Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T03:34:49.214Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reasons for cooperation and defection in real-world social dilemmas

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Shahzeen Z. Attari*
Affiliation:
School of Public & Environmental Affairs, 1315 East Tenth Street, Bloomington, IN 47405
David H. Krantz
Affiliation:
Columbia University Department of Psychology & Center for Research on Environmental Decisions
Elke U. Weber
Affiliation:
Columbia University Department of Psychology & Center for Research on Environmental Decisions Columbia University Business School
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Interventions to increase cooperation in social dilemmas depend on understanding decision makers’ motivations for cooperation or defection. We examined these in five real-world social dilemmas: situations where private interests are at odds with collective ones. An online survey (N = 929) asked respondents whether or not they cooperated in each social dilemma and then elicited both open-ended reports of reasons for their choices and endorsements of a provided list of reasons. The dilemmas chosen were ones that permit individual action rather than voting or advocacy: (1) conserving energy, (2) donating blood, (3) getting a flu vaccination, (4) donating to National Public Radio (NPR), and (5) buying green electricity. Self-reported cooperation is weakly but positively correlated across these dilemmas. Cooperation in each dilemma correlates fairly strongly with self-reported altruism and with punitive attitudes toward defectors. Some strong domain-specific behaviors and beliefs also correlate with cooperation. The strongest example is frequency of listening to NPR, which predicts donation. Socio-demographic variables relate only weakly to cooperation. Respondents who self-report cooperation usually cite social reasons (including reciprocity) for their choice. Defectors often give self-interest reasons but there are also some domain-specific reasons—some report that they are not eligible to donate blood; some cannot buy green electricity because they do not pay their own electric bills. Cooperators generally report that several of the provided reasons match their actual reasons fairly well, but most defectors endorse none or at most one of the provided reasons for defection. In particular, defectors often view cooperation as costly but do not endorse free riding as a reason for defection. We tentatively conclude that cooperation in these settings is based mostly on pro-social norms and defection on a mixture of self-interest and the possibly motivated perception that situational circumstances prevent cooperation in the given situation.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2014] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

Many situations confront people with tradeoffs between advantages for themselves versus advantages for others. Often these situations are structured such that, if many or most decision makers pursue advantages for themselves, most end up worse than if many or most had sacrificed some self-advantage to contribute toward benefits for others. Such situations, where private interests are at odds with collective interests, are called social dilemmas (Dawes, Reference Dawes1980; Kollock, Reference Kollock1998). In the United States, donation to National Public Radio (NPR) is a paradigmatic example. The broadcasts are a “public good”—one can listen without ever donating—but are supported in substantial part by listener donations to local NPR stations. If many or most listeners chose to donate little or nothing, allocating the money instead to personal needs or other causes, then NPR programming would decline and listeners would lose something they value (Weber & Murnighan, Reference Weber and Murnighan2008).

To simplify language, we use the term cooperation for choices in social-dilemma situations that lean strongly toward contribution toward benefits for others and use defection for contrary choices. Conditions that favor cooperation have been much studied, both in communities (Ostrom, Reference Ostrom1990) and in laboratory settings (Fehr & Gachter, Reference Fehr and Gachter2002; Weber & Murnighan, Reference Weber and Murnighan2008). The present research used an Internet survey to examine commonalities and differences in cooperation across several different social-dilemma situations. In particular, we ask whether cooperation is at all correlated across real-world social dilemmas and also whether the reasons that people give for cooperation or defection are at all consistent across dilemmas.

There are often strong social norms that favor cooperation, yet people also often defect. There are several paths to defection. Benefits to others from the so-called cooperative choice may be hidden or disbelieved. For example, getting a flu vaccine is a social dilemma because vaccinated individuals cannot transmit the flu to others even though non-vaccinated individuals could do so even if asymptomatic (Hershey, Asch, Thumasathit, Meszaros, & Waters, Reference Hershey, Asch, Thumasathit, Meszaros and Waters1994). Yet vaccination may be thought to benefit the recipient primarily, rather than vulnerable others and thus many people may not view getting a flu vaccination as a social dilemma (Chapman & Coups, Reference Chapman and Coups1999). Similarly, energy conservation reduces one’s own energy bills (regardless of any effect on CO2 emissions). Even if benefits to others are recognized, one may not wish to bear the costs. One may feel no obligation to help others or may believe that enough others will help, or that only those who might benefit should help. Finally, one may believe that benefits are attainable only via large-scale cooperation, and that this is unlikely, so personal sacrifices will be in vain.

Despite the fact that both cooperation and defection are commonplace, the factors underlying these choices, for a given dilemma and across dilemmas are understood only poorly. For example, 40–45% of the people in the U.S. claim to have given blood, but only 4-6% do so in any given year (Lee, Piliavin, & Call, Reference Lee, Piliavin and Call1999). What factors underlie the choices that generate such a pattern?

