Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T18:19:09.008Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A New Condition for Agglomeration in Bayesian Confirmation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 November 2024

Jakob Koscholke*
Affiliation:
Goethe-University Frankfurt am Main, Germany
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Bayesian confirmation does not generally agglomerate over conjunction. That is, whenever a piece of evidence $E$ confirms two hypotheses ${H_1}$ and ${H_2}$ individually, it does not follow that $E$ also confirms them conjunctively. Here, I present a condition under which the latter does follow from the former. But this new condition reveals a surprising fact: Bayesian confirmation agglomerates over conjunction whenever the evidence in question also confirms that both target hypotheses are false.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

According to Bayesian confirmation theory, a piece of evidence $E$ confirms two hypotheses ${H_1}$ and ${H_2}$ individually if and only if $E$ makes each of them more likely to be true (Fitelson Reference Fitelson2001; Strevens Reference Strevens2017). That is, the following two inequalities are satisfied:

(1) $$P({H_1}|E) \gt P\left( {{H_1}} \right){\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_2}|E) \gt P\left( {{H_2}} \right).$$

This conception of confirmation is perhaps the most popular currently on the market. But it is a well-known fact, presumably first noted by Carnap (Reference Carnap1950), that confirmation, thus understood, does not always agglomerate over conjunction (the label is from Leitgeb Reference Leitgeb2013). That is, condition (1) does not entail that

(2) $$P({H_1} \wedge {H_2}|E) \gt P\left( {{H_1} \wedge {H_2}} \right).$$

To see this more clearly, consider sampling a card from a standard deck. Let $E$ be that the card is red, ${H_1}$ that it is a heart, and ${H_2}$ that it is a diamond (Roche Reference Roche2012). Here, the agglomeration antecedent (1) is satisfied but the consequent (2) is not.Footnote 1

Still, there are conditions under which Bayesian confirmation does agglomerate over conjunction, i.e., conditions under which (1) does entail (2). And in this paper, I would like to present a new one. This new condition will, however, turn out somewhat puzzling. I will introduce it in section 2 and point out in section 3 that a precursor can already be found in the work of Carnap and Salmon. I then discuss an objection in section 4 and examine how the new condition relates to previous agglomeration conditions in section 5. Finally, I conclude in section 6.

2. NOR-confirmation

The new agglomeration condition I would like to present is the following:

(3) $$P(\neg {H_1} \wedge \neg {H_2}|E) \gt P\left( {\neg {H_1} \wedge \neg {H_2}} \right).$$

Less formally, it states that the evidence in question $E$ confirms that neither hypothesis ${H_1}$ nor ${H_2}$ is true, or, equivalently, that both target hypotheses are false. Due to the obvious relationship to Peirce’s (Reference Peirce, Hartshorne and Weiss1933) NOR-connective ${H_1} \downarrow {H_2}$ , I will call condition (3) NOR-confirmation.

Intuitively, NOR-confirmation (3) is at odds with both the agglomeration antecedent (1) and the consequent (2). After all, the two latter conditions state that the evidence in question $E$ confirms that both target hypotheses ${H_1}$ and ${H_2}$ are true, namely individually and conjunctively. It might therefore come as a surprise that NOR-confirmation (3) guarantees that agglomeration is valid for Bayesian confirmation. That is, whenever (3) holds, (1) entails (2). For a proof, first observe that (3) is equivalent toFootnote 2

$$P({H_1} \vee {H_2}|E) \lt P\left( {{H_1} \vee {H_2}} \right),$$

which, by general additivity, expands to

$$P({H_1}|E) + P({H_2}|E) - P({H_1} \wedge {H_2}|E) \lt P\left( {{H_1}} \right) + P\left( {{H_2}} \right) - P\left( {{H_1} \wedge {H_2}} \right).$$

