Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T08:16:00.976Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reason, Value and Desire*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2010

Jan Narveson
Affiliation:
University of Waterloo

Extract

The general subject of Professor Bond's book, Reason and Value, is, as the title implies, the relation between reason and value, or more precisely the connections between concepts of motivation and value, with reasons as the contested notion in between. Bond offers a thesis that at least appears to go very much against the current trend on these matters. Whereas most recent theorists of note have tied justificatory reasons as well as explanatory reasons to desire, thus holding, in effect, that values are somehow a function of desire, Bond wishes to cut the link between value and desire altogether. The first three chapters are devoted to developing this argument, mainly negatively. He distinguishes between “motivating” and “grounding” (or “justifying”) reasons in the customary way (e.g., Baier distinguishes “explanatory” from “justificatory” reasons to much the same effect'), and argues that “whereas desire or wanting and the reasons tied to it belong to the theory of motivation, where they are central, reason, in the sense of the reason(s) that a person has for or against doing a thing, is tied essentially to value, and the two are not to be confused” (9). “… The existence of grounding reasons (though not of motivating reasons) has no internal or necessary connection with desires of any kind” (37). “… All value is necessarily objective, in the sense that it is never a function of desire (or will); nothing is ever valuable or desirable in virtue of being desired” (84). “Value is not to any extent whatever a function or product of desire” (155).

Type
Critical Notices/Etudes critiques
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Baier, Kurt, The Moral Point of View (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1958), 148156, and more generally chap. 6Google Scholar.

2 All parenthesized numbers as references are to pages in the book under consideration.

3 Grice, G. R., The Grounds of Moral Judgment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967).Google Scholar It is worth noting that while Bond acknowledges a debt to Grice's “conclusive arguments to show that reasons (grounds) for acting are independent of desire”, he does not pay any attention to Grice's further insistence (18 of Grice) that “The only propositions which are properly understood as reasons for acting … are propositions which state either that × is in some way in accordance with A's interests or that × conduces to A's aims”.

4 MacKie, J. L., Ethics (Markham. ON: Penguin Books Canada. 1977). 3841Google Scholar.

5 Brandt, R. B., A Theory ofthe Good and the Right (New York: Oxford University Press, 1979)Google Scholar.

6 Lewis, C. I., An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation (LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1946)Google Scholar.

7 An interesting instance that comes to mind and should be of particular interest to Bond (andreaders) is Butchvarov, P., “That Simple, Indefinable, Nonnatural Property Good', Review of Metaphysics 36/1 (September 1982),Google Scholar though this was published while Bond's book was in press, of course.

8 Lewis, An Analysis, 432.

9 Narveson, J., Morality and Utility (Baltimore. MD: Johns Hopkins Press. 1967). 5766Google Scholar.