Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T21:35:34.846Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Can a Historian of Science Be a Scientific Realist?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Theodore Arabatzis*
Affiliation:
University of Athens
*
Send requests for reprints to the author, Department of Philosophy and History of Science, University of Athens, Panepistimioupolis (Ano Ilisia), GR-157 71 Athens, Greece; e-mail: [email protected].

Abstract

In this paper I address some of the problems that the historical development of science poses for a realist and discuss whether a realist construal of scientific activity is conducive to historiographical practice. First, I discuss, by means of historical examples, Ian Hacking's defense of entity realism. Second, I try to show, drawing on Kuhn's recent work on incommensurability, that the realism problem is relevant to historiography and that a realist position entails a particular historiographical strategy, which faces problems. Finally, I suggest that for historiographical purposes an agnostic attitude with respect to scientifictheories and unobservable entities is the most appropriate.

Type
History and Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to Tara Abraham, Kostas Gavroglu, Oma Harari-Eshel, Annette Imhausen, Christophe Lecuyer, Eman McMullin, Massimo Mazzotti, Nancy Nersessian, Elizabeth Paris, Stathis Psillos, Erdinc Sayan, Jutta Schickore, Bas van Fraassen, and Andre Wakefield for discussion and comments.

References

Arabatzis, Theodore (1995), The Electron: A Biographical Sketch of a Theoretical Entity. Ph.D. Dissertation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University.Google Scholar
Arabatzis, Theodore (1996), “Rethinking the ‘Discovery’ of the Electron”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27: 405435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arabatzis, Theodore (1998), “How the Electrons Spend their Leisure Time: Philosophical Reflections on a Controversy between Chemists and Physicists”, in Janich, Peter and Psarros, Nikolaos (eds.), The Autonomy of Chemistry and its Relationship to the Other Natural Sciences. Würzburg: Königshausen and Neumann, 149159.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul (1960), “Das Problem der Existenz theoretischer Entitäten”, in Topitsch, Ernst (ed.), Probleme der Wissenschaftstheorie: Festschrift für Victor Kraft. Vienna: Springer-Verlag, 3572.10.1007/978-3-662-25138-6_2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin, Allan (1996), “The are no anti-realists in the laboratory”, in Cohen, Robert S., Hilpinen, Risto, and Renzong, Qiu (eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 169. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 131149.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1983), Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1984), “Experimentation and Scientific Realism”, in Leplin, Jarrett (ed.), Scientific Realism. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 154172.10.1525/9780520337442-009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1993), “Working in a New World: The Taxonomic Solution”, in Horwich 1993, 275310.Google Scholar
Hardin, Clyde L. and Rosenberg, Alexander (1982), “In Defense of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science 49: 604615.10.1086/289080CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holmes, Frederic L. (1989), Eighteenth-Century Chemistry as an Investigative Enterprise. Berkeley: Office for History of Science and Technology, University of California.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul (ed.) (1993), World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1982), “Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability”, in Asquith, Peter D. and Nickles, Thomas (eds.), PSA 1982, Vol. 2. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association, 669688.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1989), “Possible Worlds in History of Science”, in Allén, Sture (ed.), Possible Worlds in Humanities, Arts, and Sciences. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, 932.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1993), “Afterwords”, in Horwich 1993, 311341.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000), The Road since Structure. Edited by James Conant and John Haugeland. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1984), “Discussion: Realism without the Real”, Philosophy of Science 51:156162.10.1086/289171CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, Margaret (1990), “Theory, Intervention and Realism”, Synthese 82:122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newton-Smith, William H. (1990), “Realism”, in Olby, Robert C., Cantor, Geoffrey N., Christie, John R. R., and Hodge, Michael J. S. (eds.), Companion to the History of Modern Science. London: Routledge, 181195.Google Scholar
Psillos, Stathis (1999), Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1975a), Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1975b), Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar