Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:24:22.393Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Psychiatric comorbidity: a concept in need of a theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 June 2023

Julie Nordgaard*
Affiliation:
Mental Health Center Amager, University Hospital Copenhagen, Denmark Department of Clinical Medicine, University of Copenhagen, Denmark
Kasper Møller Nielsen
Affiliation:
Mental Health Center Amager, University Hospital Copenhagen, Denmark
Andreas Rosén Rasmussen
Affiliation:
Mental Health Center Amager, University Hospital Copenhagen, Denmark Department of Clinical Medicine, University of Copenhagen, Denmark Center for Youth Mental Health, The University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Victoria, Australia
Mads Gram Henriksen
Affiliation:
Mental Health Center Amager, University Hospital Copenhagen, Denmark Department of Communication, Center for Subjectivity Research, University of Copenhagen, Denmark
*
Corresponding author: Julie Nordgaard; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Despite being a relatively new concept, psychiatric comorbidity, i.e. the co-occurrence of two or more mental disorders, has become widespread in clinical practice and psychiatric research. In this article, we trace the origin of the concept of psychiatric comorbidity, discuss the conceptual literature and point to basic problems concerning inadequate definition of the concept, differential diagnostic issues, and reification of mental disorders. We illustrate how these problems may have consequences for diagnostic assessment in current clinical practice and psychiatric research. To address some of the problems related to psychiatric comorbidity, we discuss potential principles for assessing psychiatric comorbidity. Inspired by Feinstein's original concept of comorbidity in general medicine and his differential diagnostic principles, we emphasize the importance of independence of mental disorders when assessing psychiatric comorbidity. We suggest that knowledge of trait v. state conditions and of the multitudinous clinical manifestations beyond what is captured in the diagnostic manuals may be helpful for assessing the independence of mental disorders and thus psychiatric comorbidity. We further argue that a more hierarchical diagnostic system and explicit exclusionary rules could improve clinical practice and research by reducing informational complexity and combating unwarranted psychiatric comorbidity.

Type
Review Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Despite being a relatively new concept, comorbidity has gained immense popularity in psychiatry and is currently widespread in everyday clinical work and research. The concept of comorbidity was introduced to general medicine in 1970 by Feinstein (Reference Feinstein1970), who defined it as ‘any distinct additional clinical entity that has existed or that may occur during the clinical course of a patient who has the index disease under study’. The concept of comorbidity was first used in psychiatry during the 1980s, and comorbidity was defined as the co-occurrence of medical conditions and/or mental disorders (Boyd et al., Reference Boyd, Burke, Gruenberg, Holzer, Rae, George and Nestadt1984; Klerman, Reference Klerman, Maser and Cloninger1990; Leckman, Weissman, Merikangas, Pauls, & Prusoff, Reference Leckman, Weissman, Merikangas, Pauls and Prusoff1983). Comorbidity was also used ‘internally’ in psychiatry to diagnose the co-occurrence of two or more mental disorders, viz. psychiatric comorbidity (Maj, Reference Maj2005b).

The number of patients diagnosed with psychiatric comorbidity has increased significantly and empirical research on comorbid mental disorders has similarly grown (Lilienfeld, Waldman, & Israel, Reference Lilienfeld, Waldman and Israel1994; Lilienfeld et al., Reference Lilienfeld, Sauvigné, Lynn, Cautin, Latzman and Waldman2015). This development is also reflected in the diagnostic manuals, where the term ‘comorbid’ appeared 0 times in DSM-III but more than 600 times in DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). Despite the popularity of the concept of psychiatric comorbidity, it has often been criticized. In fact, there is a striking incongruence between the widespread use of psychiatric comorbidity in clinical practice and empirical research (e.g. Etchecopar-Etchart et al., Reference Etchecopar-Etchart, Korchia, Loundou, Llorca, Auquier, Lançon and Fond2021; Plana-Ripoll et al., Reference Plana-Ripoll, Pedersen, Holtz, Benros, Dalsgaard, de Jonge and McGrath2019; Strålin & Hetta, Reference Strålin and Hetta2019) and theoretical studies that generally pose strong reservations toward psychiatric comorbidity (e.g. First, Reference First2005; Frances, Widiger, & Fyer, Reference Frances, Widiger, Fyer, Maser and Cloninger1990; Lilienfeld et al. Reference Lilienfeld, Waldman and Israel1994; Maj, Reference Maj2005b; Meehl, Reference Meehl2001; van Praag, Reference van Praag1996; Vella, Aragona, & Alliani, Reference Vella, Aragona and Alliani2000). As Maj has emphasized, this persistent incongruence calls for critical reflection on the concept of psychiatric comorbidity (Maj, Reference Maj2005a).

The purpose of this study is to examine the concept of psychiatric comorbidity and its impact on everyday clinical work and psychiatric research. First, we trace the origin of the concept of psychiatric comorbidity back to Feinstein's concept of comorbidity, and discuss some basic problems related to psychiatric comorbidity. We then exemplify how such problems may affect research and clinical practice. Finally, inspired by Feinstein's definition of comorbidity and his differential diagnostic principles, we discuss principles for assessing psychiatric comorbidity.