For each tested dilemma, our survey first asked participants to report cooperation or defection, then asked for their reasons (open-ended). The survey then probed self-reported defectors for that dilemma with a closed-ended list of six possible reasons for defection and cooperators with a complementary list of reasons favoring cooperation. The closed-ended list was formulated in terms of the different paths to defection mentioned above, and their contraries. We present these six reasons below. Additional questions asked about attitudes, beliefs, or other behaviors that we hypothesized might be related to the given dilemma.

1.1 Selection of five dilemmas

Many social dilemmas require binding group decisions to promote cooperation. Examples include tax support for public schools, recycling programs paid for by local taxes, and prices imposed for smoking or for CO2 emissions. Because political leadership and ideology are often crucial in such cases, our present research focused on five familiar settings where cooperation is largely personal and voluntary and norms for cooperation are an emergent phenomenon. These five dilemmas are shown in Table 1, along with the self-reported cooperation estimates from our survey. These dilemmas differ among themselves on many dimensions, including whether they are commonly viewed as social dilemmas. Of course, percent cooperation (column 2) depends crucially on the detailed wording and grouping of response alternatives, which varied as seemed appropriate for each social dilemma.Footnote 1

Table 1: Five social dilemmas, with estimated percentage of cooperative choice.

1.2 Aims of this study

We hoped to determine the extent to which each situation is in fact perceived as a social dilemma, the extent to which cooperation is a general trait or is related to situation-specific social norms, and the extent to which cooperation or defection in each situation is related to the six generic reasons that we probed. The reasons elicited by the open-ended questions and those endorsed in the closed-ended responses may be partial reconstructions of true goals, active at real-life decision points, or in some cases may be merely acceptable post-hoc justifications for behavior (Ericsson & Simon, Reference Ericsson and Simon1980; Nisbett & Wilson, Reference Nisbett and Wilson1977). Interpretations are based on converging evidence and of course are far from certain.

For organizations that wish to promote cooperative behavior in particular settings (e.g., the American Red Cross or NPR) it is important to understand whether a particular action is perceived as possibly benefiting others and the extent to which reasons for and against that behavior are general (e.g., altruism) or specific to each setting or situational context. It would also be interesting to compare how closely the open-ended responses for defection match the given organization’s tailored interventions to facilitate cooperation. Of course our study does not fully inform the design of interventions, but the results shed light on perceived barriers for cooperation in each dilemma.

2 Methods

2.1 Participants

We recruited 1050 participants in June 2011 via Amazon’s Mechanical Turk. This article is based on results from the 929 participants who completed the entire survey. Each received a $10 gift certificate on completion. The participants’ mean age was 29.7 years; 46.7% were male; 46.3% percent had a college degree; and only about 5% reported family incomes over $140,000 per year. The participants were thus younger and better educated than a representative U.S. sample (U.S. Census Bureau, 2011). About half self-identified as politically liberal, with the others split about equally between moderate and conservative.

2.2 Survey

The survey provided question blocks regarding each of the five social dilemmas. These five question blocks were presented in different random order for each subject. As an example, in the NPR donation block, NPR was first briefly described using the following text:

“National Public Radio’ (NPR) is a non-profit media organization that provides free public radio broadcasts to listeners around the United States. NPR radio stations are primarily supported by listener donations.”

This was followed by a question asking participants if they had ever donated to NPR (with a dichotomous Yes/No response option). Participants who said yes were branched to the cooperation arm of the NPR questions, where they were asked first to provide their main reasons for donation to NPR. If they reported never donating to NPR, they were branched to the defection arm and asked to provide their main reasons for not donating.

After entering their open-ended reasons for cooperating or defecting, the participants then rated how closely each of six generic reasons matched their own reasons for donating (or not donating) to NPR. The generic reason wording in the cooperation and defection branches for NPR is shown in Table 2; the wording for both branches for all five dilemmas is given in the Appendix. Note that each arm provided parallel but opposite reasons (i.e., the reasons in cooperation arm are contraries of the reasons provided in the defection arm). Each reason was rated on a three-point scale: “close match”, “somewhat match”, or “does not match”. The six generic reasons were presented for rating simultaneously but in random top-to-bottom order for each participant and dilemma.

Table 2: Generic closed-ended reasons provided to participants in the cooperation branch and the defection branch for NPR.

The six reasons were chosen and labeled primarily to explore possible paths to defection that the authors had encountered frequently in conversations about social dilemmas. The labels were not shown to survey participants and do not necessarily reflect the perceptions of these reasons by participants. In particular, “sucker” and “free riding” involve opposite assumptions about an assumed descriptive norm. For “sucker”, the assumed norm is that most people defect (only suckers cooperate). This is encountered as a reason for defection, often coupled with “drop in the bucket”. For those who are willing to go contrary to the presumed norm, it can be a reason for cooperation. For “free riding”, the assumed norm is that most cooperate. This also serves as a reason for defection (everyone else cooperates so they don’t need me). Contrariwise, conformity to the assumed norm can be a reason for cooperation.

Following the endorsements of any or all of the above reasons for their choice, participants were asked questions about how willing they would be to penalize others who listen to NPR but did not contribute and how angry they would be if they donated and others did not. These questions were included to gauge whether punishment (or punitive attitude) is an important characteristic for cooperation in social dilemmas, as implied by the existence of a social norm for cooperation (Bicchieri, Reference Bicchieri2005). These questions concluded the NPR block of the survey. Participants completed a similar block of questions for each of the five social dilemmas.

After their responses to all five social dilemmas, participants completed the Self Reported Altruism (SRA) scale (Rushton, Chrisjohn, & Fekken, Reference Rushton, Chrisjohn and Fekken1981), questions about their perceptions of social norms related to each of the five social dilemmas, and finally a few socio-demographic questions.

The complete survey is presented in the supplement.

3 Results

3.1 Synopsis

Self-reports of cooperation ranged from 8% (buying green electricity) to 92% (conserving energy) as shown in Table 1. The 10 pairwise correlations of cooperation for the five dilemmas are all positive but low. Below, we also present a brief multivariate analysis of the five-way table based on cooperate/defect dichotomies.

We analyzed the correlates of cooperation for each of the five dilemmas, using multiple logistic regression. Four types of variables were considered in these analyses: the demographic variables;Footnote 2 a general attitudinal variable (self-reported altruism [SRA]); domain-specific attitudes and beliefs (specified below for each dilemma), and for three dilemmas, self-reports of related behavior (frequency of listening to NPR, using green electricity in the home, or whether or not one had received a blood transfusion). The regression results will be presented in detail, but can be summarized briefly in the following overview.

For each dilemma, one or more demographic variables have statistically significant associations with cooperation, but all the effect sizes are small. SRA is strongly associated with cooperation in each dilemma. The major variables associated with cooperation are domain-specific attitudes, beliefs, and related behaviors. Despite this domain specificity, some unity can be discerned. There seems to be a strong pro-social norm associated with cooperation in each dilemma, although it emerges from responses that are specialized for the given domain.

We next analyze the open-ended reasons given for cooperation or defection. These reasons reinforce the finding of the regression analyses that social/moral norms underlie cooperation, while defection is tied to self-interest.

Finally, we briefly analyze the endorsement of closed-ended reasons for cooperation or defection. Surprisingly, cooperators endorse many closed-ended reasons, while defectors endorse few, and seem not to recognize the relationship between self-interest and free riding.

3.2 Correlates of cooperation

Pairwise correlations for reported cooperation in different dilemmas were low but positive (estimated Cronbach α = 0.26). There was a small but statistically reliable bunching of participants at both ends of the 0–5 count of cooperation reports: of 929 participants, 76 cooperated on four dilemmas and 10 on all five (compared with expected frequencies only 51.6 and 2.8, respectively, under independence). Similarly, 23 defected on all five dilemmas and 224 on four of five (respective expectations under independence would be only 14.6 and 200.2). Despite the low estimate of α, the 0–5 count correlated +0.39 with SRA. We return to this correlation below, when discussing the effect of measures of attitude and belief.

3.2.1 NPR donation

The logistic regression results for each dilemma are summarized by a sequential analysis of deviance, in which the 10 demographic variables are placed first, the SRA variable next, then some domain-specific attitudes and beliefs, and finally, the domain-related behavior (if any). To illustrate and explain this analysis strategy we use the example of donation to NPR. Here, the situation specific attitudes and beliefs consisted of two variables: percentage of listeners who should donate to NPR and punitive attitudes (described in detail below).

Table 3 displays the sequential analysis-of-deviance for NPR donation using the above four groups of variables.

Table 3: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for NPR donation

To understand these results, note first that all the deviance reductions are statistically significant. The 1% level of significance (assuming a χ 2 distribution for deviance reduction under the null hypothesis) is attained for a deviance reduction of 6.64, 9.21, 13.3, 11.3, and 23.2, for 1, 2, 3, 4 and 10 df respectively. (We report magnitude of successive deviance reductions, which serves as an index of the size of the effects.)

Because of correlations among the explanatory variables, any variable or group of variables turns out to produce a larger deviance reduction if placed earlier in the analysis. Thus, the preceding analysis shows a huge deviance reduction for the domain-relevant behavior, listening to NPR, even after accounting for the effects of demographic and attitude/belief variables first. The situation-specific attitudes and beliefs produce a much smaller but still very substantial deviance reduction after accounting for demographics and SRA, while SRA produces a substantial reduction after accounting for demographics. This same order of sequential analysis is used for each dilemma, because it accounts for as much as possible using a common set of variables (demographics and SRA) before introducing dilemma-specific variables. The latter remain very important even when tested on the background of other variables.

The same 10 demographic variables were included in the logistic regression analysis for each dilemma. In each case, 0–3 of the 10 variables show at least marginal statistical significance; yet none is related to more than one of the five dilemmas. For NPR, participants who are older, for whom English is their first language, and who have lived in the U.S. for many years are more likely to donate (see Appendix). The individual regression coefficients for demographic variables can scarcely be viewed as reliable: statistical significance is marginal in most cases (see Appendix) and there is multicollinearity among the explanatory variables. Yet, overall, demographic variables do show some effects, and collectively would remain statistically significant at the 5% level or beyond (with 10 df) even if the group of variables were inserted last into the sequential analysis.

