Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T17:51:40.069Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reduction, Elimination, and the Mental

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Justin Schwartz*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Ohio State University

Abstract

The antireductionist arguments of many philosophers (e.g., Baker, Fodor and Davidson) are motivated by a worry that successful reduction would eliminate rather than conserve the mental. This worry derives from a misunderstanding of the empiricist account of reduction, which, although it does not underwrite “cognitive suicide”, should be rejected for its positivist baggage. Philosophy of psychology needs more detailed attention to issues in natural science which serve as analogies for reduction of the mental. I consider a range of central cases, including water and H2O, genes and DNA, and common sense and scientific solidity. The last case is illuminated by Eddington's Two Tables paradox, a resolution which suggests the plasticity of the mental under reduction. If reduction of the mental is like any of these cases, it is neither empiricist nor eliminative.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1991 The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Jaegwon Kim started me on this project by arguing forcefully that reduction is eliminative. Robert Van Gulik commented helpfully on an earlier draft of the paper at the 1989 meeting of the American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division. I am indebted for incisive comments to two anonymous referees for Philosophy of Science, to Alan Gibbard, David Hills, Stewart Shapiro, and especially to Peter Railton. This paper would be rather more unsatisfactory than it is without the patient assistance of a number of scientists: Daniel Axelrod (physics), Miriam Greenberg (biology), John Loeser (chemistry), and Benjamin Schwartz (mathematics). It goes without saying they are not responsible for errors that remain, but I will say it anyway.

References

Baker, L. R. (1987), Saving Belief: A Critique of Physicalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bonevec, D. (1982), Reduction in the Abstract Sciences. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1979), Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1981), “Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes”, The Journal of Philosophy 78: 6790.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1980), Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Eddington, A. (1958), The Nature of the Physical World. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Eisberg, R. and Resnik, R. (1974), Quantum Physics of Atoms, Molecules, Solids, Nuclei, and Particles. New York: Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. (1981), Philosophical Papers. Vol. 1, Realism, Rationalism, and Scientific Method. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139171526CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1973), “Theory Change and the Indeterminacy of Reference”, The Journal of Philosophy 70: 462481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1981), Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L. (1974), Philosophy of Biological Science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L. (1984), “Informal Aspects of Theory Reduction”, in E. Sober (ed.), Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology: An Anthology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 462476.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1980), “Physicalism and the Multiple Realizability of Mental States”, in N. Block (ed.), Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 234236.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Pa. (1980), “Discussion: How to Reduce A Functional Psychology?”, Philosophy of Science 47: 134140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Ph. (1984), “1953 and All That. A Tale of Two Sciences”, The Philosophical Review 93: 335373.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nagel, E. (1961), The Structure of Science; Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World.Google Scholar
Nagel, E. (1979), Teleology Revisited and Other Essays in the Philosophy and History of Science. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1973), “Two Concepts of Intertheoretic Reduction”, The Journal of Philosophy 70: 181201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1977), “Heuristics and Justification in Scientific Research: Comments on Shapere”, in F. Suppe (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Theories, 2d ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, pp. 571589.Google Scholar
Oxtoby, D. W. and Nachtrieb, N. H. (1986), Principles of Modern Chemistry. Philadelphia: Saunders.Google Scholar
Pauling, L. (1960), The Nature of the Chemical Bond and the Structure of Molecules and Crystals: An Introduction to Modern Structural Chemistry, 3d ed. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), Philosophical Papers. Vol. 2, Mind, Language and Reality. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1961), From A Logical Point of View; 9, Logico-Philosophical Essays. 2d ed. Revised. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Railton, P. (1980), “Explaining Explanation: A Realist Account of Scientific Explanation and Understanding”. Ph.D. Dissertation, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Railton, P. (1988), “A Deductive-Nomological Model of Probabilistic Explanation”, in J. C. Pitt (ed.), Theories of Explanation. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 119135.Google Scholar
Richardson, R. C. (1979), “Functionalism and Reductionism”, Philosophy of Science 46: 533558.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, R. (1971), “Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories”, in D. M. Rosenthal (ed.), Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, pp. 174199.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (1984), Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Schaffner, K. (1967), “Approaches to Reduction”, Philosophy of Science 34: 137147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, J. (1988), “The Coherence of Cognitive Suicide”, unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Schwartz, J. (forthcoming), “Who's Afraid of Multiple Realizability? Reductionism, Functionalism, and Connectionism”, in J. Dinsmore (ed.), Closing the Gap: Symbolic vs. Subsymbolic Processing. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1967–68), “Types of Inter-Theoretic Reduction”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18: 109124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J. C. C. (1971), “Sensations and Brain Processes”, in D. M. Rosenthal (ed.), Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, pp. 5366.Google Scholar
Spector, M. (1978), Concepts of Reduction in Physical Science. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, J. (1977), The Molecular Biology of the Gene, 3d ed. New York: Benjamin.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. (1976), “Reductionism, Levels of Organization, and the Mind-Body Problem”, in G. Globus, G. Maxwell and I. Savodnik (eds.), Consciousness and the Brain; A Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry. New York: Plenum Press, pp. 205267.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. (1984), “Reductive Explanation: A Functional Account”, in E. Sober (ed.), Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology: An Anthology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 477508.Google Scholar