Theoretical issues

Feinstein (Reference Feinstein1970, p. 457) offered several examples to illustrate his concept of distinct additional clinical entity – e.g. ‘If the index disease is primary cancer of the lung, the co-morbid diseases can be such entities as: episodes of mumps or bleeding duodenal ulcer that occurred antecedently; coronary artery disease or pneumococcal pneumonia detected when the cancer is discovered’. In brief, Feinstein's (Reference Feinstein1970; Kaplan & Feinstein, Reference Kaplan and Feinstein1974) discussion of comorbidity gravitates around the case of cancer with a pragmatic focus on identifying comorbid diseases or conditions that may affect diagnosis, prognosis, pathogenicity, or therapeutic outcome. Since the concept of comorbidity invariably raises differential diagnostic issues, Feinstein proposed differential diagnostic principles for assessing comorbidity, emphasizing toponymy (i.e. considering an event's anatomic location in relation to that of the index disease) and chronometric reasoning (i.e. events or conditions, prior or presently, that impact the natural course of the index disease). From Feinstein's original definition, the many examples he discussed in the article, and the character of the differential diagnostic principles, it is evident that his concept of comorbidity hinges on the notion of distinct additional clinical entities, and, most importantly, that to qualify as a distinct additional clinical entity a medical condition must have either known etiology and/or circumscribed pathology (Lilienfeld et al., Reference Lilienfeld, Waldman and Israel1994; Maser & Cloninger, Reference Maser, Cloninger, Maser and Cloninger1990; Meehl, Reference Meehl2001; Vella et al., Reference Vella, Aragona and Alliani2000; Wyrsch, Reference Wyrsch1930).

In the 1980s, Feinstein's concept of comorbidity found its way into psychiatry, where it was also used to diagnose psychiatric comorbidity, i.e. the co-occurrence of two or more mental disorders (Andrews, Henderson, & Hall, Reference Andrews, Henderson and Hall2001; Klerman, Reference Klerman, Maser and Cloninger1990; Maser & Cloninger, Reference Maser, Cloninger, Maser and Cloninger1990; Plana-Ripoll et al., Reference Plana-Ripoll, Pedersen, Holtz, Benros, Dalsgaard, de Jonge and McGrath2019; Trull, Scheiderer, & Tomko, Reference Trull, Scheiderer, Tomko and Widiger2012; Wittchen, Reference Wittchen1996). While this may seem like an intuitive extension of Feinstein's definition, it is, in fact, not unproblematic.

When it comes to psychiatric comorbidity, it is, in most cases, not clear that the founding principle of Feinstein's original definition, viz., the notion of distinct additional clinical entities, can be met. To qualify as distinct additional clinical entities, mental disorders must have either known etiology or circumscribed pathology. Most mental disorders, however, have unknown etiology. Psychiatric comorbidity is therefore typically based solely upon description of psychopathology. If mental disorders had well circumscribed psychopathology, it could potentially compensate for the absence of known etiology, and they would still qualify as distinct additional clinical entities. However, mental disorders are precisely not assumed to be completely demarcated from each other in the sense that single symptoms of one mental disorder cannot occur in another disorder – e.g. as stated in DSM-5-TR (American Psychiatric Association, 2022; cf. American Psychiatric Association, 1980, p. 6), ‘there is no assumption that each category of mental disorder is a completely discrete entity with absolute boundaries dividing it from other mental disorders or from no mental disorder’. This assumption, underlying the classification of mental disorders, is natural given that many symptoms are found across mental disorders (e.g. anxiety), and only few symptoms are considered diagnostically specific for any disorder (e.g. Mølstrøm, Henriksen, & Nordgaard, Reference Mølstrøm, Henriksen and Nordgaard2020). However, the absence of known etiology and circumscribed psychopathology jointly implies that the founding principle of Feinstein's concept of comorbidity, i.e. the notion of distinct additional clinical entities, typically is lacking in psychiatry.

Recognizing this, First (Reference First2005) proposed a distinction between three types of psychiatric comorbidity: (1) true comorbidity pertaining to cases of mental disorders that fulfil Feinstein's requirement of distinct additional clinical entities; (2) artifactual comorbidity which is a by-product of the diagnostic manuals’ decision ‘to “split” diagnostic entities into numerous specific narrowly-defined disorders’ (First, Reference First2005, p. 207); and (3) spurious comorbidity which is best avoided (e.g. comorbidity between autistic disorder and Asperger's disorder in DSM-IV). Since true comorbidity is rare in psychiatry and spurious comorbidity must be avoided, psychiatric comorbidity, First (Reference First2005) argued, primarily consists of cases of artifactual comorbidity. Consequently, First (Reference First2005, p. 206) noted that it could be misleading to speak of psychiatric comorbidity – ‘It is important to understand that comorbidity in psychiatry does not imply the presence of multiple diseases or dysfunctions’. Still, First advocated the use of psychiatric comorbidity, citing the instruction from ICD-10 (World Health Organization, 1992), recommending that ‘clinicians should follow the general rule of recording as many diagnoses as are necessary to cover the clinical picture’. However, in the context of ICD-10, this instruction does not imply that a diagnosis should be made for every symptom constellation (mental disorder) for which a patient fulfils diagnostic criteria. In ICD-10, it only pertains to symptom complexes that cannot be accommodated by the index disorder. For example, a diagnosis of schizophrenia is sufficient to cover almost all other symptoms – e.g. anxiety and changes of personality are common features of schizophrenia. Since such symptoms can be accommodated by the index disorder (schizophrenia), no additional diagnosis is typically needed ‘to cover the clinical picture’. Finally, the renouncement of the founding principle of comorbidity (i.e. distinct additional clinical entities) seems premature and leaves us with a concept of psychiatric comorbidity (artifactual comorbidity) that, strictly put, negates the very meaning of the concept of comorbidity. If the concept of psychiatric comorbidity is to be meaningful, a qualification of distinct additional clinical entities other than known etiology and circumscribed pathology is needed (see the final section for a proposal).

Another issue, complicating matters further, is the fact that the diagnostic criteria, as stated in ICD-10 (World Health Organization, 1992), ‘do not pretend to be comprehensive statements about the current state of knowledge of the disorders’ but serve only as ‘a reasonable basis for defining the limits of categories’. In other words, the purpose of the diagnostic criteria is to delimit the different mental disorders from each other; it is not to exhaustively describe their psychopathology. Although the diagnostic criteria initially were considered as ‘gate keepers’, i.e. a sort of minimum requirement for making a diagnosis, they have increasingly come to be perceived as almost exhaustive of the psychopathology of the different mental disorders (Andreasen, Reference Andreasen2007; Kendler, Reference Kendler2016a; Kendler, Reference Kendler2022; Kendler & Zachar, Reference Kendler, Zachar, Kendler and Parnas2008). This perception is, to some extent, underpinned by contemporary textbooks of psychiatry that regularly are tailored to the diagnostic criteria and therefore predominately include information about psychopathology listed as diagnostic criteria. Consequently, knowledge of psychopathology that is not included as diagnostic criteria is disappearing from contemporary psychiatric discourse and research (Parnas, Reference Parnas2011). This unintended development may also impact assessment of comorbidity. For example, clinicians or researchers may be unaware that many symptoms and signs are well-known features of a given disorder (e.g. schizophrenia) when such symptoms and signs (e.g. obsessive-like features, concentration and attentional difficulties, self-disorders, etc.; Henriksen, Raballo, & Nordgaard, Reference Henriksen, Raballo and Nordgaard2021; Rasmussen & Parnas, Reference Rasmussen and Parnas2022) are not included in the diagnostic criteria for the disorder.

The final theoretical issue that we will address here can be summarized under the heading of reification, which designates that something essentially non-thing-like acquires a thing-like status. As Kendler (Reference Kendler2016b) aptly put it, ‘It is a conceptual error to assume that our diagnostic criteria constitute rather than index our disorders’. Despite such cautionary statements, the diagnostic categories are often taken to be the mental disorders they index (Frances et al., Reference Frances, Widiger, Fyer, Maser and Cloninger1990; Hyman, Reference Hyman2010; Jablensky, Reference Jablensky2004, Reference Jablensky2005; Kendler, Reference Kendler2014). Already in the 1970s, Kendell (Reference Kendell1975) eloquently pointed to this crucial issue, ‘Because the categories and those attributed to it has a name, it acquires a shadowy ‘existence’ of its own, and it eventually comes to be assumed that its members must differ in some fundamental way from members of the other categories in the typology’. Reification is important for the discussion of psychiatric comorbidity because reification of mental disorders and psychiatric comorbidity to some extent seem to implicate or reinforce each other. Even though the diagnostic manuals repeatedly emphasize the absence of any assumption of clear-cut boundaries between the diagnostic categories, the categories nonetheless, as Kendell described, tend to reify over time (Hyman, Reference Hyman2010; Kendell & Jablensky, Reference Kendell and Jablensky2003) and come to be viewed as separate entities.

Although psychiatric comorbidity in the literature usually is defined as the co-occurrence of mental disorders, i.e. without explicitly assuming their independence (for an exception, see Caron & Rutter, Reference Caron and Rutter1991), the concept of psychiatric comorbidity nonetheless carries an implicit assumption of independence of mental disorders. This implicit assumption of independence of mental disorders permeates much research on psychiatric comorbidity. For example, a large-scale Danish register study found that all mental disorders were associated with an increased risk of all other mental disorders (Plana-Ripoll et al., Reference Plana-Ripoll, Pedersen, Holtz, Benros, Dalsgaard, de Jonge and McGrath2019). This finding must, however, be tempered by the fact that the hierarchical rules of the applied diagnostic manual (ICD-10), which exert rules for diagnosing comorbidity, were not applied in the study. Another study – the Dunedin Longitudinal Study from New Zealand – also found psychiatric comorbidity to a large extent on a lifetime basis in a complete birth cohort (Caspi & Moffitt, Reference Caspi and Moffitt2018). Here, psychiatric comorbidity was assessed ‘without regard for hierarchical exclusionary rules’ (Caspi et al., Reference Caspi, Houts, Belsky, Goldman-Mellor, Harrington, Israel and Moffitt2014). In both studies, mutual independence of all mental disorders was presumed, exemplifying to some extent a reified approach to mental disorders, and the studies’ findings of widespread psychiatric comorbidity rest in the end on an inadequate application of the guidelines of the relevant diagnostic manual. This prompts the question of whether such results are perhaps less facts than artifacts, resulting from insufficient differential diagnosis?

Clinical issues

The theoretical issues discussed above also seep into daily clinical reality, which we illustrate with two clinical vignettes.

Clinical vignette 1

A 28-year-old man was diagnosed with schizophrenia when he was 22. He had had a difficult childhood with mentally ill parents. In primary school, he had some difficulties concentrating and motor restlessness. He only had a few friends. He dropped out of high school because of severe concentration problems. He started different educations and jobs, but he was unable to maintain them for more than a few months. In the last couple of years, he has not been working or getting an education.

He was diagnosed with schizophrenia due to the presence of delusions, auditory hallucinations, negative symptoms, and social difficulties. He was in treatment with antipsychotic medication for several periods with some effect. At age 28, he was diagnosed with comorbid attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder (ADHD) due to concentration problems, difficulties in completing simple assignments, and motor restlessness. It was assessed that these difficulties had been present since childhood due to his concentration difficulties and motor restlessness in primary school.

The challenge in this case is that some symptoms of ADHD resemble some symptoms of schizophrenia – motor disturbances, concentration difficulties, and cognitive impairments are well-known features of schizophrenia (Elvevåg & Goldberg, Reference Elvevåg and Goldberg2000). Consequently, it is difficult to determine if these symptoms are genuine symptoms of ADHD or simply early developmental aspects of schizophrenia. However, deciding whether these symptoms are expressive of ADHD or schizophrenia can have implications for treatment. If these symptoms are considered reflective of comorbid ADHD, this can lead to prescription of CNS stimulants such as methylphenidate, which some studies have reported may lead to psychotic activation in patients with schizophrenia (Lieberman, Kane, & Alvir, Reference Lieberman, Kane and Alvir1987).

Clinical vignette 2

A 28-year-old man, who recently had been diagnosed with obsessive–compulsive disorder (OCD), was subsequently diagnosed with schizophrenia due to the presence of persecutory and self-referential delusions, visual hallucinations, and negative symptoms. He described obsessions and compulsions with several themes, especially washing compulsions related to intrusive mental images of contamination and infection. When cooking, he watches ‘whole movies in the head’ about this issue. The involuntary images are extremely vivid, last several minutes, and ‘kind of automatically zoom in on disgusting details’, e.g. that some meat accidentally touched the cutlery, or that some animal urinated on the vegetables. He claims to be aware that these thoughts are exaggerated, but they still make him anxious. Often, there are several, unrelated scenarios occurring at the same time, which he ‘observes in the head’; ‘it is like a high-way intersection’, he states, the ‘thoughts are like cars passing in all directions’. When such ‘OCD-thoughts’ become intense, they feel alien, ‘almost as-if they were not mine’. He is occupied with obsessions and compulsion for several hours daily and avoids eating outside his home.

Here, OCD symptomatology is present in a patient, who also fulfils the diagnostic criteria for schizophrenia. In DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association, 2013, p. 237), criterion D specifies that a diagnosis of OCD should not be made if the disturbance is better explained by another diagnosis. It is certainly possible that the OCD symptomology in this patient is a part of schizophrenia. Yet, DSM-5 also states, ‘OCD is also much more common in individuals with certain other disorders (…) when one of those other disorders is diagnosed, the individual should be assessed for OCD as well. For example, in individuals with schizophrenia or schizoaffective disorder, the prevalence of OCD is approximately 12%’ (American Psychiatric Association, 2013, p. 242). How is the clinician to know whether the obsessions and compulsions are ‘better explained’ by schizophrenia (which would be the case in ICD-10 due to its hierarchical principles) or if making a comorbid diagnosis of OCD is the sound clinical judgment? Although the patient demonstrates some degree of insight, he is unable to resist or suppress the intrusive thoughts and images, which occur automatically with a weakened sense of being generated by the patient. In classical psychopathological literature, such symptoms exemplify pseudo-obsessive phenomena, which are characteristic of schizophrenia spectrum disorders (for reviews, see Bürgy, Reference Bürgy2007; Rasmussen & Parnas, Reference Rasmussen and Parnas2022).

As illustrated in the vignettes, applying the concept of psychiatric comorbidity in clinical settings faces certain problems. In medicine, it is an honored principle to prefer to allocate a single diagnosis if that diagnosis can accommodate all the patient's pathological phenomena. In both vignettes, the patients’ symptomatology can be explained by a single diagnosis (schizophrenia), but it is not entirely clear whether a comorbid diagnosis should be made. Following Feinstein (Reference Feinstein1970), diagnostically unspecific symptoms, which can be seen across a range of disorders, should not lead to a comorbid diagnosis, if they possibly are a part of the index disease. Nonetheless, this type of psychiatric comorbidity – what First called artifactual comorbidity – appears to be widespread in clinical work and research, but here it is often uninformed by First's realization that much psychiatric comorbidity does not qualify as true comorbidity. If the hierarchical rules of the diagnostic manuals are ignored or their exclusionary rules are too vague, it carries a risk of inflating comorbidity by reducing the psychopathological complexity of mental disorders to mere separate ‘symptom-compartments’. In clinical practice, it additionally carries a risk of ‘compartmentalizing’ the psyche of patient, thereby not seeing the patient as a whole and unified human being but instead as a person with a psyche composed of, say, one part schizophrenia, one part OCD, and one part ADHD, and where each of these parts may invite different disorder-specific treatments. Receiving comorbid diagnoses may also lead to unwarranted polypharmacy (Maj, Reference Maj2005b) and obstruct other kinds of treatment.