We could not perform a similar fully uniform analysis across all 5 dilemmas for the domain-specific attitudes, beliefs, and behaviors, because our questionnaire design was not sufficiently exhaustive with respect to beliefs and behaviors. For each dilemma, we probed punitive attitudes toward defection through four items: willingness to punish, willingness to punish at a cost to oneself, anger at defectors, and anger at self if one cooperated and most others defected (this last was reverse-coded). These four items were averaged to form an index of punitive attitude; this index was one of the explanatory variables included under domain-specific attitudes and beliefs. However we lacked the foresight to probe situation-specific beliefs similarly for each social dilemma. For NPR, we asked only for the percentage of people who should donate. By contrast, for blood donation we used three items: percentage who should donate, percentage that do donate, and effectiveness of blood donation. Thus, the group of variables for domain-specific attitudes and beliefs consisted of only two variables for NPR but four variables for blood donation. Other dilemmas were related to two or three domain-specific beliefs. Details are discussed in connection with the sequential analysis of deviance for each dilemma below.

Note that the mean percentage that people believed should donate ranged from 53% for NPR, to 64% for blood donations, and 83% for people who should buy energy efficient technology. In contrast, people believe that the actual descriptive norm is far less (in the two cases that we checked), the mean believed percentage that currently do buy efficient technologies was 33% and the mean believed percentage that currently do donate blood was 30%.

We probed situation-related behavior for only three of the five dilemmas: frequency of listening to NPR, having ever received a blood transfusion, and use of alternative energy (such as solar panels or micro wind turbines) in one’s home (this last is related to buying green electricity).

The situation-related behavior of listening to NPR is particularly powerful and interesting in its effect. The “listeners should donate” question yielded rather high rates of affirmation. Among donors, 86% respond at 50% or higher, while in the much larger group of non-donors, 69% nonetheless give such answers. Political attitudes seemed to have no effect: 77 out of 106 (73%) non-donors who rated themselves as Conservative or Extremely Conservative give answers of 50% or higher. This item thus seems to express a prevalent injunctive moral norm: “If you listen, you should probably donate.” Since this norm is expressed even more strongly among donors than non-donors, this attitude is one of the explanatory variables for donation. We view this as a reciprocity norm and return to it in our analysis of the open-ended reasons for cooperation.

If people apply the reciprocity norm to themselves, one would expect donation rate to increase as a function of how often the respondent reports listening to NPR. Indeed, reported donation rate increases from about 2% among those who seldom or never listen, to 20% or 25% among monthly listeners, to about 50% among weekly listeners, and about 70% among those who listen more often than weekly. Thus, frequency of listening to NPR has a very strong positive association with donation to NPR.

3.3 Generalizing from NPR donation to other dilemmas

The above analysis of NPR donation illustrates a general finding across all five dilemmas and dictates a general strategy for explanatory models for cooperation. We fitted analogous models for the other four dilemmas, always including all 10 demographic variables, SRA score, situation-specific Punitive Attitude, and one or more other situation-specific attitudes, beliefs, or behaviors. Demographic variables are sometimes statistically significant in isolation, and some remain so in combination with other types of variables, but are never found to be strongly explanatory. The SRA score correlates positively with cooperation in every dilemma, no matter what else is included in the model, but is also never strongly explanatory. The variables most strongly explanatory are situation specific: punitive attitudes toward defectors, specific beliefs (e.g., that flu shots are or are not highly effective), and dilemma-related behaviors, such as listening to NPR, when available.

3.3.1 Blood donation

The model includes all 10 demographic variables, SRA, two situation-specific attitudes variables (Punitive Attitude and the percentage who should donate blood), two belief variables (the percentage of Americans who do donate in any given year and how effective blood donations are), and a behavioral marker, whether the respondent has ever received a blood transfusion. We thought that having received a blood transfusion might be analogous to listening often to NPR, i.e., it would induce a reciprocity goal: having received, one should give. Table 4 shows the sequential analysis. In this case, the behavioral variable has negligible effect; surprisingly (to us), it correlated strongly with SRA. The high deviance reduction for SRA is partly due to the fact that the SRA scale includes a blood donation item. If that item is excluded, the deviance reduction falls to 47.8 and the deviance reductions attributed to situation-specific attitudes, and having received blood increase a bit (but remains non-significant). Respondents who reported having had a transfusion show considerably higher mean SRA than others (6.9 ± 1.7 points, which is over ½ a standard deviation on the SRA scale; this difference is reduced only slightly when the blood donation item is excluded). The two belief variables correlated strongly with blood donation, as does the attitudinal norm (% who should donate). Again, Punitive Attitude, though included in the model, had a coefficient of only +0.13 ± 0.14.

Table 4: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for blood donation.

Among the 10 demographic variables, male and highly educated participants are more likely to donate blood.

3.3.2 Flu Vaccination

The model again included the 10 demographic variables, SRA, and four situation-specific attitudes or beliefs. We did not ask a behavioral question relevant to a reciprocity norm—most people probably cannot guess whether they have benefited in the past from others’ flu vaccinations. Table 5 shows the results.

Table 5: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for flu vaccination.

In this dilemma, the situation-specific attitudes included two similar questions about norms for flu shots: What percentage of people should be vaccinated, and how many groups of people should be vaccinated (0–5, ranging from no one, children, people 50 years of age or older, pregnant mothers, healthy adults, and everyone). Even though these are highly correlated (+0.72), their effects on the outcome of getting vaccinated are sharply separable (logistic coefficients are +0.023 ± 0.004 and +0.47 ± 0.08 respectively). Here, Punitive Attitude was also a strong correlate (+1.18 ± 0.17). Belief about the effectiveness of flu vaccination, which is correlated with the normative and punitive attitudes, also showed an almost-significant effect. Surprisingly, participants who had children were less likely to get a flu vaccine, and those who had a higher income were more likely to get a vaccine.

3.3.3 Conserving Energy

The model in this case had only one situation-specific attitude, Punitive Attitude toward those who do not conserve, but three situation-specific beliefs, first, about the effect of not conserving energy, second, what percentage of people do conserve energy (a “descriptive norm”), and third, what percentage of people should conserve energy (an “injunctive norm”). Table 6 shows the results.

Table 6: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for energy conservation

None of the 10 demographic variables strongly correlated with energy conservation. However, Punitive Attitude and percentage that do conserve, were both positively correlated to cooperating, and the negative effect of not conserving was positively correlated to cooperating.

3.3.4 Buying green electricity

The model again included the 10 demographic variables, SRA, and four situation-specific behaviors, attitudes or beliefs (do you use alternative energy in your home, do you know about alternative energy, percentage of people who should buy green electricity, and Punitive Attitudes). Here, as with many of the other dilemmas, situation-specific behaviors, attitudes and beliefs account for the largest reduction in deviance. Table 7 shows the results. Using alternative energy, knowing about alternative energy, and the percentage of people who should buy green electricity all positively correlated with cooperation. None of the 10 demographic variables are associated with cooperating.

Table 7: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for buying green energy

3.4 Open-ended reasons

Open-ended reasons for cooperating and defecting were coded by one rater (929 participants x 5 dilemmas = 4645 responses). Even though we asked for the main reason, many participants provided more than one reason, which led to the rater coding up to 3 reasons.

Each dilemma has some idiosyncratic reasons for defection: for example, some people do not donate blood because they are afraid of needles and some are ineligible for medical reasons. Some do not buy green energy because they are not responsible for paying energy bills. There are also some unique reasons for cooperation. A coding scheme was devised for each dilemma, with 10–18 coding categories for each branch, cooperation or defection. The three most frequent categories for each dilemma and each branch are given in Table 8.

Table 8: Top three open-ended reasons for defecting and cooperating for each social dilemma.

This set of codes was developed in two stages. After the initial coding, a subset of the codes was checked by an independent coder. Inter-rater reliability was was calculated (using 3–7 coding categories). For 6 out of 10 cases, inter-rater reliability was good (κ ranging from .60 to .93, with the worst cases attributable to inconsistent use of “other” as a category). In one other case (flu defect) the main category is “self-interest”, so κ means little. In 3 cases, however, rater differences revealed ambiguities in the coding scheme; codes were modified. Only one coder provided the final codes. (Details and the full coding scheme are provided in the Appendix.) For some dilemmas, the coded open-ended reasons confirm findings from prior research. A common reason for getting a flu shot is to prevent illness (Nichol & Hauge, Reference Nichol and Hauge1997) and a common reason for not donating blood is fear of needles and perceived ineligibility (Lemmens et al., Reference Lemmens, Abraham, Ruiter, Veldhuizen, Dehing, Bos and Schaalma2009).

To further investigate the open-ended reasons, Table 9 summarizes the use of social reasons (actions for the collective good) as reasons for cooperation. To determine whether people view the problems provided as a social dilemma, we analyzed whether the open-ended reason provided was in fact a social reason. Only 304 participants out of 855 gave a reason (first or later) that relates to some sort of social reason or greater good in the Conserve Energy problem. Thus, while many people see this problem as a social dilemma, the majority seems not to, or at least do not articulate that view. An even more extreme case is the Flu Vaccine problem. Here, 434 respondents stated that they always or sometimes get flu shots, but most of the reasons had to do with personal health. Only 110 people, about 25%, mention protecting the health of others as one of their reasons.

Table 9: Main social and non-social reasons for cooperating.

On the other hand, Blood Donation and Green Electricity are perceived more widely in social terms. For example, in the Blood Donation problem, as seen in Table 8, majority of the reasons provided were justified by social reasons such as “it’s the right thing to do”, “to help people and save lives”.

Only NPR donators give exclusively social reasons; for Blood Donation and Green Electricity there is a not-so-small minority who give only personal benefit as a reason. In the case of NPR, however, the dominant social reason is reciprocity (“I listen to NPR”), rather than more abstract concern for public good (“right thing to do” or the like).

Thus social reasons do often account for why people cooperate in social dilemmas, especially in the case of NPR (where 100% of the participants donate because of implicit reciprocity), green electricity (save the earth), blood donation (to help others and save lives). In these cases the problem seems to be perceived widely as a social dilemma. Cooperation also arises from perceived self-interest, especially in the case of flu shot (protect health) and energy conservation (save money). In such cases, the problem is not perceived as a social dilemma.

Self-interest does somewhat account for why people defect when they face social dilemmas, especially in the case of flu vaccines (where 66% of the defectors think they are not vulnerable to the flu). Table 10 shows the main reasons for defecting across the social dilemmas. Surprisingly, defection often results from factors other than self-interest: ideology, eligibility, availability, beliefs about effectiveness, or non-reciprocity.

Table 10: Main self-interest and non-self-interest reasons for defecting.

From the open-ended qualitative analysis, “drop in the bucket” and “sucker” arguments for defection are rare. “Greater good” arguments for cooperation are frequent, but far from universal, because of the numerous cases of self-interest.

The logistic regressions presented earlier, with cooperation as dependent variable, highlight the importance of altruism (as assessed by the SRA scale) and of several social norms, including the reciprocity norm and beliefs that people should cooperate and that non-cooperators should be punished. The open-ended reasons that people give for cooperation or defection partly support these conclusions from the regression analyses. While some of the five problems are viewed as social dilemmas only by a minority, cooperation is often linked to moral norms or reciprocity, and defection is often linked to a predominance of self-interest reasons.

3.5 Closed-ended reasons

After entering one or more open-ended reason(s) for cooperating or defecting, a participant then indicated how closely each of six closed-ended reasons matched the reason(s) for cooperation or defection just given. These reasons are shown in Table 2, for NPR only, and in the Appendix for all dilemmas. Responses used a three-point scale: “close match”, “somewhat match”, and “does not match”. These a priori closed-ended reasons were worded to be contraries of one another for cooperation and defection. Preserving this symmetry of reasons allowed us to take reasons that we thought were important for defection, such as free riding and not wanting to be a sucker, and to provide similar opposing reasons for cooperation, such as not wanting to free ride and not minding being a sucker.

Figure 1 shows that on average, cooperators found several reasons to be a “close match” but defectors often found no such matches or often only one.

Figure 1: Mean number of closed-ended reasons endorsed as “close match” for cooperation and defection. Error bars are ± 1 standard error of the mean.

Thus the set of a priori reasons for cooperation fits the participants’ stated reasons fairly well, almost too well—to cooperators, several potentially distinct a priori reasons sound about right. The a priori reasons for defection, however, fit the stated reasons poorly. This indicates that people may not have a distinct idea of why they cooperate, so are willing to endorse several reasons as correct, whereas defectors have rather specific reasons, and resist classifying these reasons as free riding or avoiding being a sucker. This latter point is shown in Figure 2, where the fraction endorsing each type of a priori reason is shown, averaged across the five dilemmas.

Figure 2: Proportion endorsing each closed-ended reason as “close match” for cooperation and for defection (averaged across the 5 dilemmas).

Three types of reason, altruism, sucker, and free ride, are used very infrequently as matches to the reason for defection. Notably, these three are also least used as matches for cooperation, but the latter proportions are much higher. These three types all refer to other people in one-way or another (see Table 1), and are thereby perhaps more complex conceptually than the three that refer only to the dilemma directly. Nonetheless, it seems important that about 1/6 of cooperators, on average, endorse free ride (others cooperate, so I should), while many fewer defectors endorse this reason. One reason they might not endorse it is that they do not agree with assumed descriptive norm—i.e., that many others cooperate. If so, then they should agree with the assumed opposite—few cooperate—and might thus be led to endorse sucker as a reason for their choice. In fact, they endorse neither, while a substantial fraction of cooperators for any given dilemma endorse either free ride or sucker.

4 Discussion

What does trying to conserve energy have to do with supporting NPR by donations? On the surface, not much; and indeed, our data show only a weak correlation (+.12 ± .03) between these behaviors and a considerable difference in the main reasons that people cite for doing them. 92% of our subjects say that they try to conserve energy, and of these, 59% list a self-interested justification, saving money, as a major reason. By contrast, only 1 in 6 donate to NPR, and 45% of these donors mention reciprocity explicitly—I listen, therefore I should donate. There are, however similarities between the two situations. Self-reported altruism correlates with cooperation in both cases, as does punitive attitude toward violators of the domain-specific norms. About 35% of energy conservers list an environmental reason for their action, possibly in addition to a self-interested reason. In the case of NPR, a social norm is quite explicit—most people, regardless of political orientation or attitude toward NPR, believe that those who listen should donate. For energy conservation, the presence of a social norm can be inferred from punitive attitudes: among those who report that they conserve, about 27% are quite willing or extremely willing to penalize those who don’t and about 24% express strong or extreme anger at those who don’t.

The comparison of NPR donation and energy conservation was selected to illustrate an underlying commonality in social reasons for cooperation despite the considerable difference in cooperation rates and in self-interest justifications. Our data in fact suggest that social attitudes and norms are important for cooperation in all five dilemmas: cooperation correlates positively with SRA for each, and all but blood donation show a positive relation to punitive attitudes vis-à-vis defectors. In the case of blood donation we have the surprising finding that those who have received blood tend to have substantially higher SRA scores (which may mediate a somewhat greater willingness to donate blood). This raises the question of whether recipients of benefits in other domains also show higher SRA scores. This could only be answered by separate research directed toward this question.

Some lessons about method for studying social norms emerge from our results. In isolation, a stated reason or justification for behavior may or may not reflect a true underlying goal—it can also reflect social desirability or a goal that appears rational. Our inferences about social norms are produced by converging evidence: correlates of self-reported choices, open-ended statements about justification, and willingness to endorse one or several reasons (related to free riding, reciprocity, etc.) in a closed-ended probe task. In this latter regard, it is interesting to contrast the endorsement by cooperators of several different reasons from the list we provided with the rejection of the contrary putative defection reasons by defectors. The failure of our list of putative defection reasons may involve two factors. On one hand, there are highly domain-specific reasons for defection, such as ineligibility for blood donation, or unavailability (real or perceived) for green energy. The second factor is failure to acknowledge free-riding. Many reasons for defection are ones that one might label as free-riding, but are not recognized as such, either out of ignorance (people don’t understand that they benefit from others’ flu shots) or through motivated cognition.

Finally, we note the importance of domain-specific norms, attitudes and beliefs in these five dilemmas. Someone wanting to promote pro-social behavior would proceed quite differently for NPR donation versus blood donation versus getting flu shots and for promoting energy conservation versus increasing sales of green energy. NPR donation depends heavily on a reciprocity norm widely held among both donors and non-donors: if you listen, you should donate. Thus, NPR correctly depends on radio appeals to listeners—those who listen often hear these appeals and are the main source of donations. Blood donation appeals can also attempt to use reciprocity: you or one of your loved ones may need a blood transfusion some day. At the same time, campaigns for blood donation might benefit from clarification about who is eligible to donate and from efforts to reduce fear of the process of drawing blood. “Come with your closest friends and donate together” might help alleviate fear. For flu shots it seems clear that benefits to others should be emphasized, since so many people seem unaware of the social dilemma and treat the question as one of their personal vulnerability to flu. Energy conservation can probably be promoted usefully by emphasizing the combination of environmental and future-generation benefits with long-term cost savings. Finally, green energy suffers from lack of marketing efforts—people simply are unaware of the possibility.

The open-ended reasons provided by defectors offer a window into domain-specific issues that may need to be addressed in each dilemma. For example, many people state that they do not donate blood because they are afraid of needles (28%) or believe they are ineligible for health reasons (16%). We suggested above the possibility of reducing fear of needles and clarifying eligibility; other paths to these ends may be found. Similarly, some people believe that energy conservation measures are too expensive (26%); emphasizing longer time horizons is a possible remedy. Other domain-specific reasons seem irrefutable – one who does not pay for electricity cannot simply elect to buy green. Research is needed both to test methods for overcoming domain-specific barriers and to test the extent to which domain-specific reasons represent motivated cognition—reasons constructed to retain a pro-social self-image.

Appendix

Table 1 Reasons for cooperating and defecting: (1) drop in bucket, (2) reciprocity, (3) rationality (benefits vs. costs), (4) do not want to be a sucker, (5) free riding, and (6) altruism.

Logistic regression results: Analysis of maximum likelihood estimates

Table 2: Predicting donating to NPR.

Table 3 Predicting donating blood.

Table 4: Predicting buying green electricity.

Table 5: Predicting getting a flu vaccination.

Table 6: Predicting conserving energy

Open-ended coding of reasons provided for cooperation and defection for each social dilemma.

Note that the counts for all reasons are equally weighted, when multiple reasons are provided.

Table 7: Reasons for donating to NPR.

Table 8: Reasons for not donating to NPR.

Table 9: Reasons for donating blood.

Table 10: Reasons for not donating blood.

Table 11: Reasons for buying green electricity.

Table 12: Reasons for not buying green electricity.

Table 13: Reasons for getting a flu vaccination.

Table 14 Reasons for not getting a flu vaccination.

Table 15: Reasons for conserving energy.

Table 16: Reasons for not conserving energy.

Table 17: Correlation matrix to show individual relationships between each predictor and each dependent variable (highlighted in grey).

Footnotes

Funding for this project was provided by the National Science Foundation (SES–0345840) and the School of Public and Environmental Affairs at Indiana University Bloomington. The authors thank Jon Baron for helpful comments and the late Robyn Dawes for the initial idea. We thank Farzana Chowdhury and Kelsey Poinsatte-Jones for coding the open-ended responses.

