Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-01T05:04:10.674Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Intentionality and Economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Allin Cottrell
Affiliation:
Wake Forest University

Extract

In his recent book, Economics – Mathematical Politics or Science of Diminishing Returns, Alexander Rosenberg has offered a forceful critique of the scientific pretensions of economics. I am encouraged to note that in his JEL review, Wade Hands (1993) singles out Rosenberg's ‘important discussion of intentionality’ as one of the most significant aspects of the book. Encouraged, because this was exactly my impression, and Hands's judgment confirmed my intention to respond to Rosenberg's argument. I hope, however, to be able to disappoint Hands's expectation that this aspect of Rosenberg's work ‘will be least challenged by economists’!

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Anscombe, G. E. M. 1957. Intention. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Brentano, Franz. [1924] 1973. Psychology From an Empirical Standpoint. Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick. 1957. Perceiving: A Philosophical Study. Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Patricia S. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain. MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1981. ‘Eliminative materialism and the prepositional attitudes’. Journal of Philosophy, 78: 6790. Reprinted in Rosenthal (1991), pp. 601-12Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1984. Matter and Consciousness. MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 1978. Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. Bradford BooksGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 1987. The Intentional Stance. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 1988. ‘Précis of The Intentional Stance’ (with Open Peer Commentary). Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11:495546CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farjoun, E. 1984. ‘The production of commodities by means of what?’ In Ricardo, Marx, Sraffa, pp. 1141. Freeman, A. and Mandel, E. (eds.). VersoGoogle Scholar
Hands, D. Wade. 1993. Review of Rosenberg (1992). Journal of Economic Literature, 31:888–90Google Scholar
Keynes, J. M. 1936. The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money. MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Keynes, J. M. 1973. The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, Vol. XIV. Moggridge, D. E. (ed.). Macmillan for the Royal Economic SocietyGoogle Scholar
Keynes, J. M. 1979. The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, Vol. XXIX. Moggridge, D. E. (ed.). Macmillan for the Royal Economic SocietyGoogle Scholar
Kyburg, Henry. 1983. ‘Rational belief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6:2374CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, K. 1976. Capital, Volume 1. PenguinGoogle Scholar
O'Donnell, Rod M. 1989. Keynes: Philosophy, Economics and Politics. St. Martin's PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1960. Word and Object. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alexander. 1992. Economics – Mathematical Politics or Science of Diminishing Returns? University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, David M. (ed.). 1991. The Nature of Mind. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Runde, Jochen. 1991. ‘Keynesian uncertainty and the instability of beliefs’. Review of Political Economy, 3:124–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sraffa, Piero. 1960. Production of Commodities by Means of Commodities. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Stich, Stephen P. 1983. From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief. MIT PressGoogle Scholar