Diagnosing psychiatric comorbidity also entails ethical issues. If the diagnostic guidelines are not adequately followed, we are dealing with cases of misdiagnosis, which is both unethical and harmful. A related question is if a patient's symptomology can be explained by a single diagnosis, is it then ethically sound to diagnose the patient with multiple mental disorders? If we make multiple diagnoses to explain the same amount of psychopathology that could be explained by a single diagnosis, do we not risk putting the patient in an even more difficult situation? Receiving one diagnosis is frequently experienced as difficult, often requiring adjustment of one's self-understanding to accommodate certain disorder-specific vulnerabilities and developing suitable protective or compensatory strategies to deal with them. This difficulty likely increases with the number of received diagnoses and vulnerabilities one faces.

Finally, the current use of psychiatric comorbidity also has implications for research. For example, in the case of comorbid mental disorders, which disorder is considered the index disorder in register or empirical studies? If a disorder placed lower in the diagnostic hierarchy (ICD-10) is considered the index disorder and a higher placed comorbid disorder is ignored, then symptoms traditionally restricted to the higher placed disorder (e.g. psychosis) may also be found in the lower placed disorder. Regularly, such transdiagnostic findings are used to support the claim that a dimensional approach to the classification of mental disorders fits the data better than a categorical approach (Clark, Reference Clark2005; Cohen & Öngür, Reference Cohen and Öngür2023). Yet, we wonder if these data fit a dimensional approach better because it was collected with a liberal assessment of psychiatric comorbidity, disregarding hierarchical rules and/or exclusion criteria? Finally, we wonder if, say, OCD in a patient with only OCD is really the same as OCD in a patient with comorbid schizophrenia? Do we not risk losing sight of essential qualitative differences between mental disorders if we disregard the overall psychopathological context (Gestalt) in which the symptoms occur and from which they receive their clinical significance?

Toward a new assessment of psychiatric comorbidity

Despite the reservations outlined above, we believe the concept of psychiatric comorbidity can be both appropriate and helpful in psychiatry. There are clinical situations, where it is relevant to make a comorbid diagnosis – e.g. a patient, who was diagnosed with a personality disorder 20 years ago, and who develops a major depression. In this case, the patient's mental condition, which has been stable for years, changes markedly with new and clearly depressive symptoms emerging. However, if the concept of psychiatric comorbidity is to be applied in a more meaningful way in psychiatry, its theoretical foundation must first be established. Inspired by Feinstein's concept of comorbidity and his differential diagnostic principles, we suggest some potential principles for an improved assessment of psychiatric comorbidity.

Since known etiology and circumscribed pathology cannot adequately qualify mental disorders as distinct additional clinical entities, we must look elsewhere for a principle to secure, as far as possible, their mutual independence. Here, it may be helpful to distinguish between two different levels of analysis: a diagnostic level and a nosological level.

The diagnostic level targets assessment of comorbidity in clinical practice and research using the existing diagnostic manuals. Here, we suggest that the distinction between trait and state conditions (see Fig. 1) can play a more crucial role in determining whether a patient's symptomatology amounts to a distinct clinical entity in addition to the index disorder. Trait conditions are mental disorders, which are defined as such in the diagnostic manuals. The symptomatology of trait conditions can fluctuate in severity, but the disorder is usually present for a longer time, often years. Examples of trait conditions can be autism spectrum disorder, ADHD, schizophrenia, or personality disorders. By contrast, state conditions are mental disorders, which are defined as such in diagnostic manuals, and which are present in one or more circumscribed episodes. Examples of state conditions can be affective disorders, e.g. major depression. In the example above, the patient has a stable trait condition (a personality disorder), when a later state condition (major depression) emerges. Crucially, the patient's more enduring symptomology is accommodated by the personality disorder, and the emerging depressive symptoms, which cannot be explained by the trait condition, are accommodated by the diagnosis of major depression. If, by contrast, we met the patient for the very first time, and the patient fulfilled criteria for both major depression and a personality disorder, we should not immediately make both diagnoses, since apparent changes of personality could be a product of the current depressive episode. In this case, we should diagnose and treat the major depression, and wait until the depression recedes to see if the changes of personality recede with it. If they do not recede, we could then perhaps diagnose a comorbid personality disorder.

Figure. 1. Illustration of state and trait conditions. (a) A state condition with a single episode of a disorder, e.g. major depression. (b) A state condition with recurring episodes, e.g. bipolar disorder. (c) A trait condition, e.g. schizophrenia. (d) A trait condition with a comorbid state condition, e.g. personality disorder with a single episode of major depression.

Applying the distinction between trait and state conditions to inform assessment of psychiatric comorbidity cannot, however, stand alone. Such an assessment ultimately rests on a comprehensive understanding of the psychopathology of mental disorders. Such an understanding, which necessarily goes beyond the limited range of symptoms and signs included in the major diagnostic manuals, forms an indispensable part of the ‘clinical judgment’ upon which diagnoses must be made (American Psychiatric Association, 2022). Such an understanding can only be achieved through varied clinical experience, reading psychopathological literature, and ongoing discussions about psychopathological phenomena with experts.

Assessment of comorbidity can be substantially improved at the diagnostic level by making suitable changes at the nosological level. Here, a classical principle for differential diagnosis can further help us restrict the use of psychiatric comorbidity. Traditionally, psychiatry has operated with a hierarchical classification of mental disorders (American Psychiatric Association, 1980), based on the clinical method (Owen, Reference Owen2023), which, in a descending order, roughly can be summarized as follows: organic disorders, schizophrenia, affective disorders, anxiety disorders, and personality disorders (Jaspers, Reference Jaspers1997, pp. 605–606, 611–612; Klerman, Reference Klerman, Maser and Cloninger1990; Owen, Reference Owen2023, p. 1704). For disorders at the top of the diagnostic hierarchy (e.g. organic disorders or schizophrenia), most, if not all, symptoms may occur. By contrast, the range of symptoms is much more limited in disorders placed lower in the diagnostic hierarchy (e.g. anxiety or personality disorders) (American Psychiatric Association, 1980). Thus, if a patient fulfils diagnostic criteria for more than one disorder, the highest placed disorder generally outranks lower placed disorders, implying that comorbid diagnoses should not be made if the symptomatology can be accommodated by the index disorder – a point vividly illustrated in the decision trees for differential diagnoses in previous editions of DSM (American Psychiatric Association, 1980, pp. 339–349, 2000, pp. 744–757) and still operative in ICD-10.

Today, emphasis on the diagnostic hierarchy of mental disorders has gradually eroded, as it has been argued that the hierarchy is empirically unfounded (e.g. Boyd et al., Reference Boyd, Burke, Gruenberg, Holzer, Rae, George and Nestadt1984; Leckman et al., Reference Leckman, Weissman, Merikangas, Pauls and Prusoff1983; Pincus, Tew, & First, Reference Pincus, Tew and First2004). This crumbling of a pillar of classical medical thinking, coupled with a somewhat blind faith in empiricism (Faust & Miner, Reference Faust and Miner1986; Kendler, Reference Kendler1990), has, however, had various ‘unintended consequences’ (Andreasen, Reference Andreasen2007; Wakefield, Reference Wakefield2016). In the case of psychiatric comorbidity, the weakening of the diagnostic hierarchy may have contributed to the inflation of psychiatric comorbidity, because symptom constellations that previously would have been regarded as mere psychopathological aspects of hierarchically higher placed disorders – e.g. anxiety or changes of personality as features of schizophrenia or major depression – now often are perceived as comorbidities. Despite going against current trends, opting for a more hierarchical diagnostic system, which is both simple to understand and easy to administer, could improve clinical practice and psychiatric research by reducing informational complexity and combating ‘compartmentalization’ of the human psyche and a superficial and partial understanding of patients’ difficulties (Aragona, Reference Aragona2009; Jablensky, Reference Jablensky2004; Widiger & Ford-Black, Reference Widiger and Ford-Black1994).

Two often invoked arguments against a diagnostic hierarchy are that it prevents a full representation of patients’ symptomatology and that it restricts research into lower placed disorders (Clark, Reference Clark2005). The first objection hinges on the erroneous assumption that the diagnostic criteria are exhaustive of the psychopathology of the different disorders. Regarding the second objection, we cannot see why research on lower placed disorders necessarily would be restricted. Moreover, it could be beneficial to study such disorders when they occur without comorbidity – is anxiety (occurring without a comorbid disorder) really the same condition as anxiety occurring in, e.g. schizophrenia?

Even without a strict hierarchical diagnostic system, psychiatric comorbidity may still be restricted using exclusion criteria (Robins & Guze, Reference Robins and Guze1970). While exclusion criteria are frequently used, they have become increasingly vague and open to interpretation, exemplified by the recurring exclusion criterion in DSM-5 stating that the disturbance is ‘not better explained’ by another disorder. How can we decide if symptoms of a given disorder is ‘better explained’ by another disorder and what is the basis of that judgment? More explicit exclusion criteria (e.g. diagnosis A must not be made if diagnosis B or C is made) may diminish the role of interpretation and restrict psychiatric comorbidity.

Finally, other criteria for diagnostic validity have been proposed (e.g. biological markers, treatment response, or risk factors) but none of them seem able to provide strong differential diagnostic tools as long as the etiology and pathogenesis of most mental disorders remain largely unknown (e.g. Robins & Guze, Reference Robins and Guze1970; and the validators for change of diagnostic criteria at the DSM proposal submission portal).

Conclusion

We addressed theoretical issues related to the concept of psychiatric comorbidity and illustrated how these issues may affect clinical practice and psychiatric research. If the concept of psychiatric comorbidity is to be applied in a scientific sense, it is important to clarify in what sense mental disorders can be said to be independent from each other and thus constitute distinct additional clinical entities. At a diagnostic level, we suggested that the distinction between trait and state conditions may be helpful in combination with comprehensive psychopathological knowledge. At a nosological level, we suggested that a more hierarchical diagnostic system and/or more explicit exclusionary rules may aid differential diagnosis and pave the path to a sounder application of psychiatric comorbidity with benefits for both clinical practice and research.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Competing interest

None.

