Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T08:06:57.940Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What is ‘Normal‘? An Evolution-Theoretic Foundation for Normic Laws and Their Relation to Statistical Normality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Gerhard Schurz*
Affiliation:
University of Erfurt
*
Send requests for reprints to the author, Universität Erfurt, Postfach 900221, D-99006 Erfurt, Germany; e-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Normic laws have the form “if A, then normally B.” They are omnipresent in everyday life and non-physical ‘life’ sciences such as biology, psychology, social sciences, and humanities. They differ significantly from ceteris-paribus laws in physics. While several authors have doubted that normic laws are genuine laws at all, others have argued that normic laws express a certain kind of prototypical normality which is independent of statistical majority. This paper presents a foundation for normic laws which is based on generalized evolution theory and explains their omnipresence, lawlikeness, and reliability. It is argued that the fact that normic laws are a product of evolution must establish a systematic connection between prototypical and statistical normality.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Work on this paper was supported by the Research Grant F012 of the FWF, Austria. For valuable help I am indebted to two anonymous referees.

References

Adams, Ernest W. (1975), The Logic of Conditionals. Dordrecht: Reidel.10.1007/978-94-015-7622-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basalla, George (1988), The Evolution of Technology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bigelow, John and Pargetter, Robert (1987), “Function”, Journal of Philosophy 84(4): 181196.Google Scholar
Blackmore, Susan (2000), The Meme Machine. Oxford: Oxford Paperbacks.Google Scholar
Boyd, Robert and Richerson, Peter J. (1985), Culture and the Evolutionary Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1989), Nature's Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cavalli-Sforza, Luigi and Feldman, Marcus W. (1981), Cultural Transmission and Evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Dawkins, Richard (1989), The Selfish Gene, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dray, William (1957), Laws and Explanation in History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, John (1986), A Primer on Determinism. Dordrecht: Reidel.10.1007/978-94-010-9072-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabbay, Dov M., Hogger, C. J., and Robinson, J. A. (eds.) (1994), Nonmonotonic Reasoning and Uncertain Reasoning. Vol. 3 of Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen J. and Lewontin, Richard C. (1979), “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm”, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 205: 581598.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. (1988), “Provisos”, in Grünbaum, Adolf and Salmon, Wesley C. (eds.), The Limitations of Deductivism. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1936.Google Scholar
Hull, David L. (1982), “The Naked Meme”, in Plotkin, Henry C. (ed.), Learning. Development and Culture. Chichester: Wiley, 1950.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1993), “Function and Design”, in Allen, Collin et al. (eds.), Nature's Purposes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 479504.Google Scholar
Laurier, Daniel (1996), “Function, Normality, and Temporality”, in Marion, Mathieu and Cohen, Robert S. (eds.), Québec Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2552.10.1007/978-94-009-0113-1_3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mainardi, Danilo (1980), “Tradition and Social Transmission of Behaviour in Animals”, in Barlow, George and Silverberg, James (eds.), Sociobiology: Beyond Nature-Nurture? Boulder, CO: Westview, 227255.Google Scholar
May, Robert M. (1987), “Chaos and the Dynamics of Biological Populations”, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A 413: 2744.Google Scholar
McCarthy, John (1986), “Application of Circumscription to Formalizing Common-Sense Knowledge”, Artificial Intelligence 13: 89116.10.1016/0004-3702(86)90032-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1984), Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1989), White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Ernest (1977), “Teleology Revisited”, Journal of Philosophy 74(5): 261279.Google Scholar
Neander, Karen (1991), “Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defense”, Philosophy of Science 58: 168184.10.1086/289610CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearl, Judea (1988), Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems. Santa Mateo: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
Reiter, Raymond (1987), “Nonmonotonic Reasoning”, Annual Review of Computer Science, Vol. 2. Palo Alto: Annual Reviews Inc., 147186.Google Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas (1994), Philosophical Standardism. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.10.2307/j.ctt5vkgm4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ridley, Mark (1993), Evolution. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard (1998), “Probabilistic Semantics for Delgrande's Conditional Logic”, Artificial Intelligence 102(1): 8195.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard (1999), “Explanation as Unification”, Synthese 120(1): 95114.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard (2001a), “Pietroski and Rey on Ceteris Paribus Laws”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52: 359370.10.1093/bjps/52.2.359CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard (2001b), “Ceteris Paribus Laws. A Logico-Philosophical Deconstruction”, unpublished paper.Google Scholar
Scriven, Michael (1959), “Truisms as Grounds for Historical Explanations”, in Gardiner, Patrick (ed.), Theories of History. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1993), Philosophy of Biology. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Wachbroit, Robert (1994), “Normality as a Biological Concept”, Philosophy of Science 61: 579591.10.1086/289823CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Larry (1976), Teleological Explanations. Berkeley: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520333697CrossRefGoogle Scholar