Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T15:06:12.306Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Letter to the Editor: Measuring and defining: the double role of the DSM criteria for psychiatric disorders

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 July 2017

H. M. van Loo*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry, University Medical Center Groningen, University of Groningen, Groningen, The Netherlands Department of Psychiatry, Virginia Institute for Psychiatric and Behavioral Genetics, Virginia Commonwealth University, Richmond, Virginia, USA
J.-W. Romeijn
Affiliation:
Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen, Groningen, The Netherlands
*
*Address for correspondence: H. M. van Loo, Department of Psychiatry, University Medical Center Groningen, University of Groningen, Hanzeplein 1, PO Box 30.001, Groningen 9700 RB, The Netherlands. (Email: [email protected])
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Correspondence
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

‘Should the criteria in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM) constitute or index psychiatric disorders?’ is the central question of ‘DSM disorders and their criteria: how should they inter-relate?’ (Kendler, Reference Kendler2017). In this review, Dr K.S. Kendler contrasts two possible relations between psychiatric disorders and the DSM criteria (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). First, Kendler argues for a purely indexical relation – DSM criteria are meant to measure psychiatric disorders, analogous to an electrocardiogram (ECG) measuring the presence of myocardial infarction. Thus, major depression is a hypothetical diagnostic construct, which we measure with our current DSM criteria with a certain sensitivity and specificity (Kendler, Reference Kendler2016, Reference Kendler2017). Second, Kendler argues against a constitutive relation between psychiatric disorders and the DSM criteria – the DSM criteria do not define what psychiatric disorders are. Kendler argues that this latter view might have adverse consequences for clinical care, teaching, research, and revision of the DSM criteria.

We fully agree with Kendler's plea for not taking DSM criteria as definitive or authoritative, and for an evaluation of patient characteristics beyond the DSM criteria. However, we disagree with the view that DSM criteria should exclusively be seen as means to measure, and not as attempts to define disorders. The DSM criteria need not be constrained to only one of these two roles, to the exclusion of the other. The DSM criteria serve both roles at once: the current DSM criteria for major depression offer a tentative definition of what depression is, and they simultaneously provide a measurement tool for it (van Loo & Romeijn, Reference van Loo and Romeijn2015). Moreover, we maintain that the hybrid nature of the DSM is beneficial to psychiatric science.

Historical and philosophical studies of science reveal that measurement techniques and theoretical structures are often developed in tandem. When there is an overlap of this kind, questions such as ‘What counts as a measurement of X?’ and ‘What is X?’ cannot be answered independently of each other (van Fraassen, Reference van Fraassen2008). The scientific concepts that measurement and theory rely on are in such cases used for indexical and constitutive purposes simultaneously. For example, the scientific understanding of temperature developed in close connection with the development of thermometers. The thermometer was part and parcel of this development in two distinct ways, namely by facilitating the measurement of heat, and by defining what heat is (Chang, Reference Chang2004). Another example is the use of the pendulum by Galileo in his study of motion (Van Dyck, Reference Van Dyck2005). Galileo used the pendulum to measure the motion of falling bodies, but at the same time, the pendulum secured the reference of Galileo's theoretical models, i.e. it contributed to a definition of the motion of free fall. Faraday's experiments on electromagnetism offer other examples of double roles for scientific concepts (Steinle, Reference Steinle1997).

In the philosophy of science, the double role of concepts shows up in the debate over so-called conventionalism. Conventions are bridge principles that coordinate concepts (e.g. depression) onto empirical reality (e.g. a population with a certain symptom profile). They are crucial for science: by associating concepts that belong to a theoretical representation with empirical reality, we make empirical reality and theoretical representations relevant for each other.

With this in mind, we turn our attention to medical science and in particular to disease concepts in psychiatry. Many of the current concepts in the DSM perform the mediating function of conventions (van Loo & Romeijn, Reference van Loo and Romeijn2015). The DSM criteria are used to measure the occurrence of mental disorders, and simultaneously they define these disorders, i.e. they serve as part of a representation of reality.

Importantly, psychiatry is by no means an exception within medical science. For instance, migraine is both defined and measured by criteria such as having more than five headache attacks lasting 4–72 h with specific qualities (pulsating quality, unilateral location, nausea, photophobia) (Headache Classification Committee of the International Headache Society (IHS), 2013). In that sense, depression and migraine are different from myocardial infarction, in which measurement procedures (biomarkers, ECG changes, imaging techniques) and definition do not overlap, at least at present (Thysegen et al. Reference Thysegen, Alpert, Jaffe, Simoons, Chaitman and White2012). To explain our point, we consider myocardial infarction in some more detail.

The current definition of myocardial infarction has developed from the pure symptom-based diagnosis angina pectoris in the eighteenth century: precordial pain, collapse, heart failure and sudden death (Leibowitz, Reference Leibowitz1970). Definition and measurement of angina pectoris at this point overlapped – there were no independent measurement procedures to assess it – similarly to migraine and major depression. In the nineteenth century, angina pectoris became connected with the presumed cause ‘coronary artery disease’. In the twentieth century, the interest shifted from the coronary vessels to the myocardium and the concept of myocardial infarction – myocardial cell death due to prolonged ischemia – became clearly separated from angina pectoris and arteriosclerosis as a separate disease entity. Currently, myocardial infarction can be assessed by a variety of independent measurement tools: ECG changes, imaging techniques, and cardiac biomarkers (Thysegen et al. Reference Thysegen, Alpert, Jaffe, Simoons, Chaitman and White2012).

This brief history suggests that research practice might benefit from the use of concepts that simultaneously function as index and definition. After all, we must have an idea of what we are targeting if we want to rethink how we measure our target. In saying we are merely rethinking indicators, we risk losing sight of what is being indicated. The hybrid nature of scientific concepts is conducive to making scientific discoveries. Accordingly, we propose that, in tentatively formulating criteria as indicators, we are at the same time gradually building up a representation of what these disorders are. In parallel to the development from angina pectoris to myocardial infarction, DSM criteria can be improved to offer increasingly accurate descriptions of what constitutes mental disorders.

It deserves emphasis that, while we might disagree with Kendler on the exclusively indexical role of the DSM criteria, we fully concur with his recommendations for psychiatric science. In particular, our claim about the double role for the DSM criteria does not entail that having a psychiatric disorder is nothing more than meeting the relevant criteria, or that these criteria are infallible. We endorse Kendler's plea for the tentativeness of the current DSM criteria and for a broader assessment of psychiatric disorders than by DSM criteria alone, in order to improve research, clinical practice, and classification.

Declaration of Interest

None.

References

American Psychiatric Association (APA) (2013). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition (DSM-5) . American Psychiatric Publishing: Washington DC.Google Scholar
Chang, H (2004). Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress. Oxford University Press: Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Headache Classification Committee of the International Headache Society (IHS) (2013). The international classification of headache disorders, 3rd edition (ICHD-3). Cephalalgia 33, 629808.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, KS (2016). The phenomenology of major depression and the representativeness and nature of DSM criteria. American Journal of Psychiatry 173, 771780.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, KS (2017). DSM disorders and their criteria: how should they inter-relate? Psychological Medicine 17. doi: 10.1017/S0033291717000678.Google ScholarPubMed
Leibowitz, JO (1970) The History of Coronary Heart Disease. University of California Press: Berkeley, Los Angeles.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinle, F (1997). Entering new fields: exploratory uses of experimentation. Philosophy of Science 64, 6574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thysegen, K, Alpert, JS, Jaffe, AS, Simoons, ML, Chaitman, BR, White, HD, The Writing Group on behalf of the Joint ESC/ACCF/AHA/WHF Task Force for the Universal Definition of Myocardial Infarction (2012). Third universal definition of myocardial infarction. Circulation 126, 20202035.Google Scholar
Van Dyck, M (2005). The paradox of conceptual novelty and Galileo's use of experiments. Philosophy of Science 72, 864875.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, BC (2008). Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective. Clarendon Press: Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Loo, HM, Romeijn, JW (2015). Psychiatric Comorbidity: fact or artifact? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 36, 4160.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed