Article contents
Supranational public reason: On legitimacy of supranational norm-producing authorities
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 26 October 2015
Abstract
The emergence of strong authorities beyond the nation state has raised questions about the absence of democratic legitimacy at the supranational level. The usual response to this dilemma has been an attempt to uncouple the strict link between national statehood and democracy, and in the process, to confer a degree of legitimacy on supranational authorities. This article argues that such an uncoupling is unconvincing, and that within the legitimacy-democracy-statehood triangle, the uncoupling of legitimacy and democracy is a more promising strategy. The legitimacy of supranational authorities is grounded in their appeal to ‘public reason’ – a legitimacy-conferring device well-suited to supranational authorities, as illustrated in this article by the examples of the European Court of Human Rights and the WTO dispute settlement system. On this basis, the article argues that we should not see the relationship between statehood legitimacy (based optimally on electoral democracy) and supranational legitimacy (based on public reason) as mutually antagonistic and engaged in zero-sum competition. Rather, this relationship allows scope for synergy, with supranational authorities often playing an important role in supporting democracy at the nation-state level.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015
References
1 Wiener, A, Lang, AF Jr, Tully, J, Maduro, M Poiares and Kumm, M, ‘Global Constitutionalism: Human Rights, Democracy and the Rule of Law’ (2012) 1 Global Constitutionalism 1, 4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
2 de Búrca, G, ‘Developing Democracy Beyond the State’ (2008) 46 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 221, 235.Google Scholar
3 For a good discussion of different meanings of ‘autonomy’ of international organisations, see Peters, A, ‘The Constitutionalisation of International Organisations’ in Walker, N, Shaw, J and Tierney, S (eds), Europe’s Constitutional Mosaic (Hart, Oxford, 2011) 253, 257–61.Google Scholar
4 A good example is provided by the Court of ECOWAS (the Economic Community of West African States), see Alter, KJ, Helfer, LR and McAllister, JR, ‘A New International Human Rights Court for West Africa: The ECOWAS Community Court of Justice’ (2013) 107 American Journal of International Law 737.Google Scholar
5 These are some of the criteria distinguishing ‘transnational’ from ‘interstate’ dispute resolution discussed and used by Keohane, RO, Moravcsik, A and Slaughter, A-M, ‘Legalized Dispute Resolution: Interstate and Transnational’ (2000) 54 International Organization 457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6 On the ‘autonomous meanings’ doctrine of the ECtHR, see below, Part III.
7 See Wiener et al. (n 1) 6, emphasis added.
8 See e.g. Follesdal, A, ‘When Common Interests Are Not Common: Why the Global Basic Structure Should Be Democratic’ (2009) 16 Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 585CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Zürn, M, ‘Democratic Governance Beyond the Nation-State: The EU and Other International Institutions’ (2000) 6 European Journal of International Relations 183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
9 Elsewhere I have discussed EU’s democratic deficit in detail, see Sadurski, W, ‘Democratic Legitimacy of the European Union: A Diagnosis and Some Modest Proposals’ (2012) 32 Polish Yearbook of International Law 9.Google Scholar
10 See e.g. Eriksen, EO, The Unfinished Democratization of Europe (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cohen, J and Sabel, CF, ‘Global Democracy?’ (2005) 37 NYU Journal of International Law and Politics 763.Google Scholar
11 See, inter alia, Follesdal (n 8), Zürn (n 8).
12 Dryzek, J, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2002) 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
13 Bohman, J, ‘From Demos to Demoi: Democracy across Borders’ (2005) 18 Ratio Juris 293, 305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
14 De Búrca (n 2) 237.
15 Ibid 251, 276.
16 See Dworkin, R, Sovereign Virtue (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 2000) 204.Google Scholar
17 See Sadurski, W, Equality and Legitimacy (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2008) 1–17, 237–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
18 This connection between the legitimacy of a rule and ‘a pull towards compliance’ by its addressees is emphasised in the key, classical book-length treatment of legitimacy in the international sphere, Franck, TM, The Power of Legitimacy Among Nations (Oxford University Press, New York, 1990) 16Google Scholar; see also 24, 111–12.
19 Raz, J, Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1994) 211–15.Google Scholar
20 For an interpretation of Raz’s theory along these lines, see Sadurski (n 17) 3–17.
21 For a representative exposition of a stronger meaning of legitimacy, in which there is a direct connection between legitimacy and a duty to comply by virtue of morally significant relations (especially, consensual relations) between state and subject, see the Locke-inspired account in Simmons, AJ, ‘Justification and Legitimacy’ (1999) 109 Ethics 739.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
22 For such an approach, see Buchanan, A, ‘The Legitimacy of International Law’ in Besson, S and Tasioulas, J (eds), The Philosophy of International Law (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010) 79–80.Google Scholar
23 Pettit, P: On the People’s Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2012) 139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
24 See Rawls, J, Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press, New York, 1993) 212–54Google Scholar; Rawls, J, ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’ in The Law of Peoples (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1999) 129–80Google Scholar; Larmore, C, ‘Public Reason’ in Freeman, S (ed), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2003) 368Google Scholar; Sadurski, W, ‘Reason of State and Public Reason’ (2014) 27 Ratio Juris 21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
25 Forst, R, ‘The Justification of Human Rights and the Basic Right to Justification: A Reflexive Approach’ (2010) 120 Ethics 711CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Neyer, J, ‘Justice, Not Democracy: Legitimacy in the European Union’ (2010) 48 Journal of Common Market Studies 903, 908–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
26 Larmore, C, The Autonomy of Morality (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2008) 146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
27 Rawls, J, The Law of Peoples (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1999).Google Scholar
28 Ibid 55, emphasis added.
29 Ibid 55.
30 Ibid 56
31 Ibid 57.
32 Ibid 3.
33 See Rawls, Political Liberalism (n 24) 212–54; Rawls, ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’ (n 24) 129–80; C Larmore (n 24); Sadurski (n 24).
34 For a theory of international human rights, based on epistemic requirements of a credible public justification, see Buchanan, A, ‘Human Rights and the Legitimacy of the International Order’ (2008) 14 Legal Theory 39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar For an epistemic approach to the practice of the WTO, see Thomas, CA, ‘Of Facts and Phantoms: Economics, Epistemic Legitimacy, and WTO Dispute Settlement’ (2011) 14 Journal of International Economic Law 295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
35 Neyer (n 25) 913.
36 Ibid 912.
37 For an early discussion of this aspect of supranational adjudication, see Helfer, LR and Slaughter, A-M, ‘Towards a Theory of Effective Supranational Adjudication’ (1997) 107 Yale Law Journal 273, 287–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
38 For my detailed discussion of pilot judgments, see Sadurski, W, ‘Partnering with Strasbourg: Constitutionalisation of the European Court of Human Rights, the Accession of Central and East European States to the Council of Europe, and the Idea of Pilot Judgments’ (2009) 9 Human Rights Law Review 397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
39 Kumm, M, ‘Institutionalising Socratic Contestation: The Rationalist Human Rights Paradigm, Legitimate Authority and the Point of Judicial Review’ (2007) 1(2) European Journal of Legal Studies 12, italics removed.Google Scholar
40 For more on this aspect of proportionality, but also on the weaknesses of this approach, see Sadurski, W, ‘Reasonableness and Value Pluralism in Law and Politics’ in Bongiovanni, G, Sartor, G and Valentini, C (eds), Reasonableness and Law (Springer, Dordrecht, 2009) 129, 137–40.Google Scholar
41 Glendon, MA, Rights Talk (The Free Press, New York, 1991) 155.Google Scholar
42 For illustrations and discussion of these alliances, see Sadurski, W, Constitutionalism and the Enlargement of Europe (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2012) 27–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
43 Dothan, S, ‘How International Courts Enhance Their Legitimacy’ (2013) 14 Theoretical Inquiries in Law 455, 463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
44 Cossey v United Kingdon, 184 ECHR ser A (1990).
45 On the link between the doctrine of effectiveness and the finding of positive obligations, see van Dijk, P and van Hoof, GJH, Theory and Practice of the European Convention on Human Rights (3rd edn, Kluwer Law International, The Hague, 1998) 75.Google Scholar As an example, they provide freedom of assembly (art 11) which was found by the Court to correlate not merely with a prohibition on state interference with assemblies, but also with a duty on the State to protect demonstrators against physical violence by counter-demonstrators, see ibid 75 n 11.
46 See, e.g., Engel and Others v the Netherlands, Judgment of 8 June 1976, series A No 22, 1 EHRR 647.
47 For a subtle discussion of this point, see Letsas, G, A Theory of Interpretation of the European Convention on Human Rights (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2007) 37–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
48 See, e.g., Matthews v United Kingdom, Judgment of 18 February 1999, Reports 1999-I, para 39.
49 These ‘new rights’ are listed by Zwart, T, ‘More human rights than Court: Why the legitimacy of the European Court of Human Rights is in need of repair and how it can be done’ in Flogaitis, S, Zwart, T and Fraser, J (eds), The European Court of Human Rights and Its Discontents (Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, 2013) 71, 87–8.Google Scholar
50 Art 53(1) of the European Convention on Human Rights.
51 For a comparison of two European Courts, see Helfer, LR, ‘Redesigning the European Court of Human Rights: Embeddedness as a Deep Structural Principle of the European Human Rights Regime’ (2008) 19 European Journal of International Law 125, 134–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
52 For a general discussion, and examples taken from Germany, Spain and France in particular, see Krisch, N, ‘The Open Architecture of European Human Rights Law’ (2008) 71 Modern Law Review 183, 187–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
53 See, e.g., Cass, D, The Constitutionalization of the World Trade Organization: Legitimacy, Democracy and Community in the International Trading System (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
54 Shlomo-Agon, S, ‘Clearing the Smoke Signals: The Legitimation of Judicial Power at the WTO’ (2015) 49 Journal of World Trade 539, 547.Google Scholar
55 For a subtle analysis, see ibid 563–87.
56 See ibid 568–70.
57 See ibid 581.
58 Howse, R and Nicolaidis, K, ‘Enhancing WTO Legitimacy: Constitutionalization or Global Subsidiarity?’ (2003) 16 Governance 73, 87, endnote omitted.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
59 Shlomo-Agon (n 54) 589.
60 Thomas, C, ‘The Concept of Legitimacy and International Law’, LSE Law, Society and Economy Working Papers 12/2013, <http://ssrn.com/abstract=2265503> 24, footnote omitted, accessed 7 August 2015.Google Scholar
61 European Communities, Second Written Submission in EC–Measures Affecting the Approval and Marketing of Biotech Products (19 July 2004)Google Scholar para 8, quoted in Lawrence, JC, ‘Contesting Constitutionalism: Constitutional Discourse at the WTO’ (2013) 2 Global Constitutionalism 63, 78, emphasis added.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
62 See Maduro, M Poiares, ‘Courts and Pluralism: Essay on a Theory of Judicial Adjudication in the Context of Legal and Constitutional Pluralism’ in Dunoff, JL and Trachtman, JP (eds), Ruling the World? Constitutionalism, International Law, and Global Governance (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2009) 356, 369.Google Scholar
63 Idem 369.
64 For a good discussion of these diverse approaches to state compliance, see Helfer, LR, ‘Constitutional Analogies in the International Legal System’ (2003) 37 Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review 193, 220–4.Google Scholar
65 Cohen and Sabel (n 10) 788, emphasis added.
66 M Kumm, ‘An Integrative Theory of Global Public Law: Cosmopolitan, Pluralist, Public Reason Oriented’ (unpublished draft, no date) at 51–2. I am grateful to Professor Kumm for his kind permission to refer to and quote this unpublished paper.
67 See, e.g., Constitution of Spain, art 10(2); Constitution of Portugal, art 16(2); Constitution of Colombia, art 93(2); Constitution of Romania, art 20(1); Constitution of South Africa, art 39(1).
68 Neuman, GL, ‘Human Rights and Constitutional Rights: Harmony and Dissonance’ (2003) 55 Stanford Law Review 1863, 1895–7.Google Scholar
69 See, for instance, a series of admonitions by the ECtHR to the United Kingdom that it should amend its law which disenfranchises all convicted prisoners, Hirst v The United Kingdom (No 2), Judgment of 6 October 2005, App No 74025/01 and Greens and MT v The United Kingdom, Judgment of 23 November 2010, App Nos 60041/08 and 60054/08.
70 For analysis, see Sadurski (n 42) 148–55.
71 See Preuss, UK, ‘Perspectives on Post-Conflict Constitutionalism: Reflections on Regime Change Through External Constitutionalization’ (2006/07) 51 New York Law School Law Review 467, 493.Google Scholar
72 Kumm, M, ‘The Legitimacy of International Law: A Constitutionalist Framework of Analysis’ (2004) 15 European Journal of International Law 907, 919.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
73 For such a zero-sum-game approach, see Anne Peters’ theory of ‘compensatory constitutionalism’, Peters, A, ‘The Merits of Global Constitutionalism’ (2009) 16 Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
74 See Hart, HLA, The Concept of Law (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1961) 3, 77, 208–11.Google Scholar
75 Franck, TM, ‘The Emerging Right to Democratic Governance’ (1992) 86 American Journal of International Law 46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
76 Franck, TM, Fairness in International Law and Institutions (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1998) 29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar See, similarly, Peñalver, EM, ‘The Persistent Problem of Obligation in International Law’ (2000) 36 Stanford Journal of International Law 271, 283–4.Google Scholar
77 Vienna Convention on the Law of the Treaties, UN Doc A/CONF 39/27 (1969) art 26.
78 Dworkin, R, ‘A New Philosophy of International Law’ (2013) 41 Philosophy & Public Affairs 2, 9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
79 See in particular Fassbender, B, ‘The United Nations Charter as Constitution of the International Community’ (1988) 36 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 529.Google Scholar
80 See similarly Waldron, J, ‘Response: The Perils of Exaggeration’ (2011) 22 European Journal of International Law 389, 390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
81 See Grossman, N, ‘Legitimacy and International Adjudicative Bodies’ (2009) 41 The George Washington International Law Review 107Google Scholar; see also von Bogdandy, A and Venzke, I, ‘On the Democratic Legitimation of International Judicial Lawmaking’ (2011) 12 German Law Journal 1341, 1356–68.Google Scholar
- 11
- Cited by