Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T19:06:10.976Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Secession and Annexation: The Case of Crimea

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The recent crisis involving the territory of Crimea has been characterized both as a case of wrongful annexation and as one of rightful secession. Territory and competing territorial claims lie at the heart of the normative questions of secession and annexation. Any normative theory of secession or of annexation must therefore address their territorial aspect: It must explain why one agent rather than another has a valid claim to the disputed territory. One of the most interesting, yet controversial, normative accounts of secession has been offered by choice theorists of secession. Choice theorists adopt a rather permissive stance, based on the normative significance of political self-determination. Choice theories, however, have been widely criticized for failing to provide a satisfactory account of what legitimates the seceding group's territorial claim. This article argues that it is possible to remedy choice theories’ failure to address the question of territorial justification adequately. To do so, this article offers a two-tier account of territory that is grounded in the normative significance of self-determination. It defends this account of territory by showing that it is implied by our normative condemnation of annexation. It argues that the same reasons that warrant opposition to annexation provide support for secession, In closing, this article revisits the case of Crimea in light of its two-tier account of territory, and considers what role international law and institutions might play in addressing this type of situation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2015 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 The referendum took place on 16 March 2014. Results reported by election officials indicated ninety-five percent of votes in favor of joining Russia, based on eighty percent of papular participation. See BBC, Crimea Referendum: Voters “Back Russia Union,” (Mar. 16, 2014), http://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-26606097 (last accessed June 18, 2015); BBC, Crimea Exit Poll: About 93% Back Russia Union, (Mar. 16, 2014), http://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-26598832 (last accessed June 18, 2015).Google Scholar

2 Here and throughout, the term “normative” is used in its moral-philosophical sense, not in Its legal-juridical sense.Google Scholar

3 See, infra note 10.Google Scholar

4 See, infra note 7.Google Scholar

5 For a taxonomy and review of those different theories, see Buchanan, Allen, Theories of Secession, 26 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 30 (1997); Moore, Margaret, Introduction: The Self-Determination Principle and the Ethics of Secession, in National Self-Determination and Secession 1 (Margaret Moore ed., 1998).Google Scholar

6 For the former type of criticism, see Buchanan, supra note 5. For the latter type of criticism, see Moore, supra note 5.Google Scholar

7 See Buchanan, Allen, Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (2004); Moore, supra note 5.Google Scholar

8 See, infra Part F.Google Scholar

9 Such as the principle that only national groups can have valid secessionist and territorial claims —as nationalist theorists of secession would argue—or that the legitimacy of an existing state is a sufficient condition not to violate its territorial integrity—as just-cause theorists of secession would argue. For examples of nationalist theories, see Margalit, Avishai & Raz, Joseph, National Self-Determination, 87 J. Phil. 439 (1990); Miller, David, Secession and the Principle of Nationality, in National Self-Determination and Secession 62 (Margaret Moore ed., 1998); Kymlicka, Will, Territorial Boundaries: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective, in Boundaries and Justice: Diverse Ethical Perspectives 249 (Miller, David & Sohail Hashmi eds., 2001). For an example of just-cause theory, see Buchanan, Allen, Secession: The Morality of Political Divorce from Fort Sumter to Lithuania and Quebec (1991); Buchanan, supra note 7.Google Scholar

10 For such comprehensive defenses, see Altman, Andrew & Wellman, Christopher, A Liberal Theory of International Justice (2009); Beran, Harry, A Democratic Theory of Political Self-Determination for a New World Order, in Theories of Secession 33 (Percy B. Lehning ed., 1998); Copp, David, Democracy and Communal Self-Determination, in The Morality of Nationalism 277 (McKim, Robert & Jeff McMahan eds., 1997); Philpott, Daniel, In Defense of Self-Determination, 105 Ethics 352 (1995); Wellman, Christopher, A Theory of Secession: The Case for Political Self-Determination (2005).Google Scholar

11 See, infra notes 12–13.Google Scholar

12 See the nationalist theories advanced by Margalit & Raz, supra note 9; Miller, supra note 9; Kymlicka, supra note 9.Google Scholar

13 See Altman & Wellman, supra note 10, at 47; Beran, supra note 10, at 42; Copp, supra note 10, at 278, 289; Philpott, supra note 10, at 365-66; Wellman, supra note 10, at 112.Google Scholar

14 See sources cited, supra note 10.Google Scholar

15 For more on just-cause theories, see Buchanan, supra note 9; Buchanan, supra note 7.Google Scholar

16 Beran, supra note 10, at 32, 36, 38–39Google Scholar

17 See id. at 39.Google Scholar

18 For more on the distinction between Westphalian and past-Westphalian conceptions of state sovereignty, see discussion infra Part E, and David Held, Democracy: From City-States to a Cosmopolitan Order, 40 Pol. Studs. 10 (1992).Google Scholar

15 See Buchanan supra note 9, at 108-09; Buchanan, supra note 7, at 219, 231.Google Scholar

20 Beran, supra note 10, at 35.Google Scholar

21 Copp, supra note 10, at 278, 293,Google Scholar

22 Id. at 282.Google Scholar

23 Copp, David, International Law and Morality in the Theory of Secession, 2 J. Ethics 219, 229 (1993).Google Scholar

24 Id. at 227.Google Scholar

26 Philpott, supra note 10, at 355.Google Scholar

27 Id. at 370.Google Scholar

29 id. at 370, 376.Google Scholar

30 Id. at 370-71 n. 37.Google Scholar

31 Philpott, supra note 10, at 370.Google Scholar

32 See Wellman, supra note 10, at 14–15; Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia 10–53 (1974); Buchanan, supra note 5, at 47.Google Scholar

33 Philpott, supra note 10, at 362, 364.Google Scholar

34 Altman & Wellman, supra note 10, at 46, Adequate protection of human rights is hereafter referred to simply as “adequate protection.”Google Scholar

35 Wellman, supra note 10, at 37.Google Scholar

36 Id. at 37–38.Google Scholar

37 Wellman, supra note 10, at 179; Altman & Wellman, supra note 10, at 52–53.Google Scholar

38 See discussion, infra Part E.Google Scholar

39 See Buchanan, supra note 7, at 219, 231; Bishai, Linda, Forgetting Ourselves: Secession and the (Im)possibility of Territorial Identity 74–75 (2004),Google Scholar

40 Buchanan, supra note 9, at 108-09; Buchanan, supra note 7, at 219.Google Scholar

41 One might object that using the principle of community property to build this analogy is question-begging: Why pick this principle rather than other possible principles of marriage contracts? Because the principle of community property constitutes a middle ground between the two extremes of complete merging and complete separation of assets. Thus, the burden of proof here is on those claiming that a more extreme principle should be used. Of course, opting for complete separation of assets would only reinforce the secessionists’ case.Google Scholar

42 Otherwise put, what makes a group the same group over time is not a matter of what the group is—matching some set of objective criteria—but rather a matter of what the group does—engaged in sustained social and political cooperation,Google Scholar

43 This article's territorial account is in some respects similar to, yet in other respects crucially different from, an account offered by Anna Stilz. See Stilz, Anna, Nations, States, and Territory, 121 Ethics 572, 578, 588-89 (2011). For specific differences between the two accounts, see, infra notes 45 and 47.Google Scholar

44 Cf. Oklopcic, Zoran, The idea of Early-Conflict Constitution-Making: The Conflict in Ukraine Beyond Territorial Rights and Constitutional Paradoxes, 16 German L.J. 658 (2015).Google Scholar

45 Here this article's territorial account parts ways with Stilz's, which precludes the permissibility of secession arguably, inconsistently. See Stilz, supra note 43, at 597, 600. Indeed, the required rights of free association, free speech, and political participation would imply the rights for a group to select its political representatives and to form parties advocating secession as well as local governments holding plebiscites on the possibility of secession. If those measures are permitted, then respecting the democratic process would seem to require granting secessionists negotiations, should the majority be in favor of secession. See Norman, Wayne, Domesticating Secession, in Secession and Self-Determination 193, 207 (Macedo, Stephen & Allen Buchanan eds., 2003). Indeed, this is the position adopted by the Canadian Supreme Court in its 1998 “Reference” on the Quebec secession issue. See Buchanan, supra note 7, at 224.Google Scholar

46 Note that choice theorists’ exclusion of nationalist arguments from the set of normatively relevant considerations to determine the permissibility of secession does not mean that national groups, such as the Scots, cannot qualify for permissible secession on a choice account. As long as the new state would meet the choice criteria of viability and of human rights protection, secession is permissible. But it is permissible in virtue of the fulfillment of those criteria, and not in light of the fact that the group is a national group.Google Scholar

47 Here this article's territorial account further departs from Still's, according to which the relevant type of group is that which results from the formation of the state. See Stilz, supra note 43, at 579–80.Google Scholar

48 Note that settling the territorial question—who has a valid claim to what territory—does not yet settle the question of secession. As mentioned at the outset, the aim of this article is not to provide a comprehensive account of morally permissible secession. In addition to the territorial component which has been the focus of this article, other considerations would have to be taken into account in order to establish a full moral case in favor of secession—for example, a peaceable and transparent referendum, the viability of the remainder state, fair terms of separation regarding economic and natural resources, etc. Thus, having a valid territorial claim is a necessary but not sufficient condition for secession to be permissible.Google Scholar

49 It is a prima facie case because other considerations might override it. See, supra note 48.Google Scholar

50 See also, MacLaren, Malcolm, “Trust the People”? Democratic Secessionism and Contemporary Practice, 16 German L.J. 631 (2015).Google Scholar

51 One might abject that there are minorities within the Crimean territory that might not support the secession of Crimea. See Roth, Brad R., The Virtues of Bright Lines: Self-Determination, Secession, and External Intervention, 16 German L.J. 384 (2015); Roznai, Yaniv & Suteu, Silvia, The Eternal Territory? The Crimean Crisis and Ukraine's Territorial Integrity as an Unamendable Constitutional Principle, 16 German L.J. 542 (2015). See also, Oklopcic, supra note 44. But the problem of “trapped minorities” is not specific to newly seceded polities; it is a reality that many polities, old and new, have to face. Moreover, secession would alleviate, rather than exacerbate, the problem. Secession indeed frees a minority from the old polity in which it was previously trapped. So a concern for trapped minorities supports, rather than undermines, the case for secession. See MacLaren, supra note 50.Google Scholar

52 Jennings, Ivor, The Approach to Self-Government 56 (1956).Google Scholar

53 See sources cited supra note 51; MacLaren, supra note 50; Umut Özsu, Ukraine, International Law, and the Political Economy of Self-Determination, 16 German L.J. 434 (2015).Google Scholar

54 This is not to say that one should ignore the normatively problematic self-serving motives that underlie the rhetoric of self-determination used by some secessionist groups and their supporters or opponents, See Öszu, supra note 53. But those can be countered or neutralized by requiring that certain conditions be met far secession to be permissible—for example, a peaceable and transparent referendum, the viability of the remainder state, fair terms of separation regarding economic and natural resources, etc. Google Scholar

55 Mill, John Stuart, Considerations on Representative Government, in Utilitarianism, on Liberty, Considerations on Representative Government 392 (H.B. Acton ed., 1972) (1862). See also, MacLaren, supra note 50, at 634.Google Scholar

56 Buchanan, supra note 5, at 32.Google Scholar

57 Buchanan, supra note 7, at 27.Google Scholar

58 Buchanan, supra note 5, at 42–44.Google Scholar

59 See id. at 44–54.Google Scholar

60 Altman & Wellman, supra note 10, at 53–58; Weinstock, Daniel, Constitutionalizing the Right to Secede, 9 J. Pol. Phil. 182, 183 (2001).Google Scholar

61 Buchanan, supra note 5, at 49.Google Scholar

62 See id. at 47.Google Scholar

63 Catala, Amandine, Remedial Theories of Secession and Territoriol Justification, 44 J. Soc. Phil. 74 (2013).Google Scholar

64 Weinstock, supra note 60, at 185.Google Scholar

65 Relatedly, the existence of a moral right does not depend on how easy or difficult it would be to realize that right. If you are a millionaire, it might be very easy for you to give me $100, but that does not mean I have the right to receive $100 from you. Conversely, if you hit me with your car and you have no insurance, it might be very difficult for you to compensate me appropriately, but that does not mean that I do not have the right to receive appropriate compensation.Google Scholar

66 Altman & Wellman, supra note 10, at 62.Google Scholar

67 Cf. Roth, supra note 51.Google Scholar

68 See Vidmar, Jure, The Annexation of Crimea and the Boundaries of the Will of the People, 16 German L.J. 365 (2015); MacLaren, supra note 50.Google Scholar