Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T11:15:33.476Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Recognising the recognition heuristic for what it is (and what it’s not)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Ben R. Newell*
Affiliation:
School of Psychology, University of New South Wales, Sydney, 2052, Australia
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The diversity, ingenuity and differences of opinion displayed in the articles of the recent special issues on the recognition heuristic are testament to the power and theoretical fertility of a simple idea about the role of recognition in decision making. In this brief comment I mention a number of these papers, but my focus is on points of agreement and disagreement with the conclusions drawn by Gigerenzer and Goldstein (2011) in their review of a decade’s worth of research on the recognition heuristic.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2011] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Less is more—more or less

Discovering that a higher degree of familiarity with a domain (e.g., the cities of one’s own country vs. those of another) can lead to poorer inferential accuracy is an important insight. It is no wonder the aptly titled “More or Less” BBC radio show wished to demonstrate the effect to its listeners. It is robust, exceedingly simple to demonstrate (as I and I am sure many of us do regularly in undergraduate lectures) and—at least initially—counterintuitive. The conditions under which such effects hold have been discussed at length in the pages of the special issue (e.g., Beaman, Smith, Frosch, & McCloy, Reference Beaman, Smith, Frosch and McCloy2010; Hoffrage, Reference Hoffrage2011; Katsikopoulus, Reference Katsikopoulos2010; Smithson, Reference Smithson2010). However, a counter-intuitive effect, though it might have led to the “discovery” of the recognition heuristic (RH, Hoffrage, Reference Hoffrage2011), is not sufficient evidence for the claim that people use recognition information in the way that the RH dictates.

Recognition and evaluation

G&G (Gigerenzer & Goldstein, Reference Gigerenzer and Goldstein2011) describe recognition and evaluation as two processes guiding the adaptive selection of the RH (i.e., recognition: “Do I recognize one object but not the other?” and evaluation: “If so is it reasonable to rely on the recognition heuristic in this situation?”). This formulation fits neatly with the interpretation that I and David Shanks proposed in 2004: “such an argument suggests that it is not pure recognition that determines an inference but recognition plus an appropriate reason for knowing why a particular object is recognized—or, at least, a correctly interpreted feeling of familiarity. It is not that an object is recognized and chosen without justification, but that the decision maker has a reasonable idea of why he or she recognizes the object and makes an inference on the basis of this secondary knowledge.” (Newell & Shanks, Reference Newell and Shanks2004, p. 933, emphasis added).

As we argued then, such a claim is far less newsworthy than the notion of a one-reason strategy for which further (i.e., secondary) knowledge is inconsequential (e.g., Goldstein & Gigerenzer, Reference Goldstein, Gigerenzer, Gigerenzer and Todd1999). The recognition and evaluation process sounds more like the description of a person searching (memory) for information and making a trade-off (i.e., evaluating) between relying (solely) on recognition or considering how further information about the decision environment and the object (situation—in G&G’s words) might affect a judgment (e.g., over-ride recognition, support it, etc.). Perhaps my confusion about these two seemingly different interpretations arises from a misunderstanding of the differences between cues, information and knowledge.

2 Cues, information and knowledge

G&G clarify that when in the past they said that further knowledge is inconsequential once a binary recognition judgment has been made (e.g., Goldstein & Gigerenzer, Reference Goldstein, Gigerenzer, Gigerenzer and Todd1999, p.56)—what they meant was not knowledge, or information but cue-values. While I can see that there is a distinction between direct knowledge of the criterion (e.g., knowing – for a fact - the population of a city), and a cue value that might be indicative of a criterion (e.g., knowing a city has an airport) – to say that the former is knowledge/information but that the latter is not is to engage in obfuscation. Little wonder so many researchers took G&G at their (original) word and concluded that there was little evidence for a non-compensatory RH of the kind originally implied (e.g., Bröder & Eichler, Reference Bröder and Eichler2006; Glöckner & Bröder, Reference Glöckner and Bröder2011; Hilbig & Pohl, Reference Hilbig and Pohl2009; Newell & Fernandez, Reference Newell and Fernandez2006; Newell & Shanks, Reference Newell and Shanks2004; Oeusoonthornwattana & Shanks, Reference Oeusoonthornwattana and Shanks2010; Richter & Spath, Reference Richter and Späth2006).