By simple algebra, this is equivalent to

$$P({H_1}|E) - P\left( {{H_1}} \right) + P({H_2}|E) - P\left( {{H_2}} \right) \lt P({H_1} \wedge {H_2}|E) - P\left( {{H_1} \wedge {H_2}} \right),$$

and, by condition (1), the following equivalent of (2) follows:

$$0 \lt P({H_1} \wedge {H_2}|E) - P\left( {{H_1} \wedge {H_2}} \right).$$

To see that NOR-confirmation (3) is a non-trivial condition for agglomeration, i.e., (3) is consistent with (1), consider an urn containing ten balls with three binary attributes, distributed as shown in Table 1. Let the evidence $E$ be that a randomly drawn ball is blue, ${H_1}$ that it is small, and ${H_2}$ that it is clean. Then, NOR-confirmation (3) is satisfied, i.e., the evidence confirms that the drawn ball is not small and not clean:

$$P(\neg {H_1} \wedge \neg {H_2}|E) = 4/10 \gt P\left( {\neg {H_1} \wedge \neg {H_2}} \right) = 3/10.$$

Table 1. Urn model under which NOR-confirmation (3), (1), and thus (2) are jointly satisfied

Dirty Clean
Big Small Big Small Total
Red 1 2 2 0 5
Blue 2 0 0 3 5
Total 3 2 2 3 10

The agglomeration antecedent (1) is satisfied, i.e., the evidence confirms that the drawn ball is small and clean individually,

$$\forall i \in 1,2:P({H_i}|E) = 6/10 \gt \left( {{H_i}} \right) = 5/10,$$

and hence the agglomeration consequent (2) is satisfied, i.e., the evidence confirms that the drawn ball is small and clean conjunctively:

$$P({H_1} \wedge {H_2}|E) = 6/10 \gt P\left( {{H_1} \wedge {H_2}} \right) = 3/10.$$

This shows that NOR-confirmation (3) is a non-trivial condition for agglomeration.

3. Carnap and Salmon

The observation that NOR-confirmation (3) and the agglomeration antecedent (1) are consistent is not entirely new: this fact was already noted implicitly by Carnap (Reference Carnap1950) and Salmon (Reference Salmon and Achinstein1983). The two authors discussed examples in which a piece of evidence $E$ confirms two hypotheses ${H_1}$ and ${H_2}$ individually while disconfirming their disjunction ${H_1} \vee {H_2}$ , the latter being equivalent to NOR-confirmation (3). What is new, however, is that this makes Carnap’s and Salmon’s examples rather peculiar instances of agglomeration. To see this more clearly, consider Salmon’s example:

[A] medical researcher finds evidence confirming the hypothesis that Jones is suffering from viral pneumonia and also confirming the hypothesis that Jones is suffering from bacterial pneumonia—yet this very same evidence disconfirms the hypothesis that Jones has pneumonia! It is difficult to entertain such a state of affairs, even as an abstract possibility. (Salmon Reference Salmon and Achinstein1983, section 3)Footnote 3

Salmon found the fact that such situations can arise “shocking and counterintuitive” (Salmon Reference Salmon and Achinstein1983, section 3). But he overlooked that being an instance of agglomeration, it follows that the evidence also confirms the hypothesis that Jones has viral and bacterial pneumonia. Just imagine the following dialogue:

Researcher: Mr. Jones, good to see you! I just received your lab results. I have some good and some bad news for you. The bad news is that the results confirm that you have viral pneumonia; and they also confirm that you have bacterial pneumonia.

Jones: Oh dear! So I have both viral and bacterial pneumonia?! That explains why I feel so miserable!

Researcher: Well, that is not quite what I said, Mr. Jones! In any case, the good news is that the results also confirm that you have neither viral nor bacterial pneumonia.

Jones: Wait, didn’t you just tell me the opposite? Do the results confirm that I have viral and bacterial pneumonia or do they confirm that I don’t?!

Researcher: Well, they confirm both, Mr. Jones, albeit in different ways.

Jones: How can this be? Is there something wrong with the lab results?

Researcher: No, I can assure you that our lab results are flawless and absolutely reliable. In fact, it follows that they also confirm that you have viral and bacterial pneumonia at the same time.

I suspect that most readers will find the researcher’s utterances confusing and unhelpful. Perhaps, some will even question the validity of her inference, arguing that the lab results should disconfirm the hypothesis that Jones has viral and bacterial pneumonia. But the researcher’s inference is valid and everything she says is consistent.Footnote 4

4. The rarity objection

One might try to relativize the phenomenon above by arguing that it is probably very rare. My response to this objection is twofold: I admit that the phenomenon is not very prevalent, but this does not make it less unsettling. More precisely, the conjunctive prevalence of cases where NOR-confirmation (3) and (1) are jointly satisfied is around 2.5%. And the conditional prevalence of cases where NOR-confirmation (3) is satisfied if (1) is satisfied is around 10%. This can be shown using Monte Carlo integration based on 10 million regular probability functions over an algebra generated by three variables (Metropolis and Ulam Reference Metropolis and Ulam1949). The left-hand graph in figure 1 shows how the prevalence stabilizes with increasing number of probability functions.

Figure 1. Prevalence of the NOR-effect (left) and the Simpson-effect (right).

To put these values into context, compare them with Simpson’s (Reference Simpson1951) paradox, a different but similarly puzzling probabilistic phenomenon where a piece of evidence $E$ confirms a hypothesis $H$ conditional on some assumption $X$ and conditional on $\neg X$ , but $E$ fails to confirm $H$ unconditionally (Sprenger and Weinberger Reference Sprenger, Weinberger and Edward2021). The conjunctive prevalence of such cases is only around 0.83%, and their conditional prevalence is around 3.33%, as shown on the right-hand side of figure 1. But the low prevalence of Simpson’s paradox has not kept researchers from finding the phenomenon unsettling. So, even if cases where NOR-confirmation (3) and the agglomeration antecedent (1) are jointly satisfied are rare, they are prevalent enough to care about.

5. Previous agglomeration conditions

NOR-confirmation (3) is not the only agglomeration condition for Bayesian confirmation. As Reichenbach (Reference Reichenbach1956) showed in his analysis of common-cause structures, agglomeration is also valid if the evidence screens off both hypotheses from each other:

(4) $$P({H_1}|E \wedge {H_2}) = P({H_1}|E){\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_1}|\neg E \wedge {H_2}) = P({H_1}|\neg E).$$

And, as Falk (Reference Falk1986) pointed out in his discussion of Cohen’s (Reference Cohen1977) corroboration theorem, agglomeration remains valid even if screening-off is relaxed as follows:Footnote 5

(5) $$P({H_1}|E \wedge {H_2}) \geqslant P({H_1}|E){\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_1}|\neg E \wedge {H_2}) \le P({H_1}|\neg E).$$

Salmon (Reference Salmon and Achinstein1983) uncovered another interesting condition. While agglomeration can also fail for independent hypotheses, it cannot if, additionally, the two target hypotheses are independent conditional on the evidence:

(6) $$P({H_1}|{H_2} \wedge E) = P({H_1}|E){\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_1}|{H_2}) = P\left( {{H_1}} \right).$$

Finally, there are two more recent conditions from the literature on the problem of irrelevant conjunction (Schurz Reference Schurz2022). The first is part of Fitelson’s (Reference Fitelson2002) confirmational irrelevance condition,

(7) $$P({H_2}|{H_1} \wedge E) = P\left( {{H_2}} \right){\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_2}|{H_1}) = P\left( {{H_2}} \right),$$

and the second is Hawthorne and Fitelson’s (Reference Hawthorne and Fitelson2004) conditional irrelevance condition which states that the evidence is irrelevant for one hypothesis conditional on the other:

(8) $$P({H_2}|{H_1} \wedge E) = P({H_2}|{H_1}).$$

Now, interestingly, NOR-confirmation (3) is logically independent of each of the aforementioned conditions (4)–(8). That is, NOR-confirmation (3) is consistent with each of them but neither entails nor is entailed by any of them. A proof of this statement is provided in Appendix A.

Notice, however, that most of these logical independence relationships break down once the agglomeration antecedent (1) is satisfied. More precisely, if (1) holds, then NOR-confirmation (3) is inconsistent with screening-off (4), full independence (6), confirmational irrelevance (7), and conditional irrelevance (8). A proof of this is provided in Appendix B. With these remarks, I close my discussion of NOR-confirmation (3).

6. Conclusion

In this short paper, I have presented a new condition under which Bayesian confirmation agglomerates over conjunction. One might think that such a condition is helpful because it allows us to establish claims about Bayesian confirmation without tedious case-by-case examination (Shogenji Reference Shogenji2003; Roche Reference Roche2012). But the condition presented here is more puzzling than helpful: it is difficult to see why Bayesian confirmation should agglomerate over conjunction whenever the new condition is satisfied. I hope that Bayesian confirmation theorists can help with an explanation.

Appendix

A. Logical independence

The probability distributions provided in Table 2 show that (3) is logically independent of (4) to (8). Under distribution 1, all conditions (3)–(8) are satisfied and thus none of them entails the negation of the other. Under distribution 2, NOR-confirmation (3) is satisfied while none of the other conditions is. And under distribution 3, NOR-confirmation (3) is violated while the other conditions are satisfied.

Table 2. Probability distributions showing that NOR-confirmation (3) is logically independent of (4)–(8)

$E$ ${H_1}$ ${H_2}$ Distribution 1 Distribution 2 Distribution 3
0 0 0 1/16 1/16 2/16
0 0 1 1/16 1/16 2/16
0 1 0 2/16 2/16 1/16
0 1 1 2/16 2/16 1/16
1 0 0 2/16 2/16 2/16
1 0 1 2/16 3/16 2/16
1 1 0 3/16 3/16 3/16
1 1 1 3/16 2/16 3/16

Distribution 1

Under this distribution, NOR-confirmation (3) is satisfied:

$$P({H_1} \vee {H_2}|E) = 8/10 \lt P\left( {{H_1} \vee {H_2}} \right) = 13/16.$$

Screening-off (4), and thus relaxed screening-off (5), are satisfied:

$$P({H_1}|{H_2} \wedge E) = P({H_1}|E) = 3/5{\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_1}|{H_2} \wedge \neg E) = P({H_1}|\neg E) = 1/2.$$

We also have

$$P({H_2}|{H_1} \wedge E) = P\left( {{H_2}} \right) = 1/2{\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_1}|{H_2}) = P\left( {{H_1}} \right) = 10/16.$$

Thus, full independence (6), confirmational irrelevance (7), and also conditional irrelevance (8) are satisfied.

Distribution 2

NOR-confirmation (3) is satisfied:

$$P({H_1} \vee {H_2}|E) = 8/10 \lt P\left( {{H_1} \vee {H_2}} \right) = 13/16.$$

Screening-off (4), relaxed screening-off (5), and full independence (6) are violated:

$$P({H_1}|{H_2} \wedge E) = 2/5 \lt P({H_1}|E) = 1/2.$$

Conditional irrelevance (8), and thus confirmational irrelevance (7), are violated:

$$P({H_2}|{H_1} \wedge E) = 2/5 \lt P({H_2}|{H_1}) = 5/9.$$

Distribution 3

NOR-confirmation (3) is violated:

$$P({H_1} \vee {H_2}|E) = 16/20 \gt P\left( {{H_1} \vee {H_2}} \right) = 12/16.$$

Screening-off (4), and thus relaxed screening-off (5), are satisfied:

$$P({H_1}|{H_2} \wedge E) = P({H_1}|E) = 3/5{\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_1}|{H_2} \wedge \neg E) = P({H_1}|\neg E) = 1/3.$$

We also have

$$P({H_2}|{H_1} \wedge E) = P\left( {{H_2}} \right) = 1/2{\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_1}|{H_2}) = P\left( {{H_1}} \right) = 1/2.$$

Thus, full independence (6), confirmational irrelevance (7), and also conditional irrelevance (8) are satisfied.

B. Breakdown of logical independence

If the agglomeration antecedent (1) is satisfied, then (3) is no longer logically independent of (4)–(8). More precisely, if (1) holds, then NOR-confirmation (3) and the agglomeration antecedent (1) jointly entail that the evidence $E$ confirms ${H_1}$ conditional on ${H_2}$ and that $E$ confirms ${H_2}$ conditional on ${H_1}$ :

$$P({H_1}|{H_2} \wedge E) \gt P({H_1}|{H_2}){\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_2}|{H_1} \wedge E) \gt P({H_2}|{H_1}).$$

The two conditions also entail that the evidence $E$ disconfirms ${H_1}$ conditional on $\neg {H_2}$ and that $E$ confirms ${H_2}$ conditional on $\neg {H_1}$ :

$$P({H_1}|\neg {H_2} \wedge E) \lt P({H_1}|\neg {H_2}){\rm{\;\;\;\;and\;\;\;\;}}P({H_2}|\neg {H_1} \wedge E) \lt P({H_2}|\neg {H_1}).$$

Together with screening-off (4) or full-independence (6), the second condition yields a contradiction. And together with confirmational irrelevance (7), and thus with conditional irrelevance (8), the first condition yields a contradiction.

Footnotes

1 Conditional probability $P(H|E)$ is defined as usual by $P\left( {H \wedge E} \right)/P\left( E \right)$ provided $P\left( E \right)\gt 0$ . To ensure well-definedness, I will tacitly assume that the relevant probabilities are non-extreme. Notice that the card example also shows that (1) neither entails that ${H_1}$ and ${H_2}$ are positively correlated unconditionally nor conditional on $E$ . That is, it neither follows from (1) that $P\left( {{H_1} \wedge {H_2}} \right) \gt P\left( {{H_1}} \right)P\left( {{H_2}} \right)$ nor that $P({H_1} \wedge {H_2}|E) \gt P({H_1}|E)P({H_2}|E)$ . The example also helps us to see that (1) does not entail that $E$ confirms the disjunction ${H_1} \vee {H_2}$ . That is, it does not follow from (1) that $P({H_1} \vee {H_2}|E) \gt P\left( {{H_1} \vee {H_2}} \right)$ . Simply let $E$ be that the drawn card is black, ${H_1}$ that it is not a heart, and ${H_2}$ that is not a diamond.

2 Notice that I am not arguing that the sufficiency of NOR-confirmation (3) for agglomeration is mathematically surprising. It is surprising from a confirmation-theoretic perspective. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pushing me to be more explicit here. Also notice that NOR-confirmation (3) and the agglomeration antecedent (1) entail more than just (2). For instance, they also entail that $E$ confirms the two material conditionals ${H_1} \supset {H_2}$ , ${H_2} \supset {H_1}$ and their conjunction ${H_1} \leftrightarrow {H_2}$ . And it also follows that $E$ confirms each hypothesis ${H_1}$ and ${H_2}$ conditional on the other, and that $E$ confirms each negated hypothesis $\neg {H_1}$ and $\neg {H_2}$ conditional on the other. See also section 5.

3 Atkinson et al.’s (Reference Atkinson, Peijnenburg and Kuipers2009) so-called Alan Author Effect is structurally equivalent to the phenomenon described by Salmon. The effect occurs when a piece of evidence $E$ confirms a conjunction ${H_1} \wedge {H_2}$ while disconfirming its conjuncts ${H_1}$ and ${H_2}$ individually. This is equivalent to confirming the negated hypotheses individually while disconfirming their disjunction.

4 Taking inspiration from Hempel (Reference Hempel1960), we might call cases where a single piece of evidence consistently confirms a number of jointly inconsistent hypotheses evidential inconsistencies. See also the phenomenon of floating conclusions where two contradicting lines of reasoning confirm the same conclusion (Makinson and Schlechta Reference Makinson and Schlechta1991; Horty Reference Horty2002).

5 Cohen’s condition (5) should not be confused with weak screening-off $P({H_1}|E \wedge {H_2}) \ge P({H_1}|E)$ and $P(H_1|\neg E\land H_2)\geq P(H_1|\neg E)$ (Atkinson and Peijnenburg Reference Atkinson and Peijnenburg2021). The two conditions only differ in the second conjunct. But (5) guarantees agglomeration while weak screening-off does not. And weak screening-off guarantees transitivity while (5) does not (Suppes Reference Suppes1986; Roche Reference Roche2012).

References

Atkinson, David and Peijnenburg, Jeanne. 2021. “A new condition for transitivity of probabilistic support.” Erkenntnis 85 (2):273–300. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00349-7 Google Scholar
Atkinson, David, Peijnenburg, Jeanne, and Kuipers, Theo. 2009. “How to confirm the conjunction of disconfirmed hypotheses.” Philosophy of Science 76 (1):121. doi: https://doi.org/10.1086/598164 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan. 1977. The Probable and the Provable. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falk, Arthur. 1986. “Cohen on corroboration.” Mind 95 (377):110–15. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCV.377.110 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitelson, Branden. 2001. “Studies in Bayesian confirmation theory.” PhD thesis, University of Wisconsin, Madison.Google Scholar
Fitelson, Branden. 2002. “Putting the irrelevance back into the problem of irrelevant conjunction.” Philosophy of Science 69 (4):611–22. doi: https://doi.org/10.1086/344624 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, James and Fitelson, Branden. 2004. “Discussion: Re-solving irrelevant conjunction with probabilistic independence.” Philosophy of Science 71 (4):505–14. doi: https://doi.org/10.1086/423626 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1960. “Inductive inconsistencies.” Synthese 12 (4):439–69. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00485428 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horty, John F. 2002. “Skepticism and floating conclusions.” Artificial Intelligence 135 (1–2):5572. doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0004-3702(01)00160-6 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leitgeb, Hannes. 2013. “A lottery paradox for counterfactuals without agglomeration.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (3):605–36. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12035 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Makinson, David and Schlechta, Karl. 1991. “Floating conclusions and zombie paths: Two deep difficulties in the ‘directly skeptical’ approach to defeasible inheritance nets.” Artificial Intelligence 48 (2):199–209. doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/0004-3702(91)90061-N CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Metropolis, Nicholas and Ulam, Stanislaw. 1949. “The Monte Carlo method.” Journal of the American Statistical Association 44 (247):335–41. doi: https://doi.org/10.1080/01621459.1949.10483310 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1933. “A Boolian algebra with one constant.” In Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. IV, The Simplest Mathematics, edited by Hartshorne, Charles and Weiss, Paul, pp. 1318. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans. 1956. The Direction of Time. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roche, William A. 2012. “A weaker condition for transitivity in probabilistic support.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (1):111–18. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-011-0033-7 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, Wesley C. 1983. “Confirmation and relevance.” In The Concept of Evidence, edited by Achinstein, Peter. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard. 2022. “Tacking by conjunction, genuine confirmation and convergence to certainty.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 (3):118. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-022-00470-0 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shogenji, Tomoji. 2003. “A condition for transitivity in probabilistic support.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (4):613–16. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/54.4.613 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simpson, Edward H. 1951. “The interpretation of interaction in contingency tables.” Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series B 13 (2):238–41. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2517-6161.1951.tb00088.x CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sprenger, Jan and Weinberger, Naftali. 2021. “Simpson’s paradox.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward, N. Zalta. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2017. “Notes on Bayesian confirmation theory.” Available at: http://www.strevens.org/bct/BCT.pdf Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick. 1986. “Non-Markovian causality in the social sciences with some theorems on transitivity.” Synthese 68:129–40. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00413969 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Urn model under which NOR-confirmation (3), (1), and thus (2) are jointly satisfied

Figure 1

Figure 1. Prevalence of the NOR-effect (left) and the Simpson-effect (right).

Figure 2

Table 2. Probability distributions showing that NOR-confirmation (3) is logically independent of (4)–(8)