Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T09:03:18.335Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How and Why should We Write the History of Twentieth-Century Economics?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 June 2009

Roger E. Backhouse
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, University of Birmingham, Edgbaston, Birmingham B15 2TT, Great Britain.

Extract

Most discussions of how one should write the history of economics are conducted at a very abstract level. They debate the merits of alternative approaches without relating them to specific problem-situations or specific periods. The literature uses terms such as “absolutism,” “relativism,” “Whig history,” “thick history,” “historical reconstructions,” “rational reconstructions,” and “presentism,” frequently arguing that one of these approaches is better than one or more of the others. In warning historians of economics against sin, they typically define sin in absolute terms. This is particularly true of those who argue for “relativism,” “thick history,” “historical reconstructions” and the like. There is a simple reason for this. Terms such as “absolutism,” “Whig history,” and “presentism” all carry negative connotations, with the result that their advocates usually feel impelled to qualify them. On the other hand, supporters of “historical reconstruction,” “thick history” and so on feel much less pressure to offer such qualifications—the words used have the sound of “real” history. The terminology itself is value-laden.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The History of Economics Society 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Backhouse, Roger E. 1985. A History of Modern Economic Analysis. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Backhouse, Roger E. 1992. “How Should We Approach the History of Economic Thought: Fact Fiction or Moral Tale?Journal of the History of Economic Thought 14 (1): 18–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Backhouse, Roger E. 1994. “Why and How Should We Study the History of Economic Thought?History of Economic Ideas 2 (2): 115–23.Google Scholar
Backhouse, Roger E. “Vision and Progress In Economic Thought: Schumpeter After Kuhn.” In Moss, L., ed., Joseph A. Schumpeter: Historian of Economics. London: Routledge, pp. 2132. Reprinted in Explorations in Economic Methodology From Lakatos to Empirical Philosophy of Science. London: Routledge, 1998, pp. 176–89.Google Scholar
Backhouse, Roger E. Forthcoming. “On Progress and the History of Economic Thought.” In S. Böhm, C. Gehrke, H. D. Kurz, and R. Sturn, eds. Is There Progress in Economics? Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Bentley, Michael. 1997. Companion to Historiography. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hobsbawm, Eric. 1994. Age of Extremes: The Short Twentieth Century. London: Michael Joseph.Google Scholar
Marshall, Alfred. 1890. Principles of Economics. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Myrdal, Gunnar. 1968. Asian Drama: An Inquiry into the Poverty of Nations. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, J. A. 1954. History of Economic Analysis. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Veblen, Thorstein Bunde 1899. “The Preconceptions of Economic Science, III,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 13: 396426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weintraub, E. Roy. 1989. “Methodology Doesn't Matter, But the History of Thought Might.” Scandinavian Journal of Economics 91 (2): 477–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weintraub, E. Roy. 1999. “How Should We Write the History of Twentieth-Century Economics?Oxford Review of Economic Policy 15 (4): 139–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weintraub, E. Roy. Forthcoming. How Economics Became a Mathematical Science. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Wicksell, Knut. 1898. Interest and Prices, translated by Kahn, R. F.. London: Macmillan, 1935.Google Scholar