1 The detailed definition of “cooperation” varied across the five dilemmas to take account of intrinsic differences among the dilemmas in opportunities for behavioral choices. Opportunity to conserve energy arises daily, opportunity to get a flu shot annually, so a frequency response seemed natural; for these, “always” and “sometimes” were grouped together. Opportunities to donate blood or donate to NPR are harder to quantify and since annual donations are rare we simply asked whether people had ever donated. Buying green energy can be a one-time decision.

2 The 10 demographic variables (see the supplement for detailed wording) were: having children, belonging to an environmental organization, political views, gender, age, number of years in the US, being white, English as a first language, income, and education.

References

Bicchieri, C. (2005). The grammar of society: The nature and dynamics of social norms. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chapman, G. B., & Coups, E. J. (1999). Predictors of influenza vaccine acceptance among healthy adults. Preventive medicine, 29(4), 249-262.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dawes, R. M. (1980). Social dilemmas. Annual Review of Psychology, 31(1), 169193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ericsson, K. A., & Simon, H. A. (1980). Verbal reports as data. Psychological Review, 87(3), 215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E., & Gachter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature, 415, 137140.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hershey, J. C., Asch, D. A., Thumasathit, T., Meszaros, J., & Waters, V. V. (1994). The roles of altruism, free riding, and bandwagoning in vaccination decisions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 59(2), 177187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kollock, P. (1998). Social dilemmas: The anatomy of cooperation. Annual review of sociology, 24(1), 183214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, L., Piliavin, J. A., & Call, V. R. (1999). Giving time, money, and blood: Similarities and differences. Social Psychology Quarterly, 276290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemmens, K., Abraham, C., Ruiter, R., Veldhuizen, I., Dehing, C., Bos, A., & Schaalma, H. (2009). Modelling antecedents of blood donation motivation among non-donors of varying age and education. British Journal of Psychology, 100(1), 7190.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nichol, K. L., & Hauge, M. (1997). Influenza vaccination of healthcare workers. Infection Control and Hospital Epidemiology, 189194.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nisbett, R., & Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231-259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rushton, J., Chrisjohn, R., & Fekken, G. (1981). The altruistic personality and the self-report altruism scale. Personality and Individual Differences, 2(4), 293302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
U.S. Census Bureau. (2011). American Community Survey Retrieved May 2, 2013, from http://www.census.gov/acs/www/.Google Scholar
Weber, J. M., & Murnighan, J. K. (2008). Suckers or saviors? Consistent contributors in social dilemmas. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 95(6), 1340.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Figure 0

Table 1: Five social dilemmas, with estimated percentage of cooperative choice.

Figure 1

Table 2: Generic closed-ended reasons provided to participants in the cooperation branch and the defection branch for NPR.

Figure 2

Table 3: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for NPR donation

Figure 3

Table 4: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for blood donation.

Figure 4

Table 5: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for flu vaccination.

Figure 5

Table 6: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for energy conservation

Figure 6

Table 7: Sequential analysis of deviance: logistic regression for buying green energy

Figure 7

Table 8: Top three open-ended reasons for defecting and cooperating for each social dilemma.

Figure 8

Table 9: Main social and non-social reasons for cooperating.

Figure 9

Table 10: Main self-interest and non-self-interest reasons for defecting.

Figure 10

Figure 1: Mean number of closed-ended reasons endorsed as “close match” for cooperation and defection. Error bars are ± 1 standard error of the mean.

Figure 11

Figure 2: Proportion endorsing each closed-ended reason as “close match” for cooperation and for defection (averaged across the 5 dilemmas).

Figure 12

Table 1 Reasons for cooperating and defecting: (1) drop in bucket, (2) reciprocity, (3) rationality (benefits vs. costs), (4) do not want to be a sucker, (5) free riding, and (6) altruism.

Figure 13

Table 2: Predicting donating to NPR.

Figure 14

Table 3 Predicting donating blood.

Figure 15

Table 4: Predicting buying greenelectricity.

Figure 16

Table 5: Predicting getting a flu vaccination.

Figure 17

Table 6: Predicting conserving energy

Figure 18

Table 7: Reasons for donating to NPR.

Figure 19

Table 8: Reasons for not donating to NPR.

Figure 20

Table 9: Reasons for donating blood.

Figure 21

Table 10: Reasons for not donating blood.

Figure 22

Table 11: Reasons for buying green electricity.

Figure 23

Table 12: Reasons for not buying green electricity.

Figure 24

Table 13: Reasons for getting a flu vaccination.

Figure 25

Table 14 Reasons for not getting a flu vaccination.

Figure 26

Table 15: Reasons for conserving energy.

Figure 27

Table 16: Reasons for not conserving energy.

Figure 28

Table 17: Correlation matrix to show individual relationships between each predictor and each dependent variable (highlighted in grey).

Supplementary material: File

Attari et al. supplementary material

Attari et al. supplementary material 1
Download Attari et al. supplementary material(File)
File 717.2 KB
Supplementary material: File

Attari et al. supplementary material

Attari et al. supplementary material 2
Download Attari et al. supplementary material(File)
File 716.2 KB
Supplementary material: File

Attari et al. supplementary material

Supplement
Download Attari et al. supplementary material(File)
File 163.2 KB