Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:34:03.579Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Tough-Minded” Theories in Ethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 April 2009

Michael Weber
Affiliation:
Yale University

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Interventions/Discussions
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 James, William, Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking (New York: Longman, Green, 1907), Lecture 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 See my “The Resilience of the Allais Paradox,” Ethics, 109 (1998): 94118.Google Scholar

3 Of course this is not the only response available to the psychological egoist, and may well not be the best. I focus on it because of how it parallels replies to objections to other tough-minded theories, all of which I think fail for the same reason.

4 Feinberg, Joel argues similarly in “Psychological Egoism,” in his edited volume Reason and Responsibility: Readings in Some Basic Problems of Philosophy, 9th ed. (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1996), pp. 497508.Google Scholar

5 There are many kinds of utilitarianism, including “average” and “rule” utilitarianism. I will not be considering such alternatives, though I think that the general run of argument that I pursue can equally be applied to these alternative forms of utilitarianism. I will also not consider non-aggregative forms of consequentialism, which may be able to avoid the pitfalls I discuss here.

6 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 27.Google Scholar

7 A similar argument is in Williams, Bernard, “Consequentialism and Integrity,” in Scheffler, Samuel, ed., Consequentialism and Its Critics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988).Google Scholar

8 This is not to build egoism into rational-choice theory, as one may attach utility to good outcomes for others.

9 Savage, Leonard, The Foundations of Statistics, 2nd rev. ed. (New York: Wiley, 1972).Google Scholar

10 The Allais Paradox originates with Maurice Allais, in, e.g., “The Foundations of a Positive Theory of Choice Involving Risk and a Critique of the Postulates of the American School,” in Allais, M. and Hagen, O., eds., Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 See, for example, Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk,” Econometica, 47 (1979): 263–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and MacCrimmons, Kenneth, “Descriptive and Normative Implications of the Decision-Theory Postulates,” in Borch, K. and Mossin, J., eds., Risk and Uncertainty (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1968).Google Scholar

12 This is unaffected by the declining marginal utility of money because the dollar figures in states of affairs m and n are the same for options A and B and for options C and D. The declines, then, will be identical in each case.

13 Another is disappointment, which I will not consider here.

14 John Broome is the most recent prominent advocate of this general strategy. See his Weighing Goods (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991), pp. 93100.Google Scholar

15 Indeed, a bad association with instances of good decision-making that turned out badly (cases of outcome regret) could thwart good decision-making in the future.

16 See Nozick, Robert, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), pp. 2223.Google Scholar