This clarification begs the question of when a cue becomes information and information becomes knowledge. If I search my memory to try to figure out if Milwaukee is bigger than Detroit there are lots of “things” I could use (beer companies, car companies, music labels, TV sitcoms)—are these cues, information or knowledge? G&G note in their open questions that choices between pairs of items in which only one object is recognised and some additional knowledge is known are better predicted by RH than when the object is merely recognised (Pohl, Reference Pohl2006—see also Newell & Fernandez Reference Newell and Fernandez2006 Experiment 1 for the same result). Unless this extra knowledge is somehow defined as not a cue-value then it seems very difficult to reconcile such results with the notion of sole reliance on recognition (though see Marewski, Gaissmaier, Schooler, Goldstein, & Gigerenzer, Reference Marewski, Gaissmaier, Schooler, Goldstein and Gigerenzer2010 for an attempt to do so.)

Perhaps more importantly—where do these cues and our knowledge of the direction of the cue-criterion correlation come from? G&G remind us that knowledge of such things (i.e., the recognition validity) is a prerequisite for the RH to operate, but how would a decision-maker know—how does she answer the “evaluation” question? How does she know when the environment is right—or, to put it in G&G’s terms the ecological rationality criterion is satisfied?

3 Ecological rationality and adaptive decisions

A cornerstone of the fast-and-frugal approach is the idea that heuristics are selected on the basis of their ecological rationality in particular environments. Despite the fundamental importance of this idea, ecological rationality is often defined in reference to itself. For example, G&G state “ecological rationality asks in which environment a given strategy (heuristic or otherwise) excels and in which it fails” (p. 101). Ecological rationality is therefore defined as a property of a heuristic that can only be determined from the perspective of the individual making the decision once a heuristic has been tried in a given environment. If one needs to try it out first then how can ecological rationality drive the initial selection? Without question people can learn to select strategies (or accumulate more or less evidence, if you prefer) in environments that favour one type of strategy over the other (e.g., Newell & Lee, Reference Newell, Lee, Taatgen, van Rijn, Nerbonne and Schomaker2009; Rieskamp & Otto, Reference Rieskamp and Otto2006) but the demonstration of this ability has nothing to do with ecological rationality per se. It simply shows that people can learn to adapt.

The concept of ecological rationality also sits uneasily with situations in which heuristics lead to poorer decisions. G&G discuss at some length the peanut butter tasting experiments of Hoyer and Brown (Reference Hoyer and Brown1990) but fail to point out that the behaviour observed therein is a clear example of recognition being maladaptive. Choosing the inferior-tasting peanut butter because it is in the better-known-brand jar would not seem like a good choice. And yet the emphasis of the RH is that simple reliance on recognition can get you a long way. Why does the decision-maker faced with inferior peanut butter not realise that use of the RH is ecologically irrational? Perhaps the ease with which the brand name is processed leads to a biased judgment (Tversky & Kahneman, Reference Tversky and Kahneman1973).

These are important and interesting questions, and some recent work points towards possible ways of answering them (e.g., Katsikopolous, Schooler, & Hertwig, Reference Katsikopoulos, Schooler and Hertwig2010). Moreover, by simply introducing these concepts important debates have been sparked (e.g., Dougherty, Franco-Watkins, & Thomas, Reference Dougherty, Franco-Watkins and Thomas2008); but to conclude that “ecological rationality guides heuristic selection” is to go beyond the available evidence (see also Hilbig, Reference Hilbig2010).

4 Individual differences and model fits

As noted by G&G analysis of mean levels of accordance with RH often belies important individual differences. For example, in the high validity condition of Newell and Fernandez (Reference Newell and Fernandez2006) Experiment 1, 12 participants chose the recognised object on less than 50% of occasions (with 3 never choosing it) and 11 chose it on more than 50% (with 5 always choosing it) giving a mean RH accordance rate of 55.5%. Can simple heuristics bounded by ecological rationality deal with such individual difference? G&G are optimistic that they can. An alternative approach is to test models (competitively against heuristics) that adopt a different set of assumptions about the distribution of behaviours in a given environment and see how they fare (e.g., Newell & Lee, in press; Lee & Cummins, Reference Lee and Cummins2004). I am also optimistic that new methods can shed light on how and why such individual differences might arise (e.g., Lee & Newell, Reference Lee and Newell2011; see also the excellent suggestions in Tomlinson, Marewski, & Dougherty, Reference Tomlinson, Marewski and Dougherty2011).

Conclusion

The RH is the embodiment of a very simple yet powerful idea that can explain why we can sometimes benefit from ignorance. Its simplicity is also, however, its undoing. The single processing step of the RH (i.e., when only one of two objects is recognised, choose the recognised one) captures what some people do some of the time in some situations (and yes, sometimes what a lot of people do). But the RH is not a process model—in the sense of capturing all of the processes underlying judgments based on recognition. (Just as the Priority Heuristic is not a process model of all the processes underlying risky choice—see Johnson, Schulte-Mecklenbeck, & Willemsen, Reference Johnson, Schulte-Mecklenbeck and Willemsen2008). The crucial evaluation step (the one that “does all the work”) is not captured by the RH; perhaps to understand that step better, research needs to shift away from environments where the RH is likely to succeed to those where it is not.