References

American Psychiatric Association (1980). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (3rd ed.). Arlington: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
American Psychiatric Association (2000). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th ed., text revised). Arlington: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Arlington: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
American Psychiatric Association (2022). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed., text revised). Arlington: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
Andreasen, N. C. (2007). DSM and the death of phenomenology in America: An example of unintended consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 33, 108112.10.1093/schbul/sbl054CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Andrews, G., Henderson, S., & Hall, W. (2001). Prevalence, comorbidity, disability and service utilisation. Overview of the Australian National Mental Health Survey. British Journal of Psychiatry, 178, 145153.10.1192/bjp.178.2.145CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Aragona, M. (2009). The role of comorbidity in the crisis of the current psychiatric classification system. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 16, 111.10.1353/ppp.0.0211CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, J. H., Burke, J. D. Jr., Gruenberg, E., Holzer, C. E. 3rd, Rae, D. S., George, L. K., … Nestadt, G. (1984). Exclusion criteria of DSM-III. A study of co-occurrence of hierarchy-free syndromes. Archives of General Psychiatry, 41, 983989.10.1001/archpsyc.1984.01790210065008CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bürgy, M. (2007). Obsession in the strict sense: A helpful psychopathological phenomenon in the differential diagnosis between obsessive-compulsive disorder and schizophrenia. Psychopathology, 40, 102110.10.1159/000098490CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caron, C., & Rutter, M. (1991). Comorbidity in child psychopathology: Concepts, issues and research strategies. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry and Allied Disciplines, 32, 10631080.10.1111/j.1469-7610.1991.tb00350.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Caspi, A., Houts, R. M., Belsky, D. W., Goldman-Mellor, S. J., Harrington, H., Israel, S., … Moffitt, T. E. (2014). The p factor: One general psychopathology factor in the structure of psychiatric disorders? Clinical Psychological Science, 2, 119137.10.1177/2167702613497473CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caspi, A., & Moffitt, T. E. (2018). All for one and one for all: Mental disorders in one dimension. American Journal of Psychiatry, 175, 831844.10.1176/appi.ajp.2018.17121383CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, L. A. (2005). Temperament as a unifying basis for personality and psychopathology. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 114, 505521.10.1037/0021-843X.114.4.505CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cohen, B. M., & Öngür, D. (2023). The need for evidence-based updating of ICD and DSM models of psychotic and mood disorders. Molecular Psychiatry.10.1038/s41380-023-01967-7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elvevåg, B., & Goldberg, T. E. (2000). Cognitive impairment in schizophrenia is the core of the disorder. Critical Reviews in Neurobiology, 14, 121.10.1615/CritRevNeurobiol.v14.i1.10CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Etchecopar-Etchart, D., Korchia, T., Loundou, A., Llorca, P. M., Auquier, P., Lançon, C., … Fond, G. (2021). Comorbid major depressive disorder in schizophrenia: A systematic review and meta-analysis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 47, 298308.10.1093/schbul/sbaa153CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Faust, D., & Miner, R. A. (1986). The empiricist and his new clothes: DSM-III in perspective. American Journal of Psychiatry, 143, 962967.Google Scholar
Feinstein, A. R. (1970). The pre-therapeutic classification of co-morbidity in chronic disease. Journal of Chronic Diseases, 23, 455468.10.1016/0021-9681(70)90054-8CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
First, M. B. (2005). Mutually exclusive versus co-occurring diagnostic categories: The challenge of diagnostic comorbidity. Psychopathology, 38, 206210.10.1159/000086093CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Frances, A. J., Widiger, T., & Fyer, M. R. (1990). The influence of classification methods on comorbidity. In Maser, J. D. & Cloninger, C. R. (Eds.), Comorbidity of mood and anxiety disorders (pp. 4159). Washington: American Psychiatric Press, Inc.Google Scholar
Henriksen, M. G., Raballo, A., & Nordgaard, J. (2021). Self-disorders and psychopathology: A systematic review. The Lancet Psychiatry, 8, 10011012.10.1016/S2215-0366(21)00097-3CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hyman, S. E. (2010). The diagnosis of mental disorders: The problem of reification. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 6, 155179.10.1146/annurev.clinpsy.3.022806.091532CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jablensky, A. (2004). The syndrome – an antidote to spurious comorbidity? World Psychiatry, 3, 2425.Google ScholarPubMed
Jablensky, A. (2005). Categories, dimensions and prototypes: Critical issues for psychiatric classification. Psychopathology, 38, 201205.10.1159/000086092CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jaspers, K. (1997). General psychopathology. London: John Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Kaplan, M. H., & Feinstein, A. R. (1974). The importance of classifying initial co-morbidity in evaluating the outcome of diabetes mellitus. Journal of Chronic Diseases, 27, 387404.10.1016/0021-9681(74)90017-4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendell, R., & Jablensky, A. (2003). Distinguishing between the validity and utility of psychiatric diagnoses. American Journal of Psychiatry, 160, 412.10.1176/appi.ajp.160.1.4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendell, R. E. (1975). The role of diagnosis in psychiatry. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.Google Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (1990). Toward a scientific psychiatric nosology. Strengths and limitations. Archives of General Psychiatry, 47, 969973.10.1001/archpsyc.1990.01810220085011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (2014). DSM issues: Incorporation of biological tests, avoidance of reification, and an approach to the ‘box canyon problem’. American Journal of Psychiatry, 171, 12481250.10.1176/appi.ajp.2014.14081018CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (2016 a). The phenomenology of major depression and the representativeness and nature of DSM criteria. American Journal of Psychiatry, 173, 771780.10.1176/appi.ajp.2016.15121509CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, K. S. (2016 b). Phenomenology of schizophrenia and the representativeness of modern diagnostic criteria. JAMA Psychiatry, 73, 10821092.10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2016.1976CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, K. S. (2022). Potential lessons for DSM from contemporary philosophy of science. JAMA Psychiatry, 79, 99100.10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2021.3559CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, K. S., & Zachar, P. (2008). The incredible insecurity of psychiatric nosology. In Kendler, K. S. & Parnas, J. (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry: Explanation, phenomenology, and nosology (pp. 368383). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.10.1353/book.98242CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klerman, G. L. (1990). Approaches to the phenomena of comorbidity. In Maser, J. D., & Cloninger, C. R. (Eds.), Comorbidity of mood and anxiety disorders (pp. 1337). Washington: American Psychiatric Press, Inc.Google Scholar
Leckman, J. F., Weissman, M. M., Merikangas, K. R., Pauls, D. L., & Prusoff, B. A. (1983). Panic disorder and major depression. Increased risk of depression, alcoholism, panic, and phobic disorders in families of depressed probands with panic disorder. Archives of General Psychiatry, 40, 10551060.10.1001/archpsyc.1983.01790090017002CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lieberman, J. A., Kane, J. M., & Alvir, J. (1987). Provocative tests with psychostimulant drugs in schizophrenia. Psychopharmacology, 91, 415433.10.1007/BF00216006CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lilienfeld, S. O., Sauvigné, K. C., Lynn, S. J., Cautin, R. L., Latzman, R. D., & Waldman, I. D. (2015). Fifty psychological and psychiatric terms to avoid: A list of inaccurate, misleading, misused, ambiguous, and logically confused words and phrases. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1100.10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01100CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lilienfeld, S. O., Waldman, I. D., & Israel, A. C. (1994). A critical examination of the use of the term and concept of comorbidity in psychopathology research. Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice, 1, 7183.Google Scholar
Maj, M. (2005 a). The aftermath of the concept of ‘psychiatric comorbidity’. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 74, 6768.10.1159/000083164CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maj, M. (2005 b). ‘Psychiatric comorbidity’: An artefact of current diagnostic systems? British Journal of Psychiatry, 186, 182184.10.1192/bjp.186.3.182CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maser, J. D., & Cloninger, C. R. (1990). Comorbidity of anxiety and mood disorders: Introduction and overview. In Maser, J. D., & Cloninger, C. R. (Eds.), Comorbidity of mood and anxiety disorders (pp. 312). Washington: American Psychiatric Press, Inc.Google Scholar
Meehl, P. E. (2001). Comorbidity and taxometrics. Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice, 8, 507519.Google Scholar
Mølstrøm, I.-M., Henriksen, M. G., & Nordgaard, J. (2020). Differential-diagnostic confusion and non-specificity of affective symptoms and anxiety: An empirical study of first-admission patients. Psychiatry Research, 291, 113302.10.1016/j.psychres.2020.113302CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Owen, G. (2023). What is formulation in psychiatry? Psychological Medicine, 53, 18.10.1017/S0033291723000016CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Parnas, J. (2011). A disappearing heritage: The clinical core of schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 37, 11211130.10.1093/schbul/sbr081CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pincus, H. A., Tew, J. D., & First, M. B. (2004). Psychiatric comorbidity: Is more less? World Psychiatry, 3, 1823.Google ScholarPubMed
Plana-Ripoll, O., Pedersen, C. B., Holtz, Y., Benros, M. E., Dalsgaard, S., de Jonge, P., … McGrath, J. J. (2019). Exploring comorbidity within mental disorders among a Danish National Population. JAMA Psychiatry, 259270.10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2018.3658CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rasmussen, A. R., & Parnas, J. (2022). What is obsession? Differentiating obsessive-compulsive disorder and the schizophrenia spectrum. Schizophrenia Research, 243, 18.10.1016/j.schres.2022.02.014CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Robins, E., & Guze, S. B. (1970). Establishment of diagnostic validity in psychiatric illness: Its application to schizophrenia. American Journal of Psychiatry, 126, 983987.10.1176/ajp.126.7.983CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Strålin, P., & Hetta, J. (2019). First episode psychosis and comorbid ADHD, autism and intellectual disability. European Psychiatry, 55, 1822.10.1016/j.eurpsy.2018.09.007CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trull, T. J., Scheiderer, E. M., & Tomko, R. L. (2012). Axis II comorbidity. In Widiger, T. A. (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of personality disorders (pp. 219236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
van Praag, H. M. (1996). Comorbidity (psycho) analysed. British Journal of Psychiatry Supplement, 30, 129134.10.1192/S0007125000298516CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vella, G., Aragona, M., & Alliani, D. (2000). The complexity of psychiatric comorbidity: A conceptual and methodological discussion. Psychopathology, 33, 2530.10.1159/000029115CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wakefield, J. C. (2016). Diagnostic issues and controversies in DSM-5: Return of the false positives problem. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 12, 105132.10.1146/annurev-clinpsy-032814-112800CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Widiger, T. A., & Ford-Black, M. M. (1994). Diagnoses and disorders. Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice, 1, 8487.Google Scholar
Wittchen, H. U. (1996). What is comorbidity – fact or artefact? British Journal of Psychiatry Supplement, 30, 78.10.1192/S0007125000298358CrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Health Organization (1992). The ICD-10 classification of mental and behavioural disorders: Clinical descriptions and diagnostic guidelines. Geneva: World Health Organization.Google Scholar
Wyrsch, J. (1930). Psychiatrie als Wissenschaft. Neue Schweizer Rundschau, 4, 284295.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure. 1. Illustration of state and trait conditions. (a) A state condition with a single episode of a disorder, e.g. major depression. (b) A state condition with recurring episodes, e.g. bipolar disorder. (c) A trait condition, e.g. schizophrenia. (d) A trait condition with a comorbid state condition, e.g. personality disorder with a single episode of major depression.