Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T18:49:01.287Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explanation, Emergence, and Quantum Entanglement

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

This paper tries to get a grip on two seemingly conflicting intuitions about reductionism in quantum mechanics. On one hand it is received wisdom that quantum mechanics puts an end to ‘reductionism’. Quantum entanglement is responsible for such features of quantum mechanics as holism, the failure of supervenience, and emergence. While I agree with these claims, I will argue that it is only part of the story. Quantum mechanics provides us with thoroughgoing reductionist explanations. I will distinguish two kinds of microexplanation (or micro-‘reduction’). I will argue that even though quantum entanglement provides an example of the failure of one kind of microexplanation, it does not affect the other. Contrary to a recent paper by Kronz and Tiehen, I claim that the explanation of the dynamics of quantum mechanical systems is just as reductionist as it used to be in classical mechanics.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This paper was presented in Paris at a conference on reduction and emergence in November 2003. I would like to thank Anouk Barberousse, Max Kistler, and Soazig Le Bihan for helpful criticism and suggestions. Further thanks go to Alexander Altland and Claus Kiefer for valuable comments on separable and nonseparable Hamiltonians.

References

Ashcroft, N. W., and Mermin, N. D. (1976), Solid State Physics. Philadelphia: CBS Publishing Asia.Google Scholar
Bohm, Arno (1986), Quantum Mechanics: Foundations and Applications. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, Charles D. (1925), Mind and Its Place in Nature. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1989), Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Healey, Richard (1991), “Holism and Nonseparability”, Holism and Nonseparability 88:393421.Google Scholar
Hellman, Geoffrey, and Thompson, Frank (1975), “Physicalism: Ontology, Determination, Reduction”, Physicalism: Ontology, Determination, Reduction 72:551564.Google Scholar
Humphreys, Paul (1997), “How Properties Emerge”, How Properties Emerge 64:117.Google Scholar
Hüttemann, Andreas (1998), “Laws and Dispositions”, Laws and Dispositions 65:121135.Google Scholar
Hüttemann, Andreas (2004), What’s Wrong with Microphysicalism? London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, J. B. (1995), “On the Empirical Foundations of the Quantum No-Signalling Proofs”, On the Empirical Foundations of the Quantum No-Signalling Proofs 62:543560.Google Scholar
Kronz, Frederick, and Tiehen, Justin (2002), “Emergence and Quantum Mechanics”, Emergence and Quantum Mechanics 69:324347.Google Scholar
Maudlin, Tim (1998), “Part and Whole in Quantum Mechanics”, in Castellani, Elena (ed.), Interpreting Bodies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 4660.Google Scholar
Mellor, Hugh, and Crane, Tim (1990), “There Is No Question of Physicalism”, There Is No Question of Physicalism 99:185206.Google Scholar
Redhead, Michael (1990), “Explanation”, in Knowles, Dudley (ed.), Explanation and Its Limits. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 135154.Google Scholar
Teller, Paul (1992), “A Contemporary Look at Emergence”, in Beckermann, Ansgar, Flohr, Hans, and Kim, Jaegwon (eds.), Emergence or Reduction. Berlin: Springer, 139153.Google Scholar