Footnotes

The support of the Australian Research Council (DP 110100797) is gratefully acknowledged. I thank Jon Baron, Julian Marewski, Rudiger Pohl, Oliver Vitouch and Dan Goldstein for insightful comments on an earlier draft of this article.

References

Beaman, C. P., Smith, P. T., Frosch, C. A., & McCloy, R. (2010). Less-is-more effects without the recognition heuristic. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 258271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bröder, A., & Eichler, A. (2006). The use of recognition information and additional cues in inferences from memory. Acta Psychologica, 121, 275284.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dougherty, M. R., Franco-Watkins, A. M., & Thomas, R. (2008). Psychological plausibility of the theory of Probabilistic Mental Models and the Fast and Frugal Heuristics. Psychological Review, 115, 199213.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (2011). The recognition heuristic: A decade of research. Judgment and Decision Making, 6, 100121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glöckner, A. & Bröder, A. (2011). Processing of recognition information and additional cues: based analysis of choice, confidence, and response time. Judgment and Decision Making, 6, 2342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (1999). The recognition heuristic: How ignorance makes us smart. In Gigerenzer, G., & Todd, P. M., (Eds.) Simple heuristics that make us smart, pp. 3758. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hilbig, B. E. (2010). Reconsidering “evidence” for fast and frugal heuristics. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 17, 923930.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hilbig, B. E., & Pohl, R. F. (2009). Ignorance- versus evidence-based decision making: A decision time analysis of the recognition heuristic. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 35, 12961305.Google ScholarPubMed
Hoffrage, U. (2011). Recognition judgments and the performance of the recognition heuristic depend on the size of the reference class. Judgment and Decision Making, 6, 4357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyer, W. D., & Brown, S. P. (1990). Effects of brand awareness on choice for a common, repeat purchase product. Journal of Consumer Research, 17, 141148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, E.J., Schulte-Mecklenbeck, M., & Willemsen, C.J. (2008). Process models deserve process data: Comment on Brandstatter, Gigerenzer, and Hertwig (2006). Psychological Review, 115, 263273.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Katsikopoulos, K. V. (2010). The less-is-more effect: Predictions and tests. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 244257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katsikopoulos, K. V., Schooler, L. J., & Hertwig, R. (2010). The robust beauty of ordinary information. Psychological Review, 117, 12591266.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lee, M. D., & Cummins, T. D. R. (2004). Evidence accumulation in decision making: Unifying the “take the best” and the “rational” models. Psychonomic Bulletin& Review, 11, 343352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, M.D., & Newell, B.R. (2011). Using Hierarchical Bayesian Methods to Examine the Tools of Decision Making. Manuscript submitted for publication.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marewski, J. N., Gaissmaier, W., Schooler, L. J., Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (2010). From recognition to decisions: Extending and testing recognition based models for multi-alternative inference. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 17, 287309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newell, B. R. & Fernandez, D. (2006). On the binary quality of recognition and the inconsequentiality of further knowledge: Two critical tests of the recognition heuristic. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 19, 333346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newell, B. R., & Lee, M. D. (in press). The right tool for the job? comparing evidence accumulation and a naive strategy selection model of decision making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making.Google Scholar
Newell, B. R., & Shanks, D. R. (2004). On the role of recognition in decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 30, 923935.Google ScholarPubMed
Newell, B.R. & Lee, M.D. (2009). Learning to adjust evidence thresholds in decision making. In Taatgen, N., van Rijn, H., Nerbonne, J and Schomaker, L. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, 473478.Google Scholar
Oeusoonthornwattana, O., & Shanks, D. R. (2010). I like what I know: Is recognition a noncompensatory determiner of consumer choice? Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 310325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pohl, R. F. (2006). Empirical tests of the recognition heuristic. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 19, 251271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richter, T., & Späth, P. (2006). Recognition is used as one cue among others in judgment and decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 32, 150162.Google ScholarPubMed
Rieskamp, J., & Otto, P. E. (2006). SSL: A theory of how people learn to select strategies. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 207236.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smithson, M. (2010). When less is more in the recognition heuristic. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 230243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomlinson, T., Marewski, J. N., & Dougherty, M. R. (2011). Four challenges for cognitive research on the recognition heuristic and a call for a research strategy shift. Judgment and Decision Making, 6, 8999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar