gained serious analytic attention through the work of Guy Kahane (Reference Kahane2011), with a refined taxonomy of possible positions on the goodness of God's existence, or non-existence, emerging in the work of Klaas J. Kraay.Footnote 10 I focus on the latter's taxonomy, using it to guide the discussion in the rest of the article. Kraay suggests that there are a number ofFootnote 11 combinations of existential (i.e. positions on whether or not God exists) and axiological positions (i.e. views on what difference God's existence would or does make). Only four will concern us here: theistic pro-theism, atheistic pro-theism, theistic anti-theism, and atheistic pro-theism. I discuss these in turn, setting aside agnosticism, neutralism, and quietism.Footnote 12
On the axiological axis, pro-theism is the view, roughly, that God's existence would make, or does make, things better than if He did not exist. And anti-theism is the view, roughly, that His existence would (or does) make things worse. Let us bring together the axiological and the existential, and consider rough definitions of the four combinations mentioned above:
(a) theistic pro-theism: God exists, and things are better for it.
(b) atheistic pro-theism: God does not exist, but things would be better if He did.
(c) theistic anti-theism: God exists, but things would be better if He did not.
(d) atheistic anti-theism: God does not exist, and things are better for it.
Kraay (Reference Kraay and Kraay2018, 2) briefly acknowledges that alternative concepts of God exist, but quite understandably designs this detailed taxonomy of the axiology of theism with ‘the enormously influential and important’ (Kraay Reference Kraay and Kraay2018, 2) God of the exoteric Abraham traditions in mind. Let us grant him that those who favour this model of God can fit their views on the axiological question somewhere in this taxonomy. Analytic philosophers of religion and meaning may nevertheless find it interesting that the ‘God’ of one of the most influential non-Abrahamic traditions does not fit neatly into this taxonomy.Footnote 13 Specifically, Advaita Vedānta is a non-dual/non-theistic philosophy that nonetheless has immensely important things to offer vis-à-vis the axiological question, and thus the question of ‘God's’ possible role in life's meaningfulness. I attempt to introduce the field to this area of exploration in the next section by briefly discussing how ‘God’ is understood in Advaita Vedānta.
‘God’ in Advaita Vedānta
In this section, I discuss some salient aspects of how ‘God’ is understood in Advaita Vedānta. I cannot attempt a comprehensive overview, so I instead offer a summary of the aspects of the view that are most relevant to the present article. Further, I do not need to present a defence of the view here; I aim only to show that it is philosophically valuable to the field of meaning in life.
As mentioned, the Advaitin concept of ‘God’ – in contrast to the God of the exoteric Abrahamic traditions – is non-dual, and is arguably best understood as non-theistic. The central conclusion of Advaita Vedānta is that there is oneFootnote 14 cosmological Absolute – Brahman (i.e. ‘God’, for our purposes) – and ‘we’ are ‘It’. Understanding the full import of this for the field will also require a brief discussion of the Dharma – understood here as the intelligible, meaning-conferring cosmic moral order.
Advaita Vedānta can be viewed as a synthesis of various schools of classical Indian philosophy, including an adaptation of the cosmological framework of Sāṃkhya (Easwaran Reference Easwaran1985, 21–30). ‘Advaita’ means ‘non-dual’, and ‘Vedānta’ can be understood as ‘the end of the Vedas’, the ancient Indian scriptures. Vedānta claims to offer the final word on (i.e. ānta: ‘the final end of’) the teachings of the philosophical component of these scriptures, the Upaniṣads. Advaita Vedānta is the non-dual interpretation of these teachings,Footnote 15 and is prominently associated with its heavily influential eighth-century ce synthesizer and promoter, Ādi Śaṅkara. It is ‘non-dual’ because it argues that even though we each experience the world from our distinct perspectives, we and all such perceivers are the same perceiver, Ātman (‘Self’), encountering the world through manifold sites.Footnote 16 Further, this same Ātman is Brahman: the Absolute – namely, ‘God’. This conclusion is encapsulated in the famous four ‘Great Sayings’ (Mahāvākyas) of the Upaniṣads, among them, ‘tat tvam asi’: ‘that thou art’ – that is, you are Brahman.Footnote 17 Thus, the ultimate aim of the philosophy and practice of Advaita Vedānta is to realize oneself as Brahman.
Right away, there is a lot to unpack here. For one, there is of course the unintuitiveness of the view. Our ordinary experience is that of being distinct, embodied individuals, separate from others and the world in some axiomatic sense. Further, those of us with strong theistic orientations may experience a painful separateness from God, and a yearning to be reunited with Him. For the Advaitin, while such experiences and desires are understandable, it is ultimately the consequence of avidyā: ignorance of the ultimate nature of reality – that is, one's true nature as Brahman.
Indeed, ignorance is a vital concept for Advaita Vedānta: it is the key to breaking through the persistent illusion of both the experience of a ‘self’ and an external world of pluralities. Nature (Prakṛti), and one's individual sense of self in it,Footnote 18 should not be mistaken for the cosmic ‘witness consciousness’ (Puruṣa) of Brahman.Footnote 19 For the world is like the dream of Brahman, as I discuss shortly. In Advaita Vedānta, ‘God’ (Brahman) is at once the ‘manifested’ universe, and the ‘Unmanifested’ (Avyakta), transcendent Absolute. Once we sufficiently remove ignorance and begin to see through the grand cosmic conjuring (Māyā) of the world, or so the dialectic goes, we come to realize that the world is an illusory manifestation of our Real, transcendent Self.Footnote 20
Of course, it is still not clear from the above how the cosmology of Advaita Vedānta can get us to a conclusion about God's existence (let alone the axiological question of His goodness). That is to say, it is not clear how ‘Brahman’ can be understood as even roughly synonymous with the ‘God’ of the exoteric Abrahamic traditions, or – even if It could – how we (in our human forms) could gain any direction or comfort from this sort of ‘God’. This subversion of theistic expectations is in fact one of the most notable aspects of Advaita Vedānta.
While the Abrahamic traditions may encourage seeking God's grace, say, to overcome the sufferings of life, and to ultimately bridge the distance between us and Him, no such strategy is available to the Advaitin; for him, self-effort is indispensable.Footnote 21 Though there may be myriad deities in exoteric Hinduism that the spiritual aspirant may focus on to better channel his efforts towards dispelling ignorance (as avidyā), even these deities eventually must be recognized as part of the grand illusion of the world of plurality. Even Īshvara – roughly, ‘the personal aspect of the impersonal Brahman’ (Sharma Reference Sharma1987, 280), and the only ‘God’ the limited human mind of even the as-yet-unenlightened Advaitin can apprehend – is yet another aspect of Māyā. The figure of the Guru, too – the enlightened dispeller of darkness (see Vasudev Reference Vasudev2016, x) – can only guide the spiritual aspirant to the edge of awakening; he alone must make the leap.
But, the Advaitin counsels, this is not the bleak, forsaken conclusion it may initially seem, for we are not leaping into a nihilistic abyss; on the contrary, it is claimed that shedding our many layers of ignorance will move us towards the Ultimate source of meaning, and then the transcending of meaning itself, as we realize that meaning, too, is an illusory aspect of Māyā. To invoke a famous analogy: just as we awaken from sleep to discover that we were dreaming, awakening in the Advaitin sense is ‘waking up’ from the dream of this changing and ultimately unreal realityFootnote 22 (Miṭhyā) to realize that one is the cosmic dreamer, Brahman. I expand upon this specific movement of meaning in the next section. For now, it is important to remember that Advaita Vedānta appeals to the ancient idea of Dharma, which, recall, we will understand here as the intelligible, meaning-conferring cosmic moral order.
Brahman is ultimately without attributes (Nirguna), complete (Purnam),Footnote 23 and Unmanifested (Avyakta). Yet ‘we’ find ourselves in an ordered cosmosFootnote 24 – ‘the dream of Brahman’, as it were – that has attributes, broadly understood: space, time, physical laws, individual blades of grass, etc. To the Advaitin, this cosmos of plurality is ‘in’ Brahman. To say it with greater refinement, the ordered cosmos is Brahman in his manifested form.
The classical Indian philosophical term for this order was originally Ṛta, with Dharma later becoming more common.Footnote 25 The ancient Indian philosophersFootnote 26 advised that the Dharma is intelligible in ways that can be discovered – as the universe's physical laws, most conspicuously. But the deeper dimensions of its structure, they advised, must be apprehended using such subtle tools as deep meditative states. These philosophers came to believe that the Dharma has meaning-conferring, moral dimensions to it as well. And, they argued, it is through sufficiently respecting all dimensions of the Dharma that one can truly flourish as a human being. What is more, these philosophers came to believe that the universe had two fundamental aspects: order, as mentioned, and sacrifice (yajna) (Easwaran Reference Easwaran2008, 121–122). Indeed, they cautioned that failures to make the proper sacrifices or to properly orient towards the cosmic order would worsen the sufferings of life.Footnote 27 Ancient Indian societies thus aimed to arrange themselves around the Dharma.Footnote 28
I have said that the Dharma can be understood as the ‘intelligible, meaning-conferring cosmic moral order’. I have said a little about the ‘intelligible’ aspect; let me now briefly differentiate the other elements of this definition. First, it should be reiterated that the philosophers of ancient India came to believe that this is not some randomly created cosmos with arbitrary laws into which we are thrown, as it were. Rather, it is a manifested realm – and a singular one at that. The bare fact that there is an apparent order to the cosmos was not taken for granted by them, nor was the fact that the cosmos appears to have a very specific order to it.
Second – moving on to those specifics – this order appeared to them to be a moral one: morality is woven into it, such that our moral judgements are correct insofar as they accurately reflect this moral dimension of the cosmos. To put it another way, we as human beings do not ‘construct’ morality. Rather, we can be said to come up against it in the world through our investigations and failings, etc., just as we might come up against the physical aspect of reality.
Third, as with morality, meaning is built into the very fabric of reality. The ancient Indian philosophers did not consider this universe to be indifferent, let alone hostile, to our efforts. According to their view, the meaning-conferring superstructure of the Dharma, as it were, saturates the cosmos with meaning: we are within a meaning substrate – one that both vivifies and responds to our efforts to seek meaning. To see the importance of this, contrast this universe, as just described, with one in which meaningfulness is never possible. Ours is not this Sisyphean hell.
I shall take up Dharma again in the next section, and draw out its implications for the analytic field of meaning in life. So far in the current section, I have been emphasizing big ontological questions from which the answers to big theological questions cannot be straightforwardly derived. It is not self-evident what theistic conclusions can be drawn from a non-dualist ontology. Consider, for example, the fact that panpsychism need not imply pantheism (see Nagasawa Reference Nagasawa and Seager2020). Thus, to better understand the move from the ontological (non-dualism) to the theological (non-theism) in Advaita Vedānta, let us now look directly at some similar theological categories, and thereby draw out the uniqueness of the Advaitin view of ‘God’.
If pantheism is the view that the universe is God, and if panentheism is the view that the universe is God, and that He transcends the universe, Advaita Vedānta is the view that Brahman (‘God’) is both the universe and That which transcends it – and we are That. In other words:
Pantheism : All is God.
Panentheism : The world is in God.
Advaita Vedānta : The world is in Brahman, and we are Brahman.Footnote 29
The bridge, as it were, between the ontological and the theological here is consciousness, for Brahman is Pure Consciousness. As a knowledge-based path (Jñāna yoga),Footnote 30 Advaita Vedānta prioritizes philosophical reflection over the other classical paths.Footnote 31 Chiefly, it urges us to look deeper at how consciousness works. As an ancient answer to the modern question of the ‘hard problem’ of consciousness (see Chalmers Reference Chalmers1995), it argues that reality is ‘in’ the cosmic consciousness (i.e. Brahman). The world – including our experiences as individual selves – is ‘in’ the Pure Consciousness of Brahman, and Consciousness alone is Real. Here, Advaita Vedānta is in fact significantly similarFootnote 32 to a contemporary view – and a non-religious one, at that: cosmopsychism. If panpsychism is the ‘bottom-up’ view that everything is constitutive of consciousness, then cosmopsychism is the ‘top-down’ view that everything is consciousness.Footnote 33
I conclude this section by saying a little more about the value of these ideas. Cosmogonal and cosmological views similar to Advaita Vedānta have emerged across cultures and periods. On the Graeco-Roman side of things, consider, for example, certain Presocratic philosophers (viz. Anaxagoras, Heraclitus, and Parmenides); Plato himself (the Forms, and concepts like anamnēsis and anima mundi) and Neoplatonism's discussions of the One and the Demiurge. Indeed, various esoteric religious traditions, even within the Abrahamic traditions, display this similarity. Consider ‘God’ as ‘the ground of being’, in the philosophy of Meister Eckhart and other Christian mystics, and the concepts of Aeon and the Monad in Gnosticism.
Some readers may be reminded of Aldous Huxley, who championed ‘the perennial philosophy’: the idea that the world's great spiritual and philosophical traditions come to the same conclusion about the ultimate nature of reality (see Huxley Reference Huxley1947).Footnote 34 ‘Dharma’, too, has analogues in ancient Greek (Logos), African (Ma'at), Chinese (Dao), and Iranian (Asha) philosophical traditions, and perhaps others that I have yet to encounter; the fact that such views were, and still are, widespread strongly motivates for them to be seriously considered.
To summarize, Advaita Vedānta does not fit neatly into the taxonomy of views of meaning discussed in the previous section. It is not clear that Brahman can be understood as analogous to (let alone synonymous with) the way the exoteric Abrahamic traditions understand the term ‘God’, nor is it clear that the view is a theistic one; indeed, it appears that it is not. In the next section, I discuss the relevance of these matters to the contemporary literature on meaning in life.
The ‘God’ of Advaita Vedānta and meaning in life
This section makes clearer why the field of meaning in life should be interested in broadening its scope to include non-theistic, non-dual views like Advaita Vedānta. Such views may stimulate debate around largely unchallenged assumptions in the field (the primacy of meaning; what I shall call ‘base nihilism’; the ‘cosmic-terrestrial’ meaning dichotomy; the ‘natural-supernatural’ dichotomy), and offer new directions (a responsibility-based route to meaning; the promise of a unified theory of meaning). Below, I touch upon each of these areas listed in parentheses, aiming to show that more detailed explorations are warranted in future work. Much of what I say here is speculative, but, crucially, this speculation is inspired by my investigations into Advaita Vedānta as an analytic philosopher.
Interrogating the primacy of ‘meaning’
The field takes ‘meaning’ to be a good that is distinct from happiness or welfare in general, and whose worth does not merely derive from instrumental value. Further, it finds it sensible to speak of ‘great’ meaning (see Metz Reference Metz2011), and, usually when discussing theological matters, ‘ultimate’ meaning.Footnote 35 The latter is usually thought to obtain only if communion with God in an everlasting heaven is possible. In either case, meaning is assumed to be a final value – something to strive towards for its own sake.
My discussion in this article suggests that if the Advaitins and other non-dual non-theists are on to something, then meaning may be better understood as a means than an end. Specifically, it may be a means towards transcending the need for meaning. To put it provocatively, meaning may be a cosmic red herring. On my reading, ‘meaning’ for the Advaitin is not a synonym for ‘(the ultimate) purpose (of life)’,Footnote 36 nor is it a synecdoche for ‘the meaning of life’. Instead, to him, we do not strive for meaning for its own sake; rather, we strive for meaning because the very (Dharmic) structure of the universe reliably rewards certain ways of being in the world. He takes, I might venture to say, a naturalistic stance on meaning. But ultimately, he says, if we yearn to break free from the cycle of birth and rebirth, we must break free from our attachment to meaning – for meaning, too, is an illusory aspect of Māyā.
To be sure, meaning offers essential direction to, say, someone committed to the path of being a householder. But such a path, although praiseworthy, brings with it attachment to worldly desires, and thus suffering. The true aspirant aims at breaking the bonds of suffering by – in terms I have introduced in this article – remembering himself as Brahman. And this remembering entails eventually transitioningFootnote 37 to being Brahman: Pure Consciousness, beyond categories or attachments, and thus beyond suffering. Crucially, Brahman is not associated with ‘ultimate’ or ‘maximal’ meaning in Advaita Vedānta, because It is beyond all categories – and, indeed, experience, as I discuss shortly.
The aspirants of this tradition strive towards Mokṣa, which can be understood as ‘dissolution’, ‘liberation’, ‘enlightenment’, ‘awakening’, or ‘Brahman-realization’ or ‘Self-realization’.Footnote 38 Mokṣa is described as the dissolution of the persistent, individual sense of self (Ahaṁkāra), and escape from the illusion of the world and the cycle of birth of rebirth towards the end of Self-realization. However, it should not be understood as synonymous with ‘ultimate meaning’, as the contemporary, theological discussions of meaning understand it. On the face of it, it is not communion with God in an everlasting heaven, for there is no ‘God’ to commune with. But, going deeper, it is also not entrance into a maximally meaningful experiential realm. For Mokṣa is not an experience; it is, by definition, beyond experience.Footnote 39 The ‘Pure Consciousness’ that the utterance ‘Brahman’ refers to is beyond the phenomenal dimension – beyond the phenomenon of experience. For, as the logic goes, Pure Consciousness does not ‘experience’; rather, experiences are ‘in’ It.Footnote 40 On my reading, then, the Advaitin account of Brahman-realization suggests that it is best understood as beyond meaning, given that meaning is, at least in part, an experiential phenomenon.Footnote 41
The figure of the jīvanmukta – the awakened-while-still-living individualFootnote 42 – may help the reader better understanding this view. If meaning can be understood as that which guides us towards objectively valuable ends – an idea I explore below – then the jīvanmukta is the individual who has successfully followed the path of meaning towards the real final end of Self-realization, and thus no longer needs meaning to guide him. The jīvanmukta, then, is a post-meaning being.Footnote 43 Meaning is thus, in the final analysis, a kind of cosmic red herring. Indeed, in this tradition, it is not uncommon to hear stories of a jīvanmukta entirely losing attachment to the pursuit of meaning in the world, and retiring to some isolated place to spend his days and nights in deep meditation (samādhi). To summarize the idea, then, the jīvanmukta is one who has seen through the veil of Māyā, and has understood the futility of finding meaning through continuing to play at being human, and tastes the bliss (ānanda) that transcends meaning.
The above description of the ways of the jīvanmukta may seem strange to most Western readers. But it is a very familiar one in traditional Eastern cultures – and has been for millennia. And I submit that it can offer insights to the analytic field of meaning in life. If nothing else, the very idea of there being an end higher than meaning (even the ‘maximal’ or ‘ultimate’ meaning of the Abrahamic traditions), or of transcending the need for meaning, should at least pique the curiosity of those working in the field.
At this point, the reader may wonder if the Advatin account of ‘God’ entails a decrement of meaning in life. There is in fact a burgeoning discussion on whether the existence of (the Abrahamic) God would detract from meaning. For example, there are those who believe that God's existence would violate our privacy (Lougheed Reference Lougheed2020), or that the possibility of an eternal afterlife in communion with God would detract from the possibility of living a meaningful life in our earthly realm (Metz Reference Metz2021).Footnote 44 On the face of it, the ‘God’ of Advaita Vedānta undercuts these concerns.
On the Advaitin understanding, you are ‘God’: all of reality is ‘in’ the Pure Consciousness of Brahman, and you are That. There is no realm in which communion with God is to be had – though there is, ultimately, the possibility of remembering that you are the Absolute, ‘dreaming’ reality into existence. Arguably, this does not detract from meaning in life. On the contrary, it affirms both that significant meaning is possible – for life is the realm of meaning – and that, joyously, the responsibility for obtaining that meaning ultimately falls upon you.Footnote 45
Supernaturalism
The instinct to relegate apparently ‘spiritual’ views of meaning to the realm of the ‘supernatural’ is common in the field.Footnote 46 This practice is arguably not appropriate for non-dual, non-theistic views like Advaita Vedānta. The latter developed in very different social, cultural, and philosophical milieu from the ‘spiritual’ ideas in Western thought. For the Advaitin, there is no ‘spirit’ that animates Brahman, Ātman, or the individual jīva;Footnote 47 there is only consciousness, in which āvidya (ignorance) conjures such illusory notions as ‘spirit’. Indeed, it has been argued that there is no ‘spirit’ as such in Indian philosophy in general. Consider P. T. Raju:
What is spirit in Indian thought? Of course, since the word has different connotations even in Western thought, it is easy to select a corresponding connotation and say that that is spirit. . . . But most of the Indians who use the word ‘spiritual’ would say that their activities are not spiritual, because they are not those which are distinguished as spiritual from the non-spiritual. If we take what is essentially spiritual activity and ask what spirit is with reference to that activity or in terms of which that activity is called spiritual, the answer is ‘ātman.’ Spiritual activity is the activity of ātman-realization, which is translated generally as ‘self-realization,’ which may convey different meanings to the Indian and the Westerner. (Raju Reference Raju1954, 195)
Or consider Ariel Glucklich's examination of the ‘magical’ practices of Indian healers:
Is a ghost supernatural? Maybe it is by Western standards, where the known laws of nature rule out the possibility of such an entity. But in a culture where ghosts belong on a continuum of embodied existence ranging from gross body to pure soul, there is nothing supernatural about such a being. For many Indians, ghosts represent the same type of relation as a genetic link does for a Westerner. If a boy can have his father's nose for no visible reason (genes are hard to see), then a girl in India can have the spirit of her deceased aunt possessing her body. . . . Attributing supernatural beliefs to other cultures is a very risky business . . . (Glucklich Reference Glucklich1997, 11)
What could the field gain through questioning the assumption that ‘spirit’ or ‘the supernatural’ are universalizable, transcultural categories? For one, such a move could make certain potentially illuminating views more palatable to naturalist philosophers of meaning who are wary of ‘spirituality’. Though the philosophies of the ancient world may be redolent of ‘spiritual’ musings to (especially secular) Western minds, they are not straightforwardly so – as contemporary ‘Perennialist’Footnote 48 and ‘cosmopsychist’ attempts at restatements demonstrate. A lack of recognition of such important nuances may be needlessly handicapping the field.
To be clear, my aim is not to endorse the Indian view of ghosts (etc.); rather, it is to emphasize that axiomatic rejections of the view for ostensibly empirical reasons are often not only too quick – more importantly, they also fail to appreciate that differing ontologies underwrite these philosophical systems. The takeaway is that the Indian view of ghosts (or Ātman, etc.) cannot be properly understood if it is divorced from its embeddedness within a specific ontology. For within that ontology, ghosts are not considered ‘supernatural’ any more than genes are thought to be supernatural from within a materialist ontology. How does this bear upon analytic analyses of meaning? Axiomatic judgement of such matters as ‘spiritual’ by atheistic and naturalistic analytic philosophers of meaning may bias them against such matters, such that they dismiss too quickly parts of (or whole) philosophical systems before mining such systems for possible insights. (Of course, the ontologies themselves may be indefensible, ultimately; regardless, the philosophical systems they spawn may be of value to, say, atheistic naturalists.)
A second potential boon may be that revisiting assumptions about the nature of consciousness could offer fresh perspectives on the nature of meaning that should at least intrigue both naturalist and theistic philosophers of meaning. Consider the fact that in the Advaitin tradition, at least, what is fundamental is not ‘spirit’, but consciousness. All the laws of nature – indeed, nature itself – are ‘in’ consciousness. So, too, is the phenomenon of meaning. Thus, it is sensible to consider whether the view is compatible with naturalism, as contemporary philosophers of meaning understand this term.
To see why this is so, consider naturalistic pantheism, which holds that God is the natural universe, and is thus bound by its laws.Footnote 49 Similarly, on the Advaitin view, meaning is at once a naturalistic and ‘divine’ or transcendent(al) phenomenon, as I discuss shortly. And the ultimate destination of meaning is acquired when one awakens to the realization that one is the dreamer of the universe; at this point, meaning has served its mysterious purpose in the dream of life; there is no further ‘supernatural’ realm or entity to consider: there is only [Y]ou.
The ‘cosmic-terrestrial’ dichotomy
When most philosophers in the field of meaning use the term ‘cosmic’, they mean ‘from the (objective) perspective of the universe’. Certainly, this seems to be how David Benatar (Reference Benatar2006, 82–83) understands it, and, as is common in the field, he does not think we can sensibly talk about meaning from this perspective.Footnote 50 But the Dharmic view suggests that considering meaning from within a ‘cosmic-terrestrial’ dichotomy is a kind of (cosmic) category error. For, if the world seems to be devoid of meaning, at base, from the ‘terrestrial’ – that is, human – perspective, this is simply due to something lacking in the perspective of the individual investigator(s). On the Dharmic view, not only is a more-than-human meaning possible, but the only intelligible way to think of the phenomenon of meaning is as a ‘cosmic’ phenomenon. For, on this view, the cosmos is a bounded realm of intelligibility, morality, and meaningfulness. We as humans do not create meaning; rather, we discover it.
Moreover, on the Dharmic view it is not the case that meaning is an exclusively ‘human’ phenomenon. Rather, the entire universe is evolving towards Self-realization (discussed at length in Aurobindo 2005) – and this movement, this evolution, is meaning. On this Eastern understanding of evolution, Consciousness (the capitalization is intentional) manifests as ever more developed lifeforms, ‘birth’ after ‘birth’.Footnote 51 The temporary state of ‘being human’ is but a (late) step on this Dharmic evolutionary journey towards Self-realization.
‘Base nihilism’
There is a further consequence to the preceding discussion of (a perceived lack of) cosmic meaning. Much of the field proceeds from what I shall call ‘base nihilism’. It is ‘nihilism’ in that it holds that life is fundamentally meaningless (I draw distinctions between different kinds of nihilism shortly). And I emphasize its quality as ‘base’, because secular Western thought generally takes nihilism as the axiomatic starting point for discussions of meaning. It is important to note that despite life's ‘base meaningless’, meaning in life is nevertheless possible (and desirable) – or, at least, most working in the field have tried to show (acknowledged even by Benatar (Reference Benatar2017, 30–33)).Footnote 52 But what might it do to our perception of what sort of meaning is possible if we challenge base nihilism?
It goes far beyond the scope of the present article, but, as the likes of such salient commenters as Nietzsche document, the establishment of (base) nihilism in the secular Western tradition does indeed seem to follow inexorably from ‘the death of God’.Footnote 53 However, as my discussion of Advaita Vedānta shows, ‘God’ is not dead in other traditions, for they did not undergo the West's nihilistic turn. Nihilism in other traditions is not an established, self-evident conclusion no longer even warranting notice – far from it. Indeed, the presumption is reversed in the Dharmic tradition, which underwrites much of classical Indian philosophy and even contemporary Indian culture. On the Dharmic view, reality, at base, is saturated with meaning: it is the meaning substrate, as it were, into which we find ourselves born. Indeed, reality as we know it is the realm of meaning – for it is in this illusory realm of Māyā that the phenomenon of meaning looms large, directing our aims with its superlative attractiveness. In contrast, then, to the base nihilism of secular Western thought, it could be argued that the Dharmic traditions proceed from base meaning, and, at least in the case of Advaita Vedānta, ultimately motivate for the need to transcend meaning.
To summarize, a consequence of my discussions in this article is that nihilism should not be axiomatically assumed; indeed, nihilism in all its guises should be challenged. Consider existential nihilism, which holds that human efforts are ultimately without purpose, or cosmic nihilism, which holds that the cosmos is either entirely indifferent to, or hostile towards, human beings.Footnote 54 Both these versions of nihilism appear to want a perspective from outside the observable world. In contrast, on the Dharmic view, reality is the condition for the possibility of meaning. Recall that, on this view, the Dharma is observable and testable: one need only aim at living one's life according to its structure, and note what happens. In practice for most people, there need not be any mystical aspect to meaning-making, let alone appeals to faith.
A responsibility-based route to meaning
On the Dharmic view, the structure of reality is such that meaning is gained not only through accruing certain objectively valuable milestones, but also through one's efforts towards that end. Recall that Advaita Vedānta is a knowledge-based path (Jñāna yoga); insofar as it can be said to have a ‘practice’, it encourages self-effort – for it argues that there is no ontologically distinct ‘God’ who, through his Will or Grace, will lead you to ‘salvation’. Consider what I have called the ‘meaning-as-remembering’ view, in which meaning of the most superlative sort is acquired the closer one gets to realizing oneself as Brahman (until meaning itself is transcended in Self-realization). Importantly, each individual must make the final leap towards Self-realization. Self-effort, then, is a vital component of this view.
But the Dharmic traditions do not only speak about meaning of this transcendent sort; what I shall call here the ‘meaning-as-responsibility’ view is also prominent. Consider the concept of svadharma, which refers not to the direct path, as it were, to one's own liberation (Mokṣa), but rather, the meaning-conferring responsibility of fulfilling one's unique duty in the world.Footnote 55 It is not always clear what fulfilling one's duty entails, though – indeed, a central lesson of the Mahābhārata is that morality is messy.Footnote 56 Nevertheless, as Krishna famously says to the crestfallen warrior Arjuna in the Bhagavad Gītā, ‘[i]t is better to strive in one's own dharma than to succeed in the dharma of another’ (chapter 3, verse 35).Footnote 57
I do not need to claim here that the Dharmic route to meaning via responsibility is the most compelling route of this kind, nor do I even have to claim that it is one of the best. My aim is simply to point out that responsibility is a route to meaning that has been underexplored by the field.Footnote 58 Comparative analyses can be insightful – note the primacy of responsibility in the Dharmic worldview – and the field can be enriched by them.
The promise of a unified theory of meaning
I suspect that a decent attempt could be made at crafting a plausible unified theory of meaning through Advaita Vedānta.Footnote 59 So far as I can tell, some salient theories of meaning in the field share a unifying aspect – namely, the phenomenon of unification itself!
I cannot hope to satisfactorily represent such a unified theory here, but consider, for example, Robert Nozick's idea of ‘organic unity’ (Nozick Reference Nozick1981, 574–619), and Thaddeus Metz's arguments for a theory of meaning in which transcending one's ‘animal self’ is a key feature (see Metz Reference Metz2013). These and other theories of meaning appeal to the idea of transcending limits to connect with certain objective goods. Metz explicitly appeals to the classic triumvirate of ‘the good, the true, and the beautiful’ to represent the distillation of these objective goods, thinking of them in naturalistic terms as ‘exemplars of meaning for the field more generally’ (Metz Reference Metz2013, 95).
A Dharmic unified theory of meaning would go further. According to it, the classic triumvirate would represent transcendental aspects of the Dharma. That is to say, instances of correct alignment with the most fundamental aspects of the Dharma – Truth, Beauty, and the Good in their ancient, transcendental senses – are what we apprehend as ‘meaningful’; the higher the fidelity of alignment, the greater the meaning. Put differently, to align with these fundamental aspects is to taste the manifested nature of the meaning-making dream of Brahman as this realm.Footnote 60 And thus, as one gets closer to the (ultimately inscrutable) parameters of this dream, one may perhaps ‘awaken’ from it, and thus transcend meaning.
Conclusion
In this article, I have shown that the ‘God’ of Advaita Vedānta does not fit neatly into the recently proposed taxonomy of the axiology of theism, which the analytic field of meaning has begun to explore. For one, the concept of ‘Brahman’ is radically different from the concept of ‘God’ in the exoteric Abrahamic faiths. For another, it is not self-evident that Advaita Vedānta can be properly understood as ‘theistic’ or ‘supernaturalism’. I have thus argued that it is more fitting to consider Advaita Vedānta as a form of ‘non-dual/non-theism’. Further, I have suggested that contemporary cosmopsychist and Perennialist views may be considered (at least) broadly compatible with it. The view, then, is not some anomaly that can be easily ignored, dismissed, or explained away.
Indeed, my discussion demonstrates that closer engagement with the view may stimulate new ways of thinking about meaning. It, and similar views, should thus receive greater attention from scholars working in the field – the intellectual virtues of curiosity and openness to new ideas compel us to consider them. Thus, philosophers of religion and philosophers of meaning – and those who work at the intersection of these fields – should be excited by the rich new areas of exploration represented by Advaita Vedānta and similar views.
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to Thaddeus Metz for his advice and encouragement on an early version of this article, and to Cate Otto for closely reading the final version for typographical errors. I am also grateful to the organizers of the Third International Conference in Philosophy and Meaning in Life (hosted online by the University of Birmingham in July 2020) for affording me the opportunity to gain feedback on my preliminary ideas for this article. Lastly, I thank the two anonymous peer-reviewers of this work for their generous and collegial comments.