Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T23:27:24.612Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Frankfurter in Königsberg: Prolegomenon to any Future non-metaphysical Kant

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 December 2020

James Gordon Finlayson*
Affiliation:
University of Sussex

Abstract

In this article I press four different objections on Forst’s theory of the ‘Right to Justification’. These are (i) that the principle of justification is not well-formulated; (ii) that ‘reasonableness and reciprocity’, as these notions are used by Rawls, are not apt to support a Kantian conception of morality; (iii) that the principle of justification, as Forst understands it, gives an inadequate account of what makes actions wrong; and (iv) that, in spite of his protestations to the contrary, Forst’s account veers towards a version of moral realism that is prima facie incompatible with Kantian constructivism. I then evaluate Forst’s theory in the light of a distinction made by Sharon Street between restricted and unrestricted constructivism. I show that Forst has reason to deny that it is either the one or the other, but he is not able to show that it is both or neither. I conclude that the arguments Forst advances in support of his constructivist theory of the right to justification entail that it is a metaphysical and comprehensive conception in the relevant, Rawlsian sense. Forst’s theory of the right to justification therefore fails to fulfil one of the main stated aims.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Kantian Review

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aristotle (1957) Politica. Ed. Ross, W. D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Caney, Simon (2014) ‘Justice and the Right to Justification’. In Rainer, Forst (ed.), Justice Democracy and the Right to Justification (London: Bloomsbury), 147–69.Google Scholar
Dreben, Burton (2003) ‘On Rawls and Political Liberalism’. In Samuel, Freeman (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 316–46.Google Scholar
Finlayson, James G. (2000) ‘Modernity and Morality in Habermas’s Discourse Ethics’. Inquiry, 43 (3), 319–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlayson, James G. (2019) The Habermas-Rawls Debate. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forst, Rainer (2012) The Right to Justification: Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice. Trans. Jeffrey Flynn (New York: Columbia University Press).Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer (2014) Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer (2017) ‘Political Liberalism: A Kantian View’. Ethics, 128 (1), 123–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freyenhagen, F. (2011) ‘Taking Reasonable Pluralism Seriously: An Internal Critique of Political Liberalism’. Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 10 (3), 323–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen (1990) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen (2011) ‘“Reasonable” versus “True”, or the Morality of Worldviews’. In Finlayson, J. G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds), Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political (New York: Routledge), 92113.Google Scholar
Heath, Joseph (2011) ‘Justice: Trancendental, Not Metaphysical’. In Finlayson, J. G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds), Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political (New York: Routledge), 117–49.Google Scholar
Hooker, Brad (2003) ‘Scanlon’s Contractualism, the Spare Wheel Objection, and Aggregation’. In Matt, Matravers (ed.), Scanlon and Contractualism (Southgate: Frank Cass), 5377.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1986) Critique of Practical Reason. Trans. Lewis White Beck. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
McDowell, John. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John (1995) ‘Political Liberalism: Reply to Habermas’. Journal of Philosophy, 92 (3), 132–80. Reprinted in Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press 2005), 372–435.Google Scholar
Rawls, John (2005) Political Liberalism, expanded ed. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Reath, Andrews, and Timmerman, Jens (eds) (2010) Kant’s ‘Critique of Practical Reason’: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea (2014) ‘Scottish Constructivism and the Right to Justification’. In Rainer, Forst (ed.), Justice, Democracy and the Right to Justification: Rainer Forst in Dialogue (London: Bloomsbury), 2965.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998) What we Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sibley, William M. (1953) ‘The Rational versus the Reasonable’. Philosophical Review, 62 (4), 554–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skorupski, John (2017) ‘Rawls, Liberalism and Democracy’. Ethics, 128 (1), 173–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Street, Sharon (2010) ‘What is Constructivism in Ethics and Metaethics?’. Philosophy Compass, 5 (5), 363–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, Michael J. (2008) Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, Judith J. (1990) The Realm of Rights. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar