Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-18T16:41:49.608Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Collective responsibility and the state

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2009

John M. Parrish*
Affiliation:
Loyola Marymount University, USA

Abstract

This article considers the question of whether and to what degree citizens are responsible collectively for the actions of their state. In contrast to current accounts of collective responsibility, which focus on causality or affect as means for transmitting responsibility, the article develops an alternative account, the ‘authorized state’ model. This model, drawn from core intuitions of the social contract tradition, sees collective responsibility as being transmitted through the state as the agent or representative of its citizens. Having developed this model as an ideal type, the article then assesses under what circumstances the model is most applicable. The article finally applies the model to the US war in Iraq to assess the collective responsibility of US citizens for the outcomes of that war.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abdel-Nour, F. (2003), ‘National responsibility’, Political Theory 31: 693719.Google Scholar
Arendt, H. (1987), ‘Collective responsibility’, in J. Kohn (ed.), Responsibility and Judgment, New York: Schocken Books.Google Scholar
Bass, G.J. (2001), Stay the Hand of Vengeance: The Politics of War Crimes Tribunals, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Boorstin, D. (1992), The Image, New York: Vintage.Google Scholar
Brandt, R.B. (1972), ‘Utilitarianism and the rules of war’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 1: 145165.Google Scholar
Connolly, W. (1993), The Terms of Political Discourse, 3rd edn., Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Copp, D. (1999), ‘The idea of a legitimate state’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 28: 345.Google Scholar
Crawford, J. (2006), The Creation of States in International Law, 2nd edn., Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crawford, N.C. (2007), ‘Individual and collective moral responsibility for systematic military atrocity’, Journal of Political Philosophy 15: 187212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunn, J. (2002), Political Obligation in its Historical Context. New edn., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Erskine, T. (2001), ‘Assigning responsibilities to institutional moral agents: the case of states and “quasi-states” ’, Ethics and International Affairs 15: 6785.Google Scholar
Erskine, T. (2003), Can Institutions Have Responsibilities? Collective Moral Agency and International Relations, New York: Palgrave MacMillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1968). ‘Collective responsibility,’ in May and Hoffman (1991).Google Scholar
Feldman, N. (2004), What We Owe to Iraq: War and the Ethics of Nation-Building, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, J.M. (2004), ‘Responsibility and manipulation’, Journal of Ethics 8: 145177.Google Scholar
Fischer, J.M.Ravizza, M. (eds) (1993), Perspectives on Moral Responsibility, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Fishkin, J. (1996), The Dialogue of Justice, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Fletcher, G.P. (2002), ‘Liberals and romantics at war: the problem of collective guilt’, Yale Law Journal 111: 14991573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
French, P. (1984), Collective and Corporate Responsibility, New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geuss, R. (2001), History and Illusion in Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, M. (1989), On Social Facts, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gilbert, M. (1997), ‘Group wrongs and guilt feelings’, Journal of Ethics 1: 6584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2002a), ‘Collective guilt and collective guilt feelings’, Journal of Ethics 6: 115143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2002b), ‘Collective wrongdoing: moral and legal responsese’, Social Theory and Practice 28: 167187.Google Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2006a), A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Bonds of Society, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2006b), ‘Who’s to blame? Collective moral responsibility and its implications for group members’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 30: 94114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, R. (1980), Manipulatory Politics, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Goodin, R. (1995), Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Greenspan, P. (2003), ‘The problem with manipulation’, American Philosophical Quarterly 40: 155165.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. (1991), in R. Tuck (ed.), Leviathan, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T (1994), in J.C.A. Gaskin (ed.), The Elements of Law Natural and Politic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hoffman, S. (1981), Duties Beyond Borders, Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.Google Scholar
Honderich, T. (2006), Punishment: The Supposed Justifications Revisited, London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1985), ‘Of the original contract’, in E. Miller (ed.), Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Jackson, P.T. (2004), ‘Hegel’s House, or “People Are States Too” ’, Review of International Studies 30: 281287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaspers, K. (1986), ‘The Question of German Guilt’, in E. Ehrlich, L.H. Ehrlich, G.B. Pepper (eds), Karl Jaspers: Basic Philosophical Writings, Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.Google Scholar
Kavka, G.S. (1986), Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Klosko, G. (2005), Political Obligations, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kutz, C. (2000), Complicity: Ethics and Law for a Collective Age, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kutz, C. (2005), ‘The difference uniforms make: collective violence in criminal law and war’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 33: 148180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lang, A.F. Jr. (2007), ‘Crime and punishment: holding states accountable’, Ethics and International Affairs 21: 239257.Google Scholar
Lang, A.F. Jr. (2008), Punishment, Justice, and International Relations: Ethics in the Post-Cold War System, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1988), in P. Laslett (ed.), Two Treatises of Government, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, L. (1996), Sharing Responsibility, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
May, L.Hoffman, S. (eds) (1991), Collective Responsibility: Five Decades of Debate in Theoretical and Applied Ethics, Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
McGary, H. (1986), ‘Morality and collective liability’, in May and Hoffman (1991).Google Scholar
Micklethwait, J.Woolridge, A. (2003), The Company: A Short History of a Revolutionary Idea, New York: Modern Library.Google Scholar
Milanovic, M. (2006), ‘State responsibility for genocide’, European Journal of International Law 17: 553604.Google Scholar
Miller, D. (2001), ‘Distributing responsibilities’, Journal of Political Philosophy 9: 453471.Google Scholar
Miller, D. (2004), ‘Holding nations responsible’, Ethics 114: 240268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Narveson, J. (2002), ‘Collective responsibility’, Journal of Ethics 6: 179198.Google Scholar
Nollkaemper, A. (2003), ‘Concurrence between individual responsibility and state responsibility in international law’, International and Comparative Law Quarterly 52: 614640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parrish, J.M. (2007), Paradoxes of Political Ethics: From Dirty Hands to the Invisible Hand, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. (2001), A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pitkin, H. (1967), The Concept of Representation, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Räikkä, J. (1997), ‘On disassociating oneself from collective responsibility’, Social Theory and Practice 23: 93108.Google Scholar
Runciman, D. (1997), Pluralism and the Personality of the State, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runciman, D. (2003a), ‘The concept of the state: the sovereignty of a fiction’, in Q. Skinner and B. Strath (eds), States and Citizens: History, Theory, Prospects, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Runciman, D. (2003b), ‘Moral responsibility and the problem of representing the state’, in Erskine (2003).Google Scholar
Simmons, A.J. (1979), Moral Principles and Political Obligations, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, Q. (2002), ‘Visions of Politics’, 3 vols, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tuck, R. (1999), The Rights of War and Peace, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, M. (1970), Obligations, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, M. (1977), Just and Unjust Wars, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Walzer, M. (2004), Arguing About War, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Weber, M. (1946), ‘Politics as a vocation’, in H.H. Gerth and C.W. Mills (eds), From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wendt, A. (1999), Social Theory of International Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wendt, A. (2004), ‘The State as a Person in International Theory’, Review of International Studies 30: 289316.Google Scholar
Wight, C. (2004), ‘State agency: social action without human activity?’, Review of International Studies 30: 269280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1994), Shame and Necessity, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Young, I.M. (2006), ‘Responsibility and global justice: a social connection model’, Social Philosophy and Policy 23: 102130.Google Scholar