Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T13:41:41.311Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Top-down causation in psychiatric disorders: a clinical-philosophical inquiry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 June 2021

Kenneth S. Kendler*
Affiliation:
Virginia Institute for Psychiatric and Behavioral Genetics, Virginia Commonwealth University, Richmond, VA, USA Department of Psychiatry, Virginia Commonwealth University, RichmondVA, USA
James Woodward
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA, USA
*
Author for correspondence: Kenneth S. Kendler, E-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Psychiatry has long debated whether the causes of mental illness can be better explained by reductionist or pluralistic accounts. Although the former relies on commonsense scientific bottom-up causal models, the latter (which typically include environmental, psychological, and/or socio-cultural risk factors) requires top-down causal processes often viewed with skepticism, especially by neuroscientists. We begin with four clinical vignettes which illustrate self-interventions wherein high-order psychological processes (e.g. religious beliefs or deep interpersonal commitments) appear to causally impact the risk for or the course of psychiatric/behavioral disorders. We then propose a model for how to understand this sort of top-down self-causation. Our model relies centrally on the concept of a control variable which, like a radio tuning dial, can implement a series of typically unknown physical processes to obtain the desired ends. We set this control variable in the context of an interventionist account of causation that assumes that a cause (C) produces an effect (E) when intervening on C (by manipulating it) is associated with a change in E. We extend this framework by arguing that certain psychological changes can result from individuals intervening on their own mental states and/or selection of environments. This in turn requires a conception of the self that contains mental capacities that are at least partially independent of one another. Although human beings cannot directly intervene on the neurobiological systems which instantiate risk for psychiatric illness, they can, via control variables at the psychological level, and/or by self-selection into protective environments, substantially alter their own risk.

Type
Review Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beck, A. T., & Alford, B. A. (2008). Depression: Causes and treatment (2nd ed.). State College, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Berridge, K. C., & Robinson, T. E. (2016). Liking, wanting, and the incentive-sensitization theory of addiction. American Psychologist, 71(8), 670.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, J. (2010). II – control variables and mental causation. Paper presented at the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cuijpers, P., Berking, M., Andersson, G., Quigley, L., Kleiboer, A., & Dobson, K. S. (2013). A meta-analysis of cognitive-behavioural therapy for adult depression, alone and in comparison with other treatments. The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 58(7), 376385.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dutra, L., Stathopoulou, G., Basden, S. L., Leyro, T. M., Powers, M. B., & Otto, M. W. (2008). A meta-analytic review of psychosocial interventions for substance use disorders. American Journal of Psychiatry, 165(2), 179187. doi: appi.ajp.2007.06111851 [pii];10.1176/appi.ajp.2007.06111851 [doi].CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eisenberg, L. (1986). Mindlessness and brainlessness in psychiatry. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 148(5), 497508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harburg, E., Davis, D. R., & Caplan, R. (1982). Parent and offspring alcohol use; imitative and aversive transmission. Journal of Studies on Alcohol, 43(5), 497516. Retrieved from http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/7144182.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harburg, E., DiFranceisco, W., Webster, D. W., Gleiberman, L., & Schork, A. (1990). Familial transmission of alcohol use: II. Imitation of and aversion to parent drinking (1960) by adult offspring (1977) – Tecumseh, Michigan. Journal of Studies on Alcohol, 51(3), 245256. Retrieved from http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/2342364.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Honyashiki, M., Furukawa, T. A., Noma, H., Tanaka, S., Chen, P., Ichikawa, K., … Caldwell, D. M. (2014). Specificity of CBT for depression: A contribution from multiple treatments meta-analyses. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 38(3), 249260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (2005). Toward a philosophical structure for psychiatry. American Journal of Psychiatry, 163(3), 433440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (2012a). The dappled nature of causes of psychiatric illness: Replacing the organic-functional/hardware-software dichotomy with empirically based pluralism. Molecular Psychiatry, 17(4), 377388. doi: 10.1038/mp.2011.182CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (2012b). Decision making in the pathway from genes to psychiatric and substance use disorders. Molecular Psychiatry, 18(6), 640645. doi: mp2012151 [pii];10.1038/mp.2012.151 [doi].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kendler, K. S. (2014). The structure of psychiatric science. American Journal of Psychiatry, 171(9), 931938. doi: 1873859 [pii];10.1176/appi.ajp.2014.13111539 [doi].CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendler, K. S., & Campbell, J. (2009). Interventionist causal models in psychiatry: Repositioning the mind-body problem. Psychological Medicine, 39(6), 881887. Retrieved from http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/18845010.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mitchell, S. D. (2003). Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1970). Deciding to believe. In Kiefer, H. E. & Munitz, M. K. (Eds.), Language, belief, and metaphysics (pp. 95111). Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen (P. Humphreys Ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar