Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T01:35:56.824Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Syntomic cycle classes and prismatic Poincaré duality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 October 2024

Longke Tang*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ 08544, USA [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We introduce $F$-gauges over a prism, construct syntomic cycle classes, and prove the prismatic Poincaré duality for proper smooth schemes.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Compositio Mathematica is © Foundation Compositio Mathematica.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024

1. Introduction

1.1 Goal

Poincaré duality is one of the most classical theorems in algebraic topology, saying that if $X$ is a compact oriented manifold of dimension $d$, then its singular cohomologies with coefficient in a field $k$ satisfy

\begin{align*} \mathrm{H}^i(X,k)^\vee\cong\mathrm{H}^{d-i}(X,k), \end{align*}

where $-^\vee$ denotes dual $k$-vector spaces.

If $X$ is now a projective complex manifold of dimension $d$, then the Hodge decomposition theorem states that

\begin{align*} \mathrm{H}^i(X,\mathbb{Z})\otimes_\mathbb{Z}\mathbb{C}\cong\bigoplus_{p+q=i}\mathrm{H}^q(X,\Omega^p_{X/\mathbb{C}}), \end{align*}

where $\Omega ^p_{X/\mathbb {C}}$ is the sheaf of holomorphic $p$-forms on $X$, and $\mathrm {H}^q(X,-)$ means the sheaf cohomology. From the proof of the above isomorphism, it is straightforward to see that the Poincaré duality on the left and the Serre duality on the right intertwine. Therefore, in terms of Hodge structures, one can write the duality as

(1)\begin{equation} \mathrm{R}\Gamma(X,\mathbb{Z})^\vee\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma(X,\mathbb{Z})(d)[2d], \end{equation}

where $-^\vee$ denotes the dual functor $\operatorname {RHom}(-,\mathbb {Z})$ in the derived category of Hodge structures. See, for example, [Reference Cattani, El Zein, Griffiths and TrángCEGT14, Example 3.1.5, Theorem 3.1.17].

An important consequence of the Poincaré duality is the cycle class, which associates a cohomology class $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}\in \mathrm {H}^r(X,\mathbb {Z})$ to a compact oriented submanifold $Y$ of codimension $r$ in a compact oriented manifold $X$.

If $X$ is again a projective complex manifold and $Y$ is its closed submanifold of complex codimension $r$, then the above cycle class, after tensoring with $\mathbb {C}$, actually lies in the direct summand $\mathrm {H}^r(X,\Omega ^r_{X/\mathbb {C}})$ in the Hodge decomposition. See, for example, [Reference Cattani, El Zein, Griffiths and TrángCEGT14, Lemma 3.1.27]. In terms of Hodge structures, this amounts to saying that the cycle class defines a map of Hodge structures

(2)\begin{equation} \mathrm{Cl}_{Y/X}\colon\mathbb{Z}\to\mathrm{H}^{2r}(X,\mathbb{Z})(r). \end{equation}

This paper aims to tell the above story for integral $p$-adic Hodge theory.

1.2 Results

In their remarkable paper [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22], Bhatt and Scholze defined the prismatic cohomology for schemes over a $p$-adic base, which specializes to various $p$-adic cohomologies known before, including étale, de Rham, and crystalline, also generalizing their previous works [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS18] and [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19] joint with Morrow.

As its name suggests, prismatic cohomology is based on prisms, which are roughly triples $(A,I,\varphi )$, where $A$ is a ring, $I$ is an invertible ideal, $\varphi \colon A\to A$ is a Frobenius lift, $A$ is $(p,I)$-complete, and finally $p\in (I,\varphi (I))$. See [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Definition 3.2] for a precise definition. Given such a structure, prismatic cohomology associates to every $A/I$-scheme $X$ a complex $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)\in \mathsf {D}(A)$, along with a $\varphi$-semilinear Frobenius $F\colon \mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)\to \mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)$ and a so-called Nygaard filtration $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \varphi ^*\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)$, from which one can recover the étale, de Rham, and crystalline cohomologies of $X$; see [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Theorems 1.8 and 1.16].

Given the above construction, the reader might have noticed that, in the $p$-adic setting, prismatic cohomology should play the role of singular cohomology with a Hodge structure, and the outputs of prismatic cohomology should play the role of Hodge structures. This is indeed the case. The structures in these outputs are summarized in § 2 as follows.

Definition 1.1 (Definitions 2.25, 2.30, 2.31, and 2.32; Examples 2.29 and 2.33)

An $F$-gauge over a prism $(A,I)$ is a triple $(M,\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \varphi ^*M,F)$ where $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \varphi ^*M$ is a filtration on $\varphi ^*M$ and $F\colon \operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \varphi ^*M\to I^\bullet M$ exhibits $I^\bullet M$ as a filtered base change of $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \varphi ^*M$ along $A\to A[1/I]$. The category of $F$-gauges over $(A,I)$ is denoted ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$.

The outputs of prismatic cohomology are $F$-gauges, and there are various specialization functors from ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$, corresponding to Hodge–Tate, de Rham, and étale specializations of prismatic cohomology. In addition, there are Breuil–Kisin twists $A\{n\}$ of $F$-gauges for all $n\in \mathbb {Z}$ that are analogous to Tate twists $\mathbb {Z}(n)$ of complex Hodge structures.

With $F$-gauges in hand, one can now easily write down the $p$-adic analog of the isomorphism (1), the prismatic Poincaré duality.

Theorem 1.2 (Theorem 6.4)

For a proper smooth $A/I$-scheme $X$ of dimension $d$, there is a canonical isomorphism of $F$-gauges

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)^\vee\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)\{d\}[2d]. \end{align*}

Proving the above theorem is not as easy as stating it. In the case of étale cohomology, with the help of its 6-functor formalism, one essentially localizes, factorizes, and finally treats $\mathbb {A}^1$. While it might be possible, we choose not to develop a prismatic 6-functor formalism here. In the case of de Rham cohomology, [Aut, 0FW3] tried hard and managed to construct a trace map $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {dR}(X/k)\to k$ that induces a perfect pairing after the cup product; we are not sure whether this method will work here either. Instead, we follow and improve the method of the recent lecture notes [Reference ClausenCla21], which first constructed the de Rham cycle class, then applied it to the diagonal, obtaining a copairing

\begin{align*} k\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{dR}(X/k)\otimes\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{dR}(X/k)[2d], \end{align*}

and finally proved its perfectness by reduction to the Hodge case. Note that the logical order here is reverse to that in classical algebraic topology, where one constructs the cycle class using the Poincaré duality.

As suggested by the map (2) in the complex case, the prismatic cycle class should actually be an $F$-gauge map

\begin{align*} \mathrm{Cl}_{Y/X}^{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}\colon A\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)\{r\}[2r], \end{align*}

instead of merely an element of $\mathrm {H}^{2r}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)$. This brings us to consider the following.

Definition 1.3 (Proposition 2.35, cf. [Reference Antieau, Krause and NikolausAKN22, § 4])

For an $A/I$-scheme $X$, its $n$th syntomic cohomology relative to $A$, denoted by $\mathbb {Z}_p(n)(X/A)$, is the complex

\begin{align*} \operatorname{RHom}_{{F\text{-}\mathsf{Gauge}}(A,I)}(A,\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)\{n\})\in\mathsf{D}(\mathbb{Z}_p). \end{align*}

While the relative syntomic cohomology seems hard to control, its absolute counterpart has long been considered by $K$-theorists as the $p$-adic motivic cohomology, cf. [Reference NiziołNiz06], and has recently been redefined using the absolute prismatic cohomology by [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19] and [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a]. Since the absolute syntomic cohomology naturally maps to the relative one, construction of the relative syntomic cycle class boils down to that of the absolute one, which is another main result of this paper.

Theorem 1.4 (Definitions 5.26 and 5.32; Remarks 5.28 and 5.29)

There is a unique functorial way to associate a syntomic cohomology class $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}^\mathrm {syn}\in \mathrm {H}^{2r}_\mathrm {syn}(X,\mathbb {Z}_p(r))$ to every regular immersion $Y\to X$ of codimension $r$, satisfying the following.

Multiplicativity: for regular immersions $Y\to X$ and $Y'\to X'$, we have $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}^\mathrm {syn}\boxtimes \mathrm {Cl}_{Y'/X'}^\mathrm {syn}=\mathrm {Cl}_{(Y\times Y')/(X\times X')}^\mathrm {syn}$.

Normalization for divisors: in codimension one, $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}^\mathrm {syn}=c_1(\mathcal {O}(Y))$ is the first Chern class defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, §§ 7.5, 8.4].

Moreover, the syntomic cycle class can be upgraded to a syntomic Gysin map

(3)\begin{equation} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{syn}(Y,\mathbb{Z}_p(n))\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{syn}(X,\mathbb{Z}_p(n+r))[2r]. \end{equation}

We also relate the syntomic Gysin map above to the pushforward map in $K$-theory via the motivic filtration. In the following theorem, let $K$ denote the $p$-completed étale $K$-theory, which is motivic filtered by $\mathbb {Z}_p(n)$ by [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19, § 7.4].

Theorem 1.5 (Theorem 5.38)

There is a unique way to enhance the pushforward $K(Y)\to K(X)$ to a motivic filtered map $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet K(Y)\to \operatorname {Fil}^{\bullet +r}K(X)$ functorially for all regular immersions $Y\to X$ of codimension $r$ of $p$-formal stacks. Moreover, its associated graded map coincides with the map (3).

Remark 1.6 The functoriality in the above two theorems is with respect to only pullbacks of regular immersions rather than compositions of them. We are not going to pursue the latter functoriality in this work, but we hope to address it in a future project, where a more general Gysin map construction based on the $\mathbb {P}^1$-motivic homotopy theory developed in [Reference Annala, Hoyois and IwasaAHI24] will be given.

1.3 Conventions

Fix a prime $p$ throughout. By ‘rings’ we mean commutative rings. Everything is animated or derived unless otherwise stated, that is:

  • by ‘categories’ we mean $\infty$-categories, unless we say “$1$-categories”;

  • by ‘modules’ we mean complexes, unless we say “classical modules”;

  • by ‘rings’ we mean animated rings, unless we say “classical rings”;

However, by ‘sets’ we still mean $0$-groupoids, because we have ‘animas’ for $\infty$-groupoids.

2. $F$-gauges over a prism

We start by defining the notions of gauges and $F$-gauges over a prism, which are meant to capture the bunch of structures in the relative prismatic cohomology. Thus, in this section we fix an animated prism $(A,I)$ as defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22b, Definition 2.4], and everything we are going to talk about will be $(p,I)$-complete whenever it is over $A$, unless otherwise stated. For example, $\mathsf {D}(A)$ will denote the $(p,I)$-complete derived category of $A$. Readers not familiar with animated prisms can assume that $(A,I)$ is a bounded classical prism. Let $\bar {A}=A/I$.

2.1 Reminders on filtered objects

In this subsection we recall the definition of filtered objects and some basic constructions on them, roughly following [Reference LurieLur17, § 1.2.2] and [Reference RaksitRak20, § 3.1, § 3.2]. Let $\mathcal {C}$ be a stable $\infty$-category.

Definition 2.1 (Filtered objects)

A filtered object $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M$ of $\mathcal {C}$ is a functor $\mathbb {Z}^\mathrm {op}\to \mathcal {C}$, where $\mathbb {Z}=(\mathbb {Z},\le )$ is the poset viewed as a category. We denote its value on $n\in \mathbb {Z}$ by $\operatorname {Fil}^nM$. The $n$th graded piece of $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M$ is defined as $\operatorname {Fil}^nM/\operatorname {Fil}^{n+1}M$ and is denoted $\operatorname {gr}^nM$. If $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M$ has all its graded pieces vanishing, namely it takes all arrows in $\mathbb {Z}^\mathrm {op}$ to isomorphisms, then we call it a constant filtered object.

The category of filtered objects of $\mathcal {C}$ is defined as the functor category $\mathsf {Fun}(\mathbb {Z}^\mathrm {op},\mathcal {C})$ and is denoted $\mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})$. All the graded pieces assemble to a functor $\operatorname {gr}\colon \mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})\to \mathcal {C}^\mathbb {Z}$, called taking associated graded objects. Taking constant objects is also a functor $\operatorname {const}\colon \mathcal {C}\to \mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})$.

Remark 2.2 (Increasing filtrations)

What Definition 2.1 defines are the so-called decreasing filtrations, in that if we do the same construction for an abelian category and require all the transition maps to be injective, then $\operatorname {Fil}^nM$ gets smaller when $n$ gets larger. One can similarly define increasing filtrations as functors $\mathbb {Z}\to \mathcal {C}$, where the same theory applies with indices reversed. We will sometimes use increasing filtrations below, and these will be denoted by $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet M$.

Definition 2.3 (Underlying objects)

Suppose $\mathcal {C}$ admits countable colimits. Then ${\operatorname {const}\colon \mathcal {C}\to \mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})}$ has an obvious left adjoint, given by

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M \mapsto \mathop{\operatorname{colim}}\limits_{n\to-\infty}\operatorname{Fil}^nM. \end{align*}

We call it the underlying object of $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M$ and denote it by $M$.

Definition 2.4 (Day convolution)

Suppose $\mathcal {C}$ admits countable colimits, and let $\otimes$ be a symmetric monoidal structure on it compatible with countable colimits. Then there is a natural symmetric monoidal structure on $\mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})$ called Day convolution, defined as

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^r(M\otimes N)=\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}\limits_{m+n\ge r}(\operatorname{Fil}^mM\otimes\operatorname{Fil}^nN), \end{align*}

where the colimit is taken over the full subcategory of $\mathbb {Z}^\mathrm {op}\times \mathbb {Z}^\mathrm {op}$ spanned by ${\{(m,n)\mid m+n\ge r\}}$. For a rigorous $\infty$-categorical definition, see [Reference LurieLur17, § 2.2.6].

By our compatibility assumption, it is easy to see that taking underlying objects is symmetric monoidal, so our notation above is compatible. It is also worth noting that taking associated graded objects is symmetric monoidal with respect to the tensor product

\begin{align*} (X\otimes Y)_r=\bigoplus_{m+n=r}X_m\otimes Y_n \end{align*}

for graded objects.

Definition 2.5 (Completion)

Suppose $\mathcal {C}$ admits countable limits. We say that a filtered object $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M$ of $\mathcal {C}$ is complete if

\begin{align*} \lim_{n\to+\infty}\operatorname{Fil}^nM=0. \end{align*}

We denote the full subcategory of complete filtered objects of $\mathcal {C}$ by $\widehat {\mathsf {Fil}}(\mathcal {C})$, and write $\widehat {\mathsf {DF}}(-)$ for $\widehat {\mathsf {Fil}}(\mathsf {D}(-))$ as above. The inclusion functor $\widehat {\mathsf {Fil}}(\mathcal {C})\to \mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})$ has an obvious left adjoint, given by

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M\mapsto\frac{\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M}{\lim_{n\to+\infty}\operatorname{Fil}^nM}, \end{align*}

called completion. Note that a filtered object is constant if and only if its completion is zero, and the completion functor is a localization with kernel the constant objects.

Remark 2.6 (Monoidality of completion)

Suppose $(\mathcal {C},\otimes )$ satisfies the assumptions of both Definitions 2.4 and 2.5. Obviously, constant objects form a tensor ideal under Day convolution; therefore, by [Reference LurieLur17, Proposition 2.2.1.9] there is a natural symmetric monoidal structure on $\widehat {\mathsf {Fil}}(\mathcal {C})$, where the completion functor is symmetric monoidal, and the inclusion functor is lax symmetric monoidal.

Definition 2.7 (Trivial filtration)

For $M\in \mathcal {C}$, we call the filtered object

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^nM=\begin{cases} M, & m\le0;\\ 0, & m>0; \end{cases} \end{align*}

$M$ with trivial filtration, and by abuse of notation we often denote it by $M$. This is natural in $M$, giving rise to a functor $\operatorname {triv}\colon \mathcal {C}\to \mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})$, which is easily seen to be the left adjoint of taking $\operatorname {Fil}^0$. When $\mathcal {C}$ satisfies the assumption of Definition 2.4, it is also easy to see that $\operatorname {triv}$ is symmetric monoidal.

Definition 2.8 (Translation)

For a filtered object $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M$, its translation by $n$ is defined as $\operatorname {Fil}^{\bullet +n}M$. Sometimes we also denote this translation functor by $-(n)$.

Definition 2.9 (Filtered $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebras)

Suppose $(\mathcal {C},\otimes )$ satisfies the assumption of Definition 2.4. Then a filtered $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebra in $\mathcal {C}$ is defined as an $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebra in $\mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})$ with respect to Day convolution. By the above, one can take underlying $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebras, associated graded $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebras, and completions of filtered $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebras, and make trivially filtered $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebras starting with $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebras in $\mathcal {C}$.

For a filtered $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebra $R$, we often call its modules in $\mathsf {Fil}(\mathcal {C})$ filtered $R$-modules, and denote the category of them by $\mathsf {DF}(R)$. This is compatible with the notation in [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19, § 5.1], as when $R$ is an $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-algebra in $\mathcal {C}$ that is trivially filtered, $\mathsf {DF}(R)$ is just $\mathsf {Fil}(\mathsf {D}(R))$, where $\mathsf {D}(R)$ denotes the category of $R$-modules in $\mathcal {C}$.

Definition 2.10 (Filtered rings)

Using [Reference RaksitRak20, Definition 4.2.22, Construction 4.3.4], we define the category of derived filtered rings to be $\mathsf {DAlg}(\mathsf {DF}(\mathbb {Z}))$, and that of animated filtered rings to be the full subcategory spanned by those derived filtered rings $R$ with $\operatorname {Fil}^nR$ connective for all $n$. By [Reference RaksitRak20, Remark 4.2.24], one can alternatively define the category of animated filtered rings to be the animation, namely $\mathsf {P}_\Sigma$, of the $1$-category of classical filtered rings of the form $\operatorname {LSym}(M)$, where $M$ runs through finite direct sums of translations of the trivially filtered $\mathbb {Z}$. Passing through the Rees algebra construction, one can also view an animated filtered ring as an animated graded algebra over $\mathbb {Z}[t]$ (cf. Definition 5.11 below).

Remark 2.11 By our convention, ‘filtered rings’ will mean animated filtered rings. However, this filtered animation is never really used in this section and only rarely used in § 5. Readers can safely replace filtered rings with filtered $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-rings in this section if they are willing to.

2.2 Generalities on filtered modules

In this subsection we discuss general properties of filtered $A$-modules that do not depend on the $\delta$-ring structure on $A$.

We view both $A$ and $A[1/I]$ as filtered rings with the $I$-adic filtrations, i.e.

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^mA=\begin{cases} I^m, & m\ge0;\\ A, & m<0; \end{cases}\quad \operatorname{Fil}^mA[1/I]=I^m. \end{align*}

Accordingly, $\mathsf {DF}(A)$ and $\mathsf {DF}(A[1/I])$ refer to the filtered derived categories with respect to the $I$-adic filtrations. Note that we are not breaking our convention that everything is $(p,I)$-complete; $A[1/I]$ is just a filtered $(p,I)$-complete $A$-algebra with underlying object $0$. We view $\bar {A}$ as with the trivial filtration, i.e.

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^m\bar{A}=\begin{cases} \bar{A}, & m\le0;\\ 0, & m>0; \end{cases} \end{align*}

then the reduction map $A\to \bar {A}$ is naturally a filtered map.

Proposition 2.12 Taking $\operatorname {Fil}^0$ gives an equivalence $\mathsf {DF}(A[1/I])\cong \mathsf {D}(A)$, whose inverse is $M\mapsto I^\bullet M$.

Proof. Obviously $M\mapsto I^\bullet M$ is right inverse to $\operatorname {Fil}^0(-)$. Conversely, for $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N\in \mathsf {DF}(A[1/I])$, from the filtered multiplication map $I^\bullet \otimes \operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N\to \operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N$ one gets maps $I^m\otimes \operatorname {Fil}^n N\to \operatorname {Fil}^{m+n}N$ for all $m,n\in \mathbb {Z}$. By their compatibility one can easily see that they are all isomorphisms, so $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N=I^\bullet \operatorname {Fil}^0N$.

Now we introduce two specializations of filtered $A$-modules, both of which take values in filtered $\bar {A}$-modules.

Definition 2.13 (Hodge–Tate specialization)

For $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$, the associated graded object $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet N$ is a graded module over $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet A=\bigoplus _{m\in \mathbb {N}}I^m/I^{m+1}$. Twist the $m$th grade by $(I/I^2)^{\otimes (-m)}$; the module $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet N\{-\bullet \}$ we get is a graded module over $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet A\{-\bullet \}=\bar {A}[u]$ where $u$ is in the 1st grade. Note that such a graded module corresponds to an increasingly filtered $\bar {A}$-module, since multiplying by $u$ gives us the maps. This increasingly filtered $\bar {A}$-module is called the Hodge–Tate specialization of $N$, denoted by $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet N^\mathrm {HT}\in \mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})$.

Definition 2.14 (de Rham specialization)

The de Rham specialization of $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$ is its base change along the filtered map $A\to \bar {A}$, denoted by $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \bar {N}\in \mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})$.

Remark 2.15 Since taking associated graded objects commutes with filtered base change, and the associated graded of the map $A\to \bar {A}$ is the map $\bigoplus _{m\in \mathbb {N}}I^m/I^{m+1}\to \bar {A}$ that kills all the $m>0$ summands, we can naturally identify the graded pieces of the Hodge–Tate specialization with those of the de Rham specialization up to twists by $I/I^2$. More specifically, for $N\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$, we have

\begin{align*} \operatorname{gr}_\bullet N^\mathrm{HT}\{\bullet\}\cong\operatorname{gr}^\bullet\bar{N}. \end{align*}

In Example 2.33 below, this corresponds to the fact that the Hodge–Tate filtration on $\overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{R/A}}$ has graded pieces $\Omega _{R/\bar {A}}^\bullet \{-\bullet \}$ while the de Rham filtration on $\overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{R/A}^{(1)}}$ has graded pieces $\Omega _{R/\bar {A}}^\bullet$.

Remark 2.16 (The underlying object of the Hodge–Tate specialization)

If we view a graded $\bar {A}[u]$-module $X_\bullet$ as an increasing filtration, then by definition its underlying object is the colimit of $X_n$ along multiplying $u$, which is the same as the $0$th grade of $X_\bullet [u^{-1}]$. Accordingly, the underlying object $N^\mathrm {HT}$ of $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet N^\mathrm {HT}$ is the same as the $0$th grade of the base change of $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet N$ from $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet A=\bigoplus _{m\in \mathbb {N}}I^m/I^{m+1}$ to $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet A[1/I]=\bigoplus _{m\in \mathbb {Z}}I^m/I^{m+1}$, which means that

\begin{align*} N^\mathrm{HT}=\operatorname{gr}^0(N[1/I])=\operatorname{Fil}^0(N[1/I])\otimes_A\bar{A}, \end{align*}

where $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N[1/I]$ denotes the filtered base change of $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N$ from $A$ to $A[1/I]$, and the last equality comes from Proposition 2.12.

Finally we give some dualizability criteria.

Proposition 2.17 Let $\mathcal {C}$ be a presentably symmetric monoidal category. Then:

  • if $1_\mathcal {C}$ is compact, then dualizable objects in $\mathcal {C}$ are compact;

  • if  $\mathcal {C}$ is compactly generated by its dualizable objects, then compact objects in $\mathcal {C}$ are dualizable.

Proof. If $1$ is compact and $X\in \mathcal {C}$ is dualizable with dual $X^\vee$, then since

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}(X,-)=\operatorname{Hom}(1,\operatorname{\underline{Hom}}(X,-))=\operatorname{Hom}(1,X^\vee\otimes-) \end{align*}

commutes with filtered colimits, $X$ is compact.

If $\mathcal {C}$ is stable, then finite colimits of dualizable objects are dualizable: for finite direct sums it is obvious, and for cofibers one easily verify that $\operatorname {cofib}(X\to Y)^\vee =\operatorname {fib}(Y^\vee \to X^\vee )$. In general, retracts of dualizable objects are dualizable. Thus, if $\mathcal {C}$ is compactly generated by its dualizable objects, then compact objects, as retracts of finite colimits of generators, are dualizable.

Corollary 2.18 Let $R$ be a filtered ring. Then in $\mathsf {DF}(R)$, dualizable objects coincide with compact objects. If, moreover, the filtration of $R$ is trivial, then they are exactly the complete filtered objects with only finitely many nonzero graded pieces that are all dualizable in $\mathsf {D}(R)$.

Proof. Note that:

  • $1_{\mathsf {DF}(R)}=R$ and $\operatorname {Hom}(R,-)=\operatorname {Fil}^0(-)$ commutes with colimits, so $1_{\mathsf {DF}(R)}$ is compact;

  • the translations $R(n)$ are all dualizable with $R(n)^\vee =R(-n)$, and form a family of compact generators of $\mathsf {DF}(R)$, since the functor $\mathsf {DF}(R)\to \mathsf {Sp}^\mathbb {Z}$, $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet N\mapsto (\operatorname {Fil}^nN)_{n\in \mathbb {Z}}$ is clearly conservative.

If the filtration of $R$ is trivial, then it is in particular complete, so every $R(n)$ is complete, with only one nonzero graded piece $\operatorname {gr}^{-n}R(n)=R$. Therefore, the compact objects in $\mathsf {DF}(R)$, as retracts of finite colimits of objects of the form $R(n)[d]$, are also complete, with only finitely many nonzero graded pieces that are all compact in $\mathsf {D}(R)$. Conversely, let $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M\in \mathsf {DF}(R)$ be complete with only finitely many nonzero graded pieces that are all compact in $\mathsf {D}(R)$. Then for $m\gg 0$ we have $\operatorname {Fil}^mM=0$ and $\operatorname {Fil}^{-m}M=M$. In addition, the terms $\operatorname {Fil}^mM$ are all compact in $\mathsf {D}(R)$, being a finite extension of compact objects. Now it is easy to write $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M$ as a finite extension of compact objects in $\mathsf {D}(R)$ with trivial filtration, which are clearly compact in $\mathsf {DF}(R)$.

Lemma 2.19 Let $\mathcal {C}$ and $\mathcal {D}$ be presentably symmetric monoidal categories and $F\colon \mathcal {C}\to \mathcal {D}$ be a conservative symmetric monoidal functor that preserves internal Homs. Then $c\in \mathcal {C}$ is dualizable if and only if $Fc\in \mathcal {D}$ is dualizable.

Proof. If $c\in \mathcal {C}$ is dualizable, clearly so is $Fc\in \mathcal {D}$ since $F$ is symmetric monoidal. Conversely if $Fc\in \mathcal {D}$ is dualizable, let $c^\vee =\operatorname {\underline {Hom}}_\mathcal {C}(c,1_\mathcal {C})$, then since $F$ is symmetric monoidal and preserves internal Homs, $F(c^\vee )=(Fc)^\vee$. To prove that $c\in \mathcal {C}$ is dualizable, it suffices to show that the natural transformation $c^\vee \otimes _\mathcal {C}-\to \operatorname {\underline {Hom}}_\mathcal {C}(c,-)$ is an isomorphism. This can be checked after applying $F$ by conservativity, whence it becomes obvious.

Remark 2.20 Lemma 2.19 applies when $A\in \mathsf {CAlg}(\mathcal {C})$ is dualizable in $\mathcal {C}$, $\mathcal {D}=\mathsf {Mod}_\mathcal {C}(A)$ is the module category and the base change functor $F=-\otimes _\mathcal {C} A$ is conservative, since

\begin{align*} \operatorname{\underline{Hom}}_\mathcal{D}(X\otimes_\mathcal{C} A,Y\otimes_\mathcal{C} A)=\operatorname{\underline{Hom}}_\mathcal{C}(X,Y\otimes_\mathcal{C} A)=\operatorname{\underline{Hom}}_\mathcal{C}(X,Y)\otimes_\mathcal{C} A \end{align*}

by dualizability.

Corollary 2.21 An object in $\mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})$ is dualizable if and only if it is complete and has only finitely many nonzero graded pieces that are all dualizable in $\mathsf {D}(\bar {A})$.

Proof. By Lemma 2.19, $M\in \mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})$ is dualizable if and only if $M/p\in \mathsf {DF}(\bar {A}/p)$ is. Now the corollary follows from Corollary 2.18.

Proposition 2.22 The functor $N\mapsto (\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet N^\mathrm {HT},\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \bar {N})$ from $\mathsf {DF}(A)$ to $\mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})\times \mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})$ is conservative.

Proof. Assume $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet N^\mathrm {HT}=\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \bar {N}=0$; we want to prove that $N=0$. This is easy: $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet N^\mathrm {HT}=0$ just means $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet N=0$ by definition, so the filtration is constant; then $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \bar {N}$ is also constant, and that it is zero implies that $N$ is zero by $I$-completeness.

Remark 2.23 The conservativity above has a geometric interpretation: view filtered $A$-modules as graded modules over the Rees algebra $\mathcal {R}=\bigoplus _{m\in \mathbb {Z}}I^mt^{-m}$ where $t$ is in the $(-1)$st grade. For simplicity assume $I=(d)$ is principal, so $\mathcal {R}=A[t,u]/(tu-d)$. Then the two specializations correspond to taking quotients by $t$ and $u$, so they are jointly conservative since $tu=d$ and everything is $d$-complete.

Proposition 2.24 An object $N\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$ is dualizable if and only if its two specializations $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet N^\mathrm {HT}$ and $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \bar {N}$ are both dualizable in $\mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})$, equivalently they are both complete and has only finitely many nonzero graded pieces that are all dualizable in $\mathsf {D}(\bar {A})$.

Proof. It suffices to prove that the functor $N\mapsto (\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet N^\mathrm {HT},\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \bar {N})$ satisfies the assumptions of Lemma 2.19. Note that the algebras $\bar {A}$ and $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet A$ in $\mathsf {DF}(A)$ are both dualizable, being cofibers of maps $I\to A$ and $A(1)\to A$. Hence, the proposition follows from Remark 2.20 and Proposition 2.22.

2.3 $F$-gauges over a prism

Definition 2.25 (Gauges and $F$-gauges)

A gauge over $(A,I)$ is a pair $(M,\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)})$ where $M\in \mathsf {D}(A)$ and $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$ with underlying object $M^{(1)}=\varphi _A^*M$. An $F$-gauge over $(A,I)$ is a triple $(M,\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)},F)$ where $(M,\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)})$ is a gauge over $(A,I)$ and $F\colon \operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}[1/I]\to I^\bullet M$ is an isomorphism in $\mathsf {DF}(A[1/I])$. As above, $-[1/I]$ denotes the base change functor from $\mathsf {DF}(A)$ to $\mathsf {DF}(A[1/I])$ and $I^\bullet M$ denotes the obvious filtered module of $A[1/I]$ with underlying object $M[1/I]$.

Denote the categories of gauges and $F$-gauges over $(A,I)$ by $\mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)$ and ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$, respectively. They are both presentably symmetric monoidal stable $\infty$-categories, since they are finite limits of such categories by definition. Clearly, the forgetful functor ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)\to \mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)$ is symmetric monoidal and preserves all colimits.

Remark 2.26 We often view $F$ as a morphism $F\colon \operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}\to I^\bullet M$ in $\mathsf {DF}(A)$ that exhibits $I^\bullet M\in \mathsf {DF}(A[1/I])$ as the base change of $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$ to $A[1/I]$. Thus, $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}$ and $F$ actually determine $M$, as the $\operatorname {Fil}^0$ of this base change.

Remark 2.27 (Changing prisms)

Let $(A,I)\to (B,J)$ be a morphism of prisms. Then $(M,\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)})\mapsto (M\otimes _AB,(\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)})\otimes _{A^{(1)}}B^{(1)})$ gives base change functors $\mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)\to \mathsf {Gauge}(B,J)$ and ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)\to {F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(B,J)$. We denote them by $-\otimes _AB$ and call their right adjoints forgetful functors. Note that these forgetful functors commute with the forgetful functor $\mathsf {D}(B)\to \mathsf {D}(A)$ in the first component but not in the second, since for $N\in \mathsf {D}(B)$, $\varphi _B^*N$ and $\varphi _A^*N$ are in general different.

Remark 2.28 (Descent)

Since each datum of a gauge or an $F$-gauge satisfies $(p,I)$-completely flat descent, so do gauges and $F$-gauges. In other words, $\mathsf {Gauge}$ and ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}$ are sheaves of $\infty$-categories on the absolute prismatic site.

Example 2.29 (Breuil–Kisin twists)

For $n\in \mathbb {Z}$, consider the Breuil–Kisin twist $A\{n\}$ defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Definition 2.5.2, Notation 2.5.4]. It is an invertible $A$-module with canonical isomorphism $A\{n\}^{(1)}\cong I^{-n}A\{n\}$. We view it as an $F$-gauge over $(A,I)$ by defining

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^mA\{n\}^{(1)}=\begin{cases} I^{m+n}A\{n\}^{(1)}, & m\ge-n;\\ A\{n\}^{(1)}, & m<-n; \end{cases} \end{align*}

and taking $F$ to be the canonical isomorphism. Note that $\operatorname {Fil}^mA\{n\}^{(1)}$ is chosen to correspond to $I^mA\{n\}$ under the canonical isomorphism for $m\ge -n$.

Obviously, $A=A\{0\}$ is the tensor unit of ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$, and $A\{n\}\otimes A\{n'\}=A\{n+n'\}$ for all $n,n'\in \mathbb {Z}$. By [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Remark 2.5.5], the Breuil–Kisin twists commute with base changes, i.e. $A\{n\}\otimes _AB=B\{n\}$ for every prism $(B,J)$ over $(A,I)$.

For a gauge or an $F$-gauge $M$, let $M\{n\}$ denote the tensor product $M\otimes A\{n\}$ in the respective category. Then it is easy to see that

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^m(M\{n\}^{(1)})=(\operatorname{Fil}^{m+n}M^{(1)})\{n\}, \end{align*}

where the $\{n\}$ outside the brackets means the Breuil–Kisin twist relative to the animated prism $(A^{(1)},IA^{(1)})$.

We discuss several specializations of $F$-gauges.

Definition 2.30 (Hodge–Tate specialization)

For $M\in \mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)$, its Hodge–Tate specialization is defined as the Hodge–Tate specialization of $M^{(1)}\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$ as in Definition 2.13. For $M\in {F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$, by Proposition 2.12 and Remark 2.16, the underlying object of its Hodge–Tate specialization is $\bar {M}=M\otimes _A\bar {A}$, so in this case we denote it by $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet \bar {M}$.

Definition 2.31 (De Rham specialization)

For $M\in \mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)$, its de Rham specialization is defined as the base change of $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$ to $\bar {A}$, denoted by $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \overline {M^{(1)}}$. It is also a functor $\mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)\to \mathsf {DF}(\bar {A})$.

Definition 2.32 (Étale specialization)

Here we suspend the convention that everything is $(p,I)$-complete. Suppose the prism $(A,I)$ is perfect with $R=A/p$, so $A=W(R)$ and $A[1/I]_p^\wedge =W(R[1/I])$. For $M\in {F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$, since $M^{(1)}$ is just $M$ with the $A$-module structure twisted by Frobenius, we can view the isomorphism $F\colon M^{(1)}[1/I]_p^\wedge \to M[1/I]_p^\wedge$ as a Frobenius-semilinear automorphism of $M[1/I]_p^\wedge$. Now view $M[1/I]_p^\wedge$ as a sheaf on $\operatorname {Spa}(R[1/I],R)_\mathrm {pro\acute {e}t}\cong \operatorname {Spd}(\bar {A}[1/p],\bar {A})_\mathrm {pro\acute {e}t}$, and form the equalizer of $\operatorname {id}$ and $F$. This defines a functor $M\mapsto (M[1/I]_p^\wedge )^{F=1}: {F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)\to \mathsf {D}_\mathrm {pro\acute {e}t}(\operatorname {Spd}(\bar {A}[1/p],\bar {A}),\mathbb {Z}_p)$, which we call the étale specialization.

Example 2.33 (Prismatic cohomology)

Let $X$ be a smooth formal scheme over $\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$. Then [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Theorems 1.8, 1.16] gives the prismatic cohomology $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)$ an $F$-gauge structure, whose Hodge–Tate specialization is the conjugate-filtered Hodge–Tate cohomology, whose de Rham specialization is the Hodge-filtered de Rham cohomology, and when $(A,I)$ is perfect whose étale specialization is the étale pushforward of $\mathbb {Z}_p$ along the diamond generic fiber of $X\to \operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$. This can be generalized to general stacks over $\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$ using [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, §§ 5.1 and 5.2].

Remark 2.34 (Relative gauges and $F$-gauges)

It is possible to define for every formal scheme $X$ over $\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$ the categories $\mathsf {Gauge}(X/A)$ and ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(X/A)$ that serve as coefficients for the prismatic cohomology of $X$ over $(A,I)$: first for $X=\operatorname {Spf}(R)$ with $R$ a large quasisyntomic $\bar {A}$-algebra as in [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Definition 15.1], define

\begin{align*} \mathsf{Gauge}(X/A)=\{(M,\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)})\mid M\in\mathsf{D}({{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_{R/A}),\,\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}\in\mathsf{DF}(\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet{{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_{R/A}^{(1)})\}, \end{align*}
\begin{align*} {F\text{-}\mathsf{Gauge}}(X/A)&=\Big\{(M,\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)},F)\mid(M,\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)})\in\mathsf{Gauge}(X/A),\\ &\qquad F\colon\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}\otimes_{{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}_{R/A}^{(1)},\varphi}{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}_{R/A}[1/I]\cong M[1/I]\Big\}; \end{align*}

next for smooth affine $X$ use quasisyntomic descent from the large algebras; then for general affine $X$ use left Kan extension from the smooth ones; finally, for general $X$ use descent again.

The category ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(X/A)$ should have specialization to relative prismatic crystals (i.e. quasicoherent $\mathcal {O}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}$-modules on the site $(X/A)_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}$), Hodge–Tate specialization to Higgs modules, de Rham specialization to $\mathcal {D}$-modules, and when $(A,I)$ is perfect, étale specialization to étale sheaves on the generic fiber. In addition, the Poincaré duality should hold for proper smooth $X$ with dualizable coefficients in these categories. However, we will not explore these in this paper.

The following proposition computes global sections of gauges and $F$-gauges, with which we can reinterpret the relative syntomic cohomology $\mathbb {Z}_p(n)(X/A)$ in [Reference Antieau, Krause and NikolausAKN22] as $\operatorname {Hom}_{{F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)}(A,\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)\{n\})$, cf. Examples 2.29 and 2.33.

Proposition 2.35 If $M$ is a gauge, then

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathsf{Gauge}(A,I)}(A,M)=M\times_{M^{(1)}}\operatorname{Fil}^0M^{(1)}, \end{align*}

where the map $M\to M^{(1)}=M\otimes _{A,\varphi }A$ is $m\mapsto m\otimes 1$. If $M$ is an $F$-gauge, then

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}_{{F\text{-}\mathsf{Gauge}}(A,I)}(A,M)=\operatorname{eq}(\operatorname{Fil}^0M^{(1)}\rightrightarrows M^{(1)}), \end{align*}

where the two maps are the natural map and the composition

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^0M^{(1)}\to\operatorname{Fil}^0(M^{(1)}[1/I])=M\to M^{(1)}. \end{align*}

Proof. The first sentence is clear from the definition of $\mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)$, and the second sentence is clear from Remark 2.26.

We finally offer a dualizability criterion using Proposition 2.24.

Proposition 2.36 (Dualizability of gauges)

Let $M$ be a gauge or an $F$-gauge. Then $M$ is dualizable if and only if it satisfies the following conditions:

  1. (i) $M$ is dualizable in $\mathsf {D}(A)$;

  2. (ii) the Hodge–Tate specialization of $M$ is dualizable, i.e. is complete with only finitely many graded pieces that are perfect complexes;

  3. (iii) the de Rham specialization of $M$ is dualizable, i.e. is complete with only finitely many graded pieces that are perfect complexes.

The perfectnesses of the graded pieces in conditions (ii) and (iii) are equivalent, and in the $F$-gauge case, condition (ii) implies condition (i).

Proof. Recall that the symmetric monoidal category of gauges is defined as the pullback

where the right vertical arrow is taking underlying objects and the lower horizontal arrow is base change along $\varphi$. Therefore, $M\in \mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)$ is dualizable if and only if its two images in $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}\in \mathsf {DF}(A)$ and $M\in \mathsf {D}(A)$ are dualizable. Now the proposition follows from Proposition 2.24. The two perfectnesses are equivalent because of Remark 2.15.

Recall that by Proposition 2.12, the symmetric monoidal category of $F$-gauges is defined as the equalizer

\begin{align*} {F\text{-}\mathsf{Gauge}}(A,I)\to\mathsf{Gauge}(A,I)\rightrightarrows\mathsf{D}(A) \end{align*}

where the two arrows send a gauge $(M,\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)})\in \mathsf {Gauge}(A,I)$ to $M\in \mathsf {D}(A)$ and $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet M^{(1)}[1/I]\in \mathsf {DF}(A[1/I])\cong \mathsf {D}(A)$, respectively. Therefore, an $F$-gauge $M$ is dualizable if and only if it is dualizable as a gauge. Since $\bar {M}\in \mathsf {D}(\bar {A})$ is the underlying object of the Hodge–Tate specialization, the dualizability of the Hodge–Tate specialization implies that of $\bar {M}$, which, in turn, implies that of $M$ by Lemma 2.19.

Corollary 2.37 Let $X$ be a proper smooth formal algebraic space over $\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$. Then $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)\in {F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$ is dualizable.

Proof. By Proposition 2.36 we only need to show that the Hodge–Tate specialization and the de Rham specialization of $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)$ are both dualizable. This is clear: both are complete with the graded pieces zero outside $[0,\dim (X)]$; the nonzero graded pieces are $\mathrm {R}\Gamma (X,\Omega ^\star _{X/\bar {A}}[-\star ])$, which is dualizable by [Aut, 0A1P].

3. Weighted homotopy invariance of cohomologies

One remarkable property that the $\ell$-adic étale cohomology enjoys is the $\mathbb {A}^1$-invariance, namely $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\mathbb {A}^1_X,\mathbb {Z}_\ell )=\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(X,\mathbb {Z}_\ell )$ for $\ell$ invertible on $X$. Not only does this fact help us compute the étale cohomology for many schemes, it has also been a crucial input to the norm residue isomorphism theorem of Suslin and Voevodsky; see, for example, [Reference Suslin and VoevodskySV00].

However, various cohomologies studied in $p$-adic Hodge theory, including Hodge, de Rham, prismatic, and syntomic, usually do not satisfy the $\mathbb {A}^1$-invariance. Fortunately, as [Reference ClausenCla21] suggests, they actually enjoy a weaker property, the weighted $\!\mathbb {A}^1$-invariance, namely $\mathcal {F}(X\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m)=\mathcal {F}(X\times \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m)$ for $\mathcal {F}$ being some of the above cohomologies. In this section, we will formulate this invariance property in general, and prove it for some cohomologies, in order for later sections to exploit.

3.1 Big étale sheaves

We first study the notion of big étale sheaves.

Definition 3.1 (Big étale sheaves)

Let $\mathcal {C}$ be a presentable $\infty$-category. A big étale sheaf with values in $\mathcal {C}$ is an accessible functor $\mathcal {F}\colon \mathsf {Ring}\to \mathcal {C}$ that satisfies étale descent, i.e. a $\mathcal {C}$-object of the big étale topos. A stack in this paper is a big étale sheaf of animas. For a stack $S$, a big étale sheaf over $S$ with values in $\mathcal {C}$ is an accessible functor $\mathcal {F}\colon \mathsf {Ring}_{/S}\to \mathcal {C}$ that satisfies étale descent, i.e. a $\mathcal {C}$-object of the slice topos over $S$. A big étale sheaf of animas over $S$ is the same as a stack with a map to $S$, and thus is called a stack over $\!S$.

Remark 3.2 (Small étale sheaves)

Let $A$ be a ring and let $X$ be a sheaf of animas on the small étale site $A_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}$, i.e. the étale site of étale $A$-algebras. Then one can view it as a stack over $A$ by pulling back along the topos map $(\mathsf {Ring}_{/A})_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}\to A_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}$. Such a stack is called an étale stack over $A$. We call a map of stacks étale if it is étale after every pullback to a representable.

Example 3.3 All geometric objects that appear in this paper are stacks, including the following.

  • Rings, i.e. affine schemes. For a ring $A$, the functor $R\mapsto \operatorname {Hom}(A,R)$ is a stack, denoted $\operatorname {Spec}(A)$. We often identify $A$ and $\operatorname {Spec}(A)$.

  • Deligne–Mumford stacks. They are just stacks that are affine schemes étale locally. Namely, a Deligne–Mumford stack is a stack $X$ that is covered by a family of étale maps from affine schemes, cf. [Reference LurieLur18, § 1.6.4].

  • Algebraic spaces. They are just those Deligne–Mumford stacks that take classical rings to sets, cf. [Reference LurieLur18, Definition 1.6.8.1].

  • Affine formal schemes. For a ring $A$ and a finitely generated ideal $I\subseteq \pi _0A$, the functor

    \begin{align*} R\mapsto\{f\in\operatorname{Hom}(A,R)\mid \pi_0(f)(I) \text{ is nilpotent}\} \end{align*}
    is a stack, denoted $\operatorname {Spf}(A,I)$, or $\operatorname {Spf}(A)$ if not confusing. We often identify $A$ and $\operatorname {Spf}(A)$ whenever $A$ is complete, so $\mathsf {D}(A)$ will mean the category of derived $I$-complete complexes, and in particular this applies to $\mathsf {D}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$.
  • Formal Deligne–Mumford stacks. They are just stacks that are affine formal schemes étale locally, in the same way as above.

  • Formal algebraic spaces. They are just formal Deligne–Mumford stacks that take classical rings to sets.

  • Quotient stacks. Let $X$ be a stack and $G$ be a group scheme smooth over $\mathbb {Z}$ acting on $X$. Then

    \begin{align*} X/G=(R\mapsto\{(E,f)\mid E\to\operatorname{Spec}(R) \text{ is a } G\text{-torsor,}\ f\colon E\to X \text{ is } G\text{-equivariant}\}) \end{align*}
    is a stack that receives an effective epimorphism from $X$, since smooth maps have sections étale locally. Alternatively, $X/G=\operatorname{colim}_{n\in \Delta ^\mathrm {op}}(X\times G^n)$, where the simplicial object is defined by the group action.

Remark 3.4 (Taking values in stacks)

Let $\mathcal {C}$ be a presentable category and let $S$ be a stack. Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a big étale sheaf over $S$ and let $X$ be a stack over $S$. Viewing $X$ as a big étale sheaf over $S$ with values in $\mathsf {Ani}$, since $\mathcal {C}$ is naturally powered over $\mathsf {Ani}$, the anima $\operatorname {Hom}_S(X,\mathcal {F})$ is naturally enhanced to an object $\mathcal {F}(X)\in \mathcal {C}$, which we call the value of $\mathcal {F}$ on $X$. Equivalently,

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}(X)=\lim_{\operatorname{Spec}(R)\to X}\mathcal{F}(R). \end{align*}

Note that $\mathcal {F}(X)$ takes colimits in $X$ to limits, since it is $\operatorname {Hom}$ out of it.

The following notion is central in this section.

Definition 3.5 (Weighted homotopy invariance)

We say that a big étale sheaf $\mathcal {F}$ over a stack $S$ satisfies strong weighted homotopy invariance if, for every $\mathbb {N}$-graded ring $R=\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {N}}R_n$ over $S$, viewed as acted by $\mathbb {G}_m$ naturally by grading,

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)=\mathcal{F}(\operatorname{Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb{G}_m). \end{align*}

In this case, we have, in particular, $\mathcal {F}(V/\mathbb {G}_m)=\mathcal {F}(X/\mathbb {G}_m)$ for any stack $X$ and vector bundle $V$ over it, where $\mathbb {G}_m$ acts on $X$ trivially and acts on $V$ by scaling. This follows from take the limit of the definition over all $\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)\to X$. Therefore, we say that $\mathcal {F}$ satisfies smooth weighted homotopy invariance if, for every vector bundle $V\to X$ with $X$ smooth over $S$, we have $\mathcal {F}(V/\mathbb {G}_m)=\mathcal {F}(X/\mathbb {G}_m)$.

Remark 3.6 (Quasicoherent sheaves on stacks)

Let $\mathsf {Pr}_\mathrm {st}^\mathrm {L}$ denote the category of presentable stable categories with morphisms the left adjoints. Then $R\mapsto \mathsf {D}(R)$ satisfies étale descent, and is nearly a big étale sheaf except that $\mathsf {Pr}_\mathrm {st}^\mathrm {L}$ is itself not presentable. Yet $\mathsf {Pr}_\mathrm {st}^\mathrm {L}$ admits arbitrary small limits, so Remark 3.4 gives rise to a presentable stable category $\mathsf {D}(X)$ for any stack $X$, called the derived category of $\!X$, and its object is called a quasicoherent sheaf on $X$. By construction, for a stack map $f\colon X\to S$, we have the adjoint pair $(f^*,f_*)\colon \mathsf {D}(S)\rightleftarrows \mathsf {D}(X)$. We sometimes write $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{X/S}$ instead of $f_*$.

Remark 3.7 (Small étale $\mathbb {Z}_p$-sheaves on stacks)

Similarly, $R\mapsto \mathsf {D}_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\operatorname {Spec}(R),\mathbb {Z}_p)$ satisfies étale descent, so Remark 3.4 gives rise to a presentable stable category $\mathsf {D}_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(X,\mathbb {Z}_p)$ for any stack $X$, whose object is called an étale $\mathbb {Z}_p$-sheaf on $\!X$. Here we also have an adjoint pair $(f^*,f_*)\colon \mathsf {D}_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(S,\mathbb {Z}_p)\rightleftarrows \mathsf {D}_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(X,\mathbb {Z}_p)$ for every stack map $X\to S$. Alternatively, $\mathsf {D}_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(-,\mathbb {Z}_p)$ is the big étale sheafification of the constant functor $\mathsf {Ring}\to \mathsf {Pr}_\mathrm {st}^\mathrm {L}$ with value $\mathsf {D}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$.

Example 3.8 (Étale cohomology)

Let $S$ be a stack and let $\mathcal {F}$ be an étale $\mathbb {Z}_p$-sheaf on $S$. Then the étale cohomology $X\mapsto \mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(X,f^*\mathcal {F})$ is a big étale sheaf over $S$ with values in $\mathsf {D}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$, where $f\colon X\to S$ is the structure map. By abuse of notation, we denote this big étale sheaf still by $\mathcal {F}$. Some important special cases of this construction are:

  1. (i) $S=\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z}[1/p])$ and $\mathcal {F}=\mathbb {Z}_p(n)$ is the Tate twist, where $n\in \mathbb {Z}$;

  2. (ii) $S=\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z})$ and $\mathcal {F}=j_!\mathbb {Z}_p(n)$ where $j\colon \operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z}[1/p])\to \operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z})$.

Example 3.9 (Étale cohomology of the adic generic fiber)

Let $S$ be a stack over $\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z}[t])$ and let $\mathcal {F}$ be an étale $\mathbb {Z}_p$-sheaf on $S$. Then the étale cohomology of the adic generic fiber $R\mapsto \mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\hat {R}_t[1/t],f^*\mathcal {F})$ is a big étale sheaf over $S$ with values in $\mathsf {D}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$, where $\hat {R}_t$ is the $t$-completion of $R$ and $f\colon \operatorname {Spec}(\hat {R}_t[1/t])\to S$ is the obvious map. In fact, by [Reference Bhatt and MathewBM21, Corollary 6.17], it is even an $\mathrm {arc}_t$ sheaf. The most important special case is $S=\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z})$ with structure map $t\mapsto p$.

Example 3.10 (Hodge cohomology)

Let $S$ be a stack. The Hodge cohomology $X\mapsto \mathrm {R}\Gamma _{X/S}(\mathrm {L}\Omega _{X/S}^\star )[-\star ]$ is a big étale sheaf over $S$ with values in $\mathsf {Gr}(S)$. We denote it by $\mathrm {L}\Omega _{-/S}^\star [-\star ]$. When $S=\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z})$ we often omit the ‘$/S$’.

Example 3.11 (De Rham cohomology)

Let $S$ be a stack. The de Rham cohomology $X\mapsto \operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \mathrm {dR}_{X/S}$ is a big étale sheaf over $S$ with values in $\mathsf {DF}(S)$. Note that its associated graded object is the Hodge cohomology.

Example 3.12 (Relative prismatic cohomology)

Let $(A,I)$ be a prism and let $\bar {A}=A/I$. The relative prismatic cohomology $R\mapsto { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{R/A}$ is a big étale sheaf over $\bar {A}$ with values in ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$. Its Hodge–Tate specialization $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet \overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}}_{-/A}$ (Definition 2.30) is called the relative Hodge–Tate cohomology, and its de Rham specialization (Definition 2.31) is the de Rham cohomology over $\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$.

Example 3.13 (Absolute prismatic cohomology)

Let $\mathrm {WCart}$ and $\mathrm {WCart}^\mathrm {HT}$ be the Cartier–Witt stack and its Hodge–Tate divisor, as in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, §§ 3.3 and 3.4]. The prismatic cohomology sheaf $\mathcal {H}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}$ defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Construction 4.4.1] is a big étale sheaf with values in $\mathsf {D}(\mathrm {WCart})$, and the (twisted and Nygaard filtered) absolute prismatic cohomology is the sheaf ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{n\}=\mathrm {R}\Gamma (\mathrm {WCart},\mathcal {H}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}\{n\})\in \mathsf {DF}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$ defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Construction 4.4.10] with the Nygaard filtration $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{n\}$ as in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Construction 5.5.3], for $n\in \mathbb {Z}$. The (conjugate filtered) Hodge–Tate cohomology sheaf $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet \mathcal {H}_{\overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}}}$ defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Construction 4.5.1] is a big étale sheaf with values in $\mathsf {DF}(\mathrm {WCart}^\mathrm {HT})$, and similarly the (twisted and conjugate filtered) absolute Hodge–Tate cohomology is the sheaf $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet \overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}}_-\{n\}=\mathrm {R}\Gamma (\mathrm {WCart}^\mathrm {HT},\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet \mathcal {H}_{\overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}}}\{n\})\in \mathsf {DF}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$, for $n\in \mathbb {Z}$.

Example 3.14 (Diffracted Hodge cohomology)

The diffracted Hodge cohomology $\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet \Omega ^{\not {D}}_-$, defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, § 4.9], is a big étale sheaf with values in $\mathsf {DF}(\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m^\sharp )$. Rationally, it is the Hodge cohomology with the filtration naïvely defined by the grading, under the identifications $\mathbb {G}^\sharp _{m,\mathbb {Q}}=\mathbb {G}_{m,\mathbb {Q}}$ and $\mathsf {D}(\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_{m,\mathbb {Q}})=\mathsf {Gr}(\mathbb {Q})$, while after $p$-completion it is the Hodge–Tate cohomology sheaf, under the identification $\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}^\sharp _{m,\mathbb {Z}_p}=\mathrm {WCart}^\mathrm {HT}$ (see [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Theorem 3.4.13]). Its associated graded object is the Hodge cohomology, where the $\mathbb {G}_m^\sharp$-action on the $n$th grade comes from the $\mathbb {G}_m$-action of weight $-n$.

Example 3.15 (Syntomic cohomology)

The syntomic cohomology $\mathbb {Z}_p(\star )$, defined in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, § 8.4], is a big étale sheaf with values in $\mathsf {Gr}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$. By [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Construction 7.4.1], for $n\in \mathbb {Z}$ and $X$ over $\operatorname {Spf}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$, $\mathbb {Z}_p(n)(X)$ is the equalizer of the maps $\varphi \{n\}$ and $\iota$ from $\operatorname {Fil}^n{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_X\{n\}$ to ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_X\{n\}$, while by [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Remark 8.4.4], for a stack $X$ with $p$-completion $\hat {X}$, there is a fiber sequence

\begin{align*} j_!\mathbb{Z}_p(n)(X)\to\mathbb{Z}_p(n)(X)\to\mathbb{Z}_p(n)(\hat{X}), \end{align*}

where the first term is as in Example 3.8.

Remark 3.16 As [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a] has constructed, all the examples above except Example 3.8(ii) have symmetric algebra structures in their respective categories, i.e. they actually have values in $\mathsf {CAlg}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$, $\mathsf {CAlg}\mathsf {DF}(\mathbb {Z}_p)$, and so on. We have omitted this clumsy ‘$\mathsf {CAlg}$’ notation in above.

Remark 3.17 Almost every cohomology theory that we encounter is left Kan extended from its restriction to smooth $\mathbb {Z}$-algebras, at least when formulated properly. See [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Propositions 4.5.8, 4.5.10, 4.9.6, and 8.4.10 and Remark 5.5.10]. Therefore, our generality of allowing arbitrary animated rings to be ‘test objects’ of stacks may be redundant; in most cases smooth $\mathbb {Z}$-algebras suffice. However, in order not to introduce more complication, we refrain from restricting test objects.

3.2 Comparing cohomology

This subsection aims to abstract the arguments of [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Proposition 9.2.9] and [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, § 9.4]. We first generalize the notion of quasisyntomic rings in [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19, § 4.2] to animated rings. Before that let us recall the notion of $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude. Note that unlike [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19, § 4.1], we use the homological indexing here.

Definition 3.18 ($\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude)

Let $A$ be a ring and let $M\in \mathsf {D}(A)$. For $a,b\in \mathbb {Z}$, we say that the ( $\!p$-complete) $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude of $M$ is in $[a,b]$ if, for every classical $A$-module $N$ (with $pN=0$), $M\otimes _AN$ has nonzero homotopy groups only in degree $[a,b]$. Similarly we have the notion of ($p$-complete) $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude in $\ge a$ or $\le b$. If an $A$-module $M$ has ($p$-complete) $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude concentrated at $0$, we say that it is ( $\!p$-completely) flat.

Obviously, ($p$-complete) $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude is preserved by arbitrary base change.

Proposition 3.19 Let $n\in \mathbb {N}$ and let $A$ be a ring whose homotopy groups of degrees $>n$ are zero. Let $a,b\in \mathbb {Z}$ and let $M\in \mathsf {D}(A)$ have $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude in $[a,b]$ (respectively, $\ge a$, $\le b$). Then $M$ has nonzero homotopy groups only in degree $[a,b+n]$ (respectively, $\ge a$, $\le b+n$).

Proof. This is simply because $A$ itself is an iterated extension of $(\pi _iA)[i]$ for $i=0,1,\ldots,n$, and each $\pi _iA$ is a classical $A$-module.

The following lemmas discuss commutation of cosimplicial totalizations and filtered colimits, under some coconnectivity conditions. Let $I$ be a filtered index category and $\Delta$ be the opposite category of ordered nonempty finite sets, which is also called the category of standard simplices.

Lemma 3.20 Let $M$ be a diagram of spectra indexed by $\Delta \times I$. Suppose $\tau _{>0}M$ is ind-zero as a diagram $I\to \mathsf {Fun}(\Delta,\mathsf {Sp})$, i.e. for every $i\in I$, there is a map $i\to j$ in $I$ such that the map $\tau _{>0}M_i\to \tau _{>0}M_j$ is zero in $\mathsf {Fun}(\Delta,\mathsf {Sp})$. Then

\begin{align*} \mathop{\operatorname{colim}}\limits_I\lim_{\Delta}M=\lim_{\Delta}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}\limits_IM \end{align*}

and is coconnective.

Proof. There is an obvious map from the left-hand side to the right-hand side. The fiber sequence $\tau _{>0}M\to M\to \tau _{\le 0}M$ of diagrams induces fiber sequences for both sides. The assumption implies that

\begin{align*} \mathop{\operatorname{colim}}\limits_I\lim_{\Delta}\tau_{>0}M=\lim_{\Delta}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}\limits_I\tau_{>0}M=0. \end{align*}

Therefore, one can assume that $M=\tau _{\le 0}M$ is coconnective. For $n\in \mathbb {N}$, let $M_{\le n}$ be the restriction of $M$ to $\Delta _{\le n}\times I$, where $\Delta _{\le n}$ is the full subcategory of $\Delta$ generated by the simplices of dimension $\le n$. Then for every $n\in \mathbb {N}$, we have the following.

  • For every $i\in I$ we have

    \begin{align*} \operatorname{fib}\Big(\lim_{\Delta}M_i\to\lim_{\Delta_{\le n}}M_{\le n,i}\Big)\in\mathsf{Sp}_{\le-n}; \end{align*}
    since filtered colimits respect coconnectivity, we can take $\operatorname{colim}_I$ and get
    \begin{align*} \operatorname{fib}\Big(\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_I\lim_{\Delta}M\to \mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_I\lim_{\Delta_{\le n}}M_{\le n}\Big)\in\mathsf{Sp}_{<-n}. \end{align*}
  • In addition, by the fact that filtered colimits respect coconnectivity,

    \begin{align*} \operatorname{fib}\Big(\lim_{\Delta}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_IM\to\lim_{\Delta_{\le n}}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_IM_{\le n}\Big)\in\mathsf{Sp}_{<-n}. \end{align*}
  • Since $\Delta _{\le n}$ is finite and in a stable $\infty$-category finite limits are just shifts of finite colimits,

    \begin{align*} \mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_I\lim_{\Delta_{\le n}}M_{\le n}=\lim_{\Delta_{\le n}}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_IM_{\le n}. \end{align*}

Combining, we get

\begin{align*} \operatorname{fib}\Big(\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_I\lim_{\Delta}M\to\lim_{\Delta}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_IM\Big)\in\mathsf{Sp}_{\le-n}, \end{align*}

but the fiber is independent of $n$, so it is zero, and the lemma follows.

Lemma 3.21 Let $A$ be a homotopically bounded ring, i.e. $\pi _nA=0$ for $n\gg 0$. Let $M$ be a diagram of objects in $\mathsf {D}(A)$ with $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude $\le 0$, indexed by $\Delta \times I$. Then

\begin{align*} \mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_I\lim_{\Delta}M=\lim_{\Delta}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_IM. \end{align*}

Proof. Combine Proposition 3.19 and (some shift of) Lemma 3.20.

The terms below are taken from [Reference Hahn, Raksit and WilsonHRW22, § 4.1]. Their apparent incompatibility originates from [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19, Definition 4.10].

Definition 3.22 Let $A\to R$ be a ring map. We say that it is ( $\kern -0.009em p$-)quasi-lci if $\mathrm {L}_{R/A}\in \mathsf {D}(R)$ has ($p$-complete) $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude $\le 1$. If it is moreover ($p$-completely) flat, we say that it is ( $p$-)quasisyntomic. A ( $\kern -0.009em p$-)quasisyntomic ring means a ring that is ($\kern -0.009em p$-)quasi-lci over $\mathbb {Z}$.

If $A\to R$ is a ($p$-)quasi-lci ring map, since $\mathrm {L}_{R/A}$ is connective, $\mathrm {L}_{R/A}$ actually has ($p$-complete) $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude in $[0,1]$. Therefore, its wedge product $\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_{R/A}$ has ($p$-complete) $\operatorname {Tor}$ amplitude in $[0,n]$, for all $n\in \mathbb {N}$.

Now we begin to compare the cohomology of different stacks. In what follows, let $(X_i)_{i\in I}$ be a finite diagram of stacks, and let $X$ be a stack receiving compatible maps from them. Rigorously speaking, the data should be a diagram $(X_i)_{i\in I\star \Delta ^0}$, where $X=X_{\Delta ^0}$. Then for any big étale sheaf $\mathcal {F}$ with values in any presentable category $\mathcal {C}$, we have a natural map

(4)\begin{equation} \mathcal{F}(X)\to\lim_{i\in I}\mathcal{F}(X_i). \end{equation}

The following lemmas discuss conditions under which the map is an isomorphism.

Lemma 3.23 If the map (4) is an isomorphism for $\mathcal {F}=\mathrm {L}\Omega ^\star$, then so is it for $\mathcal {F}(R)=\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {syn}(\operatorname {Spf}(\hat {R}),\mathbb {Z}_p(\star ))$. If it is moreover an isomorphism either for $\mathcal {F}=j_!\mathbb {Z}_p(\star )$ or for $\mathcal {F}$ being both $R\mapsto \mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(R[1/p],\mathbb {Z}_p(\star ))$ and $R\mapsto \mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\hat {R}[1/p],\mathbb {Z}_p(\star ))$, then it is also an isomorphism for $\mathcal {F}=\mathbb {Z}_p(\star )$.

Proof. We prove the lemma in steps.

  • For $\mathcal {F}=\operatorname {Fil}_\bullet \Omega ^{\not {D}}_-$, (4) is an isomorphism. This is because $\operatorname {Fil}_{<0}\Omega ^{\not {D}}_-=0$ and $\operatorname {gr}_n\Omega ^{\not {D}}_-=\mathrm {L}\Omega _-^n[-n]$, by [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Remark 4.9.3].

  • For $\mathcal {F}=\operatorname {gr}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{\star \}$, (4) is an isomorphism. This is due to the fiber sequence

    \begin{align*} \operatorname{gr}^m{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}_R\{n\}\to\operatorname{Fil}_m\widehat{\Omega^{\not{D}}_R}\to\operatorname{Fil}_{m-1}\widehat{\Omega^{\not{D}}_R} \end{align*}
    in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Remark 5.5.8]. Here the hat denotes $p$-completion.
  • For $\mathcal {F}=\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \hat {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}}_-\{\star \}$, where the hat denotes Nygaard completion, (4) is an isomorphism. This follows from forming finite extensions of $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{\star \}$ and then taking limits.

  • Finally, the lemma follows from [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Constructions 7.4.1 and 8.4.1, Proposition 7.4.6, Remark 8.4.4].

Lemma 3.24 Assume each of the $X_i$ and $X$ is a simplicial colimit of the form

with the face maps all ($p$-completely) flat and the $R_m$ all ($p$-)quasisyntomic and ($p$-completely) homotopically bounded. Then if the map (4) is an isomorphism for $\mathcal {F}=\mathrm {L}\Omega ^\star$, so is it for $\mathcal {F}$ being (the $p$-completions of) $\Omega ^{\not {D}}_-$, $\mathcal {H}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}$, and $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{\star \}$.

Proof. We first show that, for any stack $X=\operatorname{colim}_{m\in \Delta ^\mathrm {op}}\operatorname {Spec}(R_m)$ as assumed, we have $\Omega ^{\not {D}}_X=\operatorname{colim}_n\operatorname {Fil}_n\Omega ^{\not {D}}_X$ ($p$-completely). For this, take $N\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $\pi _{>N}R_0=0$ ($p$-completely). Then by flatness, $\pi _{>N}R_n=0$ ($p$-completely) for every $n\in \mathbb {N}$. By Proposition 3.19 one can see that $\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_{R_m}[-n]\in \mathsf {Sp}_{\le N}$ ($p$-completely), and thus so is $\operatorname {Fil}_n\Omega ^{\not {D}}_{R_m}$. Now by Remark 3.4 and Lemma 3.20, we have ($p$-completely)

\begin{align*} \Omega^{\not{D}}_X&=\lim_{m\in\Delta}\Omega^{\not{D}}_{R_m}=\lim_{m\in\Delta}\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_n\operatorname{Fil}_n\Omega^{\not{D}}_{R_m}\\ &=\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_n\lim_{m\in\Delta}\operatorname{Fil}_n\Omega^{\not{D}}_{R_m}=\mathop{\operatorname{colim}}_n\operatorname{Fil}_n\Omega^{\not{D}}_X. \end{align*}

With this in hand, we now prove the lemma.

  • $\Omega^{\not{D}}_-$ This follows from the previous paragraph and the proof of Lemma 3.23.

  • $\mathcal{H}_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}$ This is because $\mathcal {H}_{\overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}}}$ is the $p$-completion of $\Omega ^{\not {D}}_-$ (cf. Example 3.14), and $\mathrm {WCart}$ is complete along $\mathrm {WCart}^\mathrm {HT}$.

  • $\operatorname{Fil}^\bullet{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}_-\{\star\}$ For ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{\star \}$ this follows by twisting $\mathcal {H}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}$ by $\mathcal {O}_\mathrm {WCart}\{\star \}$ and taking global sections. For $\operatorname {gr}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{\star \}$ this follows from the proof of Lemma 3.23. Combine them and get what we want.

Remark 3.25 The proof of Lemma 3.24 shows that, for $X=\operatorname{colim}_{m\in \Delta ^\mathrm {op}}\operatorname {Spec}(R_m)$ as assumed and $N\in \mathbb {N}$ with $\pi _{>N}R_0=0$ ($p$-completely), the spectra $\Omega ^{\not {D}}_X$, $\mathcal {H}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X)$, $\operatorname {Fil}^i{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_X\{n\}$, and $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {syn}(X,\mathbb {Z}_p(n))$ are in $\mathsf {Sp}_{\le N}$ ($p$-completely) for all $i,n\in \mathbb {Z}$, since the étale cohomology is always coconnective.

Remark 3.26 The proof of Lemma 3.24 also shows that (the $p$-completions of) $\Omega ^{\not {D}}_-$, $\mathcal {H}_{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}$, and $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-\{\star \}$ satisfy descent along a ($p$-completely) quasisyntomic map between ($p$-)quasisyntomic and ($p$-completely) homotopically bounded rings.

3.3 Cohomologies of graded rings

In this subsection, we finally establish the strong weighted homotopy invariance of the syntomic cohomology.

First we discuss the Hodge cohomology. The first part of the following definition is taken from [Reference ClausenCla21, Lecture 13]; beware that it is expected to be somewhat reasonable only when $Z$ is an Artin stack.

Definition 3.27 (Cotangent complex)

For a stack $Z$ over a ring $A$, let

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}_{Z/A}=\lim_{g\colon\operatorname{Spec}(R)\to Z}g_*\mathrm{L}_{R/A}\in\mathsf{D}(Z), \end{align*}

where $g_*$ denotes the quasicoherent pushforward as in Remark 3.6. We often write $\mathrm {L}_Z$ for $\mathrm {L}_{Z/\mathbb {Z}}$. For a map of stacks $X\to Y$, let

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}_{X/Y}=\lim_{f\colon\operatorname{Spec}(R)\to Y}(f_X)_*\mathrm{L}_{(X\times_Y\operatorname{Spec}(R))/R}\in\mathsf{D}(X), \end{align*}

where $f_X$ is the base change of $f$ along $X\to Y$.

Remark 3.28 Note that the assignment $R\mapsto (\mathsf {D}(R),\mathrm {L}_{R/A})$ is a big étale sheaf over $A$ of pointed categories, and the above definition for $\mathrm {L}_{Z/A}$ is just Remark 3.4 expanded, so $\mathrm {L}_{-/A}$ takes colimits to limits of pushforwards, and so do $\mathrm {L}_{-/Y}$ and $\mathrm {L}_{X\times _Y-/-}$. In particular, to compute $\mathrm {L}_{Z/A}$, one can write $Z$ as a colimit of affines and take the limit just along these affines, rather than take the whole limit as in the definition. Similarly, one can replace the limit in the definition of $\mathrm {L}_{X/Y}$ by a smaller one, as long as the colimit of the affines is $Y$.

Let $A$ be a ring and $R=\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {Z}}R_n$ be a graded $A$-algebra, considered as acted by $\mathbb {G}_m$ naturally by the grading. In the following proposition, we view quasicoherent sheaves over $\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$ as graded modules of $R$, for example by [Reference MoulinosMou21, Theorem 4.1] and [Reference LurieLur18, Proposition 2.5.1.2].

Proposition 3.29 Let $Y\!=\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$ and $(Y_n)$, $g_n\colon Y_n\to Y$ be the Čech nerve of the cover $\operatorname {Spec}(R)\to \operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$. Then the simplicial object $(g_n)_*\mathrm {L}_{Y_n/A}$ has its partial totalization tower $(\lim _{\Delta _{\le n}}(g_n)_*\mathrm {L}_{Y_n/A})_{n\in \mathbb {N}}$ pro-constant.

Proof. View stacks affine over $Y$ as graded $R$-algebras. Then $Y_n$ corresponds to $S^{(n)}=R[x_0^{\pm 1},\ldots,x_n^{\pm 1}]$ with $\deg (x_i)=1$, while absolutely $Y_n$ is the spectrum of its $0$th grade part $S^{(n)}_0$. Since $S^{(n)}=S^{(n)}_0[x_0^{\pm 1}]$, it is easy to see that for an $S^{(n)}_0$-module $M$, the pushforward along $g_n$ of $M$ is the graded module $M[x_0^{\pm 1}]$. Hence, there is a fiber sequence of graded modules

\begin{align*} (g_n)_*\mathrm{L}_{Y_n/A}=\mathrm{L}_{S^{(n)}_0/A}\otimes_{S^{(n)}_0}S^{(n)}\to \mathrm{L}_{S^{(n)}/A}\to\mathrm{L}_{S^{(n)}/S^{(n)}_0}=S^{(n)}. \end{align*}

Now consider both $(\mathrm {L}_{S^{(n)}/A})$ and $(S^{(n)})$ as cosimplicial objects; then they are functorially made from the Čech nerve of $R\to S^{(0)}=R[x_0^{\pm 1}]$; but this has a left inverse as a map of ungraded rings, so both $(\mathrm {L}_{S^{(n)}/A})$ and $S^{(n)}$ split as cosimplicial ungraded modules, and in particular their pro-objects of partial totalizations are pro-constant ungradedly; now this forces them to also be pro-constant gradedly, and hence so is the pro-object of partial totalizations of the fiber $((g_n)_*\mathrm {L}_{Y_n/A})$.

Proposition 3.30 Consider the natural graded map $\mathrm {L}_{R/A}\to R$ defined as the left Kan extension of the map $\Omega _{R/A}\to R$, $d r\mapsto \deg (r)r$. Then there is a natural isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}_{(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)/A}\cong\operatorname{fib}(\mathrm{L}_{R/A}\to R) \end{align*}

of graded $R$-modules.

Proof. Descend the fiber sequence in the proof of Proposition 3.29 and we have

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}_{(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)/A}=\operatorname{fib}(\mathrm{L}_{R/A}\to\mathrm{L}_{R/(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)}) \end{align*}

as graded $R$-modules. Now view stacks affine over $\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$ as graded rings over $R$. Then by definition, the stack $\operatorname {Spec}(R)$ over $\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$ corresponds to the ring $R[t^{\pm 1}]$ with $\deg (t)=1$. Note that here $R=\mathrm {R}\Gamma (\operatorname {Spec}(R),\mathcal {O}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R)})$ is identified with the $0$th grade part of $R[t^{\pm 1}]$, which is $\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {Z}}R_nt^n$, while on the other hand $\mathrm {L}_{R/(\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m)}=\mathrm {R}\Gamma (\operatorname {Spec}(R),\mathrm {L}_{R/(\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m)})$ is identified with that of $\mathrm {L}_{R[t^{\pm 1}]/R}=R[t^{\pm 1}]\,d t$, which is $\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {Z}}R_nt^{n-1}\,d t$. Therefore, the map $\mathrm {L}_{R/A}\to \mathrm {L}_{R/(\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m)}$ sends $r\in R_n$ to $d(rt^n)=nrt^{n-1}\,d t$, which gives the identification of $\mathrm {L}_{(\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m)/A}$ in the proposition.

The following corollary is [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Proposition B.9], which was left as an exercise by the authors there.

Corollary 3.31 If $R$ is $\mathbb {N}$-graded, then $\mathrm {L}_{(\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m)/A}$ is also $\mathbb {N}$-graded, with $0$th grade part $R_0[-1]\oplus \mathrm {L}_{R_0/A}$, which is the same as $\mathrm {L}_{(\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb {G}_m)/A}$. Therefore, for every integer $n$, the natural map

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma(\operatorname{Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathrm{L}\Omega_{(\operatorname{Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb{G}_m)/A}^n)\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathrm{L}\Omega_{(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)/A}^n) \end{align*}

is an isomorphism. Namely, the Hodge cohomology satisfies strong weighted homotopy invariance.

Proof. Clearly, if $R$ is $\mathbb {N}$-graded, then so is $\mathrm {L}_{R/A}$, with $0$th graded part $\mathrm {L}_{R_0/A}$, and thus so is $\mathrm {L}_{(\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m)/A}=\operatorname {fib}(\mathrm {L}_{R/A}\to R)$, with $0$th graded part $\operatorname {fib}(0\colon \mathrm {L}_{R_0/A}\to R_0)=R_0[-1]\oplus \mathrm {L}_{R_0/A}$. Note that this only depends on $R_0$, so if we replace $R$ by another $\mathbb {N}$-graded $A$-algebra with the same $R_0$, the cotangent complex will be the same. This applies, in particular, to $R_0$, as a graded ring purely in the $0$th grade. Now by Proposition 3.29, one can commute the wedge power with the Čech descent and conclude that

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}\Omega_{(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)/A}^n=\mathrm{L}\Lambda^n\mathrm{L}_{(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)/A}, \end{align*}

where the wedge power is over $\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$. Thus, the desired isomorphism follows from the fact that the wedge power of an $\mathbb {N}$-graded $R$-module $M$ is still $\mathbb {N}$-graded, whose $0$th graded part is just the wedge power of the $R_0$-module $M_0$.

Example 3.32 Take $A=R=\mathbb {Z}$. We get

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}_{\mathrm{B}\mathbb{G}_m/\mathbb{Z}}=\operatorname{fib}(0\to\mathbb{Z})=\mathbb{Z}[-1]. \end{align*}

Example 3.33 Take $A=\mathbb {Z}$ and $R=\mathbb {Z}[t]$ with $\deg (t)=1$. We get

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}_{(\mathbb{A}^1/\mathbb{G}_m)/\mathbb{Z}}=\operatorname{fib}(\mathbb{Z}[t]\,d t\to\mathbb{Z}[t])=\mathbb{Z}[-1] \end{align*}

as a graded $\mathbb {Z}[t]$-module purely in $0$th grade, since the map here is $d t\mapsto t$.

Next we discuss the étale cohomology.

Lemma 3.34 Let $S$ be a $\mathbb {Z}[1/p]$-scheme, $\pi \colon L\to S$ be a line bundle, and $i_0\colon S\to L$ be the zero section. Let $\mathcal {M}\in \mathsf {D}_{\mathrm {\acute {e}t}}(S,\mathbb {Z}_p)$. Then $\pi$ or, equivalently, $i_0$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(S,\mathcal{M})\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(L,\pi^*\mathcal{M}). \end{align*}

Proof. Let $P=\mathbb {P}(L\oplus \mathcal {O}_S)$ be the compactification of $L$ and $\pi _P\colon P\to S$ be the projection. Let $j_\infty \colon L\to P$ and $i_\infty \colon S\to P$ be the inclusions of $L$ and $\infty$, respectively. Then there is a natural fiber sequence

\begin{align*} {i_\infty}_!i_\infty^!\pi_P^*\mathcal{M}\to\pi_P^*\mathcal{M}\to{j_\infty}_*\pi^*\mathcal{M}. \end{align*}

By the étale Poincaré duality, $\pi _P^*\mathcal {M}=\pi _P^!\mathcal {M}(-1)[-2]$, so $i_\infty ^!\pi _P^*\mathcal {M}=\mathcal {M}(-1)[-2]$. Now take $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(P,-)$ of the above sequence, and the lemma follows from the classical computation of the étale cohomology of the projective line.

Let $R=\bigoplus _{i\in \mathbb {N}}R_i$ be a graded $\mathbb {Z}[1/p]$-algebra, considered as acted by $\mathbb {G}_m$ naturally by the grading. Let $\pi \colon \operatorname {Spec}(R)\to \operatorname {Spec}(R_0)$ and $i\colon \operatorname {Spec}(R_0)\to \operatorname {Spec}(R)$ denote the obvious maps.

Proposition 3.35 Let $\mathcal {M}\in \mathsf {D}_\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\operatorname {Spec}(R_0),\mathbb {Z}_p)$. Then $\pi$ or, equivalently, $i$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\operatorname{Spec}(R_0),\mathcal{M})\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\operatorname{Spec}(R),\pi^*\mathcal{M}). \end{align*}

Proof. Since the étale cohomology is insensitive to thickenings, without loss of generality we can assume that $R$ is classical. Let $U=\operatorname {Spec}(R)\setminus \operatorname {Spec}(R_0)$ and let $\pi _U\colon U\to \operatorname {Spec}(R_0)$ and $j_U\colon U\to \operatorname {Spec}(R)$ denote the obvious maps. By the exact triangle

\begin{align*} {j_U}_!\pi_U^*\mathcal{M}\to\pi^*\mathcal{M}\to i_*\mathcal{M}, \end{align*}

it suffices to prove $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\operatorname {Spec}(R),{j_U}_!\pi _U^*\mathcal {M})=0$. Let $X$ be the blowup of $\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)$ in $\operatorname {Spec}(R)$, and let $D$ denote the exceptional divisor. Then $U$ is also $X\setminus D$, and it suffices to prove $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(X,{j_U}_!\pi _U^*\mathcal {M})=0$, where $j_U$ now denotes the open immersion $U\to X$. Let $\mathcal {O}(-1)$ denote the invertible sheaf on $\operatorname {Proj}(R)$ as usual. Then by the construction of blowup, $X$ is the total space of $\mathcal {O}(-1)$ and $D$ is $\operatorname {Proj}(R)$ itself, so the proposition follows from Lemma 3.34.

Corollary 3.36 For every $n\in \mathbb {Z}$,

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\operatorname{Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathbb{Z}_p(n))\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathbb{Z}_p(n)). \end{align*}

Namely, the étale cohomology satisfies strong weighted homotopy invariance.

Proof. This follows immediately from Proposition 3.35 by descent.

Finally, we discuss the étale cohomology of the adic generic fiber, generalizing [Reference Kubrak and PrikhodkoKP21, Remark 5.3.7]. Therefore, let $\mathcal {F}(R)=\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\operatorname {Spec}(\hat {R}[1/p]),\mathbb {Z}_p(n))$ as in Example 3.9, where $n\in \mathbb {Z}$ is fixed. Recall from [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, § 9] that, for $R$ over a perfectoid,

(5)\begin{equation} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\operatorname{Spec}(\hat{R}[1/p]),\mathbb{Z}_p)=({{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_R[1/I]_p^\wedge)^{\varphi=1} =({{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_{R,\mathrm{perf}}[1/I]_p^\wedge)^{\varphi=1}. \end{equation}

In what follows, we will use this to control $\mathcal {F}$. Before this, let us extend the functor ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{-,\mathrm {perf}}$ to arbitrary rings.

Definition 3.37 (Perfect prismatic cohomology)

Recall from [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Lemma 8.8] that perfectoid rings form a basis of the topology $\mathrm {arc}_p$ on $\mathsf {Ring}$. For $m\in \mathbb {Z}$, let ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}^{[m]}_{-,\mathrm {perf}}$ denote the $\mathrm {arc}_p$ sheaves on $\mathsf {Ring}$ whose values on a perfectoid ring $R$ is $I^m{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_R$. Obviously, they are always coconnective and depend on the $\pi _0$ of a ring. By [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Proposition 8.10, Corollary 8.11], ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{-,\mathrm {perf}}={ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}^{[0]}_{-,\mathrm {perf}}$ is well-defined and coincides with the notion there on rings over perfectoids. Let ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{-,\mathrm {perf}}[1/I]=\operatorname{colim}_m{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}^{[m]}_{-,\mathrm {perf}}$ as a functor. By Lemma 3.20, it is automatically an $\mathrm {arc}_p$ sheaf, and we also have

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\operatorname{Spec}(\hat{R}[1/p]),\mathbb{Z}_p)=({{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_{R,\mathrm{perf}}[1/I]_p^\wedge)^{\varphi=1} \end{align*}

for any ring $R$.

Now let $R=\bigoplus _{i\in \mathbb {N}}R_i$ be a graded ring, considered as acted by $\mathbb {G}_m$ naturally by the grading.

Proposition 3.38 The perfect prismatic cohomology satisfies strong weighted homotopy invariance. Namely,

\begin{align*} {{\mathbb {\Delta}}}_{\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathrm{perf}}={{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_{\operatorname{Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathrm{perf}}. \end{align*}

Proof. Since $\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$ and $\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb {G}_m$ are stacks over $R_0$, both sides are $\mathrm {arc}_p$ sheaves with respect to $R_0$, so we can assume that $R_0$ is perfectoid. Consider the Čech nerves of $\operatorname {Spec}(R)\to \operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m$ and $\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)\to \operatorname {Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb {G}_m$, from which we know that ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m,\mathrm {perf}}=\lim _{i\in \Delta }{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R)\times \mathbb {G}_m^i,\mathrm {perf}}$ and similarly for ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb {G}_m,\mathrm {perf}}$. Therefore, the following hold.

  • We can assume that $R$ is classical.

  • By Lemma 3.20, we can pass to limit and assume that $R$ is finitely presented over $R_0$. Say $R=\pi _0(R_0[x_1,\ldots,x_a]/(f_1,\ldots,f_b))$, where $x_1,\ldots,x_a$ and $f_1,\ldots,f_b$ are homogeneous in positive grade.

  • We can replace $R$ by the non-classical $R_0[x_1,\ldots,x_a]/(f_1,\ldots,f_b)$.

Now we are in the case that $R_0$ and $R$ are homotopically bounded $p$-quasisyntomic rings: $R_0$ is perfectoid and, hence, $p$-quasisyntomic, and $R$ is a derived complete intersection over $R_0$. Therefore, by Lemma 3.24, we have ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m}={ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb {G}_m}$. Reducing modulo $p$, since the Frobenius is functorially nullhomotopic in positive homotopical degrees (see the proof of [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Lemma 8.4], or use [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS17, Remark 11.8], since ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-$ actually has derived rings as values), by Lemma 3.20 we have ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R)/\mathbb {G}_m,\mathrm {perf}}/p={ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\operatorname {Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb {G}_m,\mathrm {perf}}/p$. Finally, by $p$-completeness of both sides we get the desired equality.

Remark 3.39 By similar limiting and replacement argument, then using Remark 3.25 to descend from something over a perfectoid, one can prove in steps that:

  • the functors ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{-,\mathrm {perf}}$ commutes with filtered colimits of rings;

  • for any ring $S$ we have ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{S,\mathrm {perf}}=\operatorname{colim}_\varphi { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_S$, where the colimit is taken in the category of ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_S$-modules that are complete along ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_S\to \overline {{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}}_S/p$;

  • equation (5) holds for rings not necessarily over a perfectoid.

Corollary 3.40 The étale cohomology of the adic generic fiber satisfies strong weighted homotopy invariance. Namely,

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m)=\mathcal{F}(\operatorname{Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb{G}_m). \end{align*}

Proof. By [Reference Bhatt and MathewBM21, Corollary 6.17], both sides are $\mathrm {arc}_p$ sheaves with respect to $R_0$. Therefore, we can assume that $R_0$ is over $\mathbb {Z}_p^\mathrm {cyc}$. Since $\mathbb {Z}_p(n)\cong \mathbb {Z}_p$ on $\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Q}_p^\mathrm {cyc})$, we can assume $n=0$. Again use Čech nerves to compute both sides. Since $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\operatorname {Spec}(\hat {S}[1/p]),\mathbb {Z}_p)=({ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{S,\mathrm {perf}}[1/I]_p^\wedge )^{\varphi =1}$ and ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{S,\mathrm {perf}}$ is coconnective for any ring $S$, the desired equality follows from Proposition 3.38 and Lemma 3.20.

Theorem 3.41 The syntomic cohomology satisfies strong weighted homotopy invariance. Namely, for all $n\in \mathbb {Z}$,

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{syn}(\operatorname{Spec}(R)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathbb{Z}_p(n))=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{syn}(\operatorname{Spec}(R_0)/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathbb{Z}_p(n)). \end{align*}

Proof. Combine Lemma 3.23 and Corollaries 3.31, 3.36, and 3.40.

Remark 3.42 The failure of strong weighted homotopy invariance of the absolute prismatic cohomology ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-$ results from the failure of Lemma 3.24 for general stacks. Probably, this is because we are using the wrong category of values, and may be remedied by viewing ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_-$ as taking values in the category of ‘absolute $F$-gauges’, along with a careful study of the strong weighted homotopy invariance of the (non-Hodge-completed) derived de Rham cohomology.

4. Thom classes

We now produce the theory of Thom classes for cohomologies that satisfy a coconnectivity condition. In this and the next sections we will often encounter relative cohomology, so for a big étale sheaf $\mathcal {F}$ with values in a pointed category $\mathcal {C}$:

  • for stacks $X$ and $Y$ with a map $Y\to X$ understood, we let $\mathcal {F}(X,Y)$ denote $\operatorname {fib}(\mathcal {F}(X)\to \mathcal {F}(Y))$;

  • for a pointed stack $*\to X$, we let $\tilde {\mathcal {F}}(X)$ denote $\mathcal {F}(X,*)$.

Throughout this section we are in the following situation.

Situation 4.1 Let $\mathcal {F}=\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {Z}}\mathcal {F}^n$ be a big étale sheaf with values in $\mathsf {Gr}\mathsf {CAlg}(\mathsf {Sp})$. Fix a point $c_1\in \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^1(\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m)$, call it the first Chern class, and suppose that:

  1. (i) $\mathcal {F}$ satisfies the projective bundle formula; more precisely, for any $r\in \mathbb {N}$ and any rank $r$ vector bundle $V\to X$, $(c_1(\mathcal {O}(1))^i)_{i=0}^{r-1}$ induces an isomorphism

    \begin{align*} \bigoplus_{i=0}^{r-1}\mathcal{F}^{\star-i}(X)\cong\mathcal{F}^\star(\mathbb{P}(V)); \end{align*}
  2. (ii) $\mathcal {F}$ satisfies the strong weighted homotopy invariance of Definition 3.5;

  3. (iii) $\mathcal {F}^{\le 0}(\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z}))$ is coconnective.

Note that with the projective bundle formula and the strong weighted homotopy invariance in hand, the proof of [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Theorem 9.3.1] actually shows that:

  • $\mathcal {F}$ has Chern classes, i.e. for $r\in \mathbb {N}$ and a stack $X$ with $\mathcal {F}^{\le 0}(X)$ coconnective,

    \begin{align*} \pi_*\mathcal{F}(X\times\mathrm{B}\mathrm{GL}_r)=(\pi_*\mathcal{F}(X))[c_1,\ldots,c_r] \end{align*}
    as doubly graded rings, where $c_i\in \pi _0\mathcal {F}^i(\mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r)$; these Chern classes are additive, i.e. for $r,s\in \mathbb {N}$, the direct sum map $\mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r\times \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_s\to \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_{r+s}$ induces the map $c_i\mapsto \sum _{j=0}^ic'_jc''_{i-j}$ on homotopy groups.

The prototypical examples are $\mathcal {F}^n(R)$ being $\mathrm {L}\Omega _R^n[n]$, $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(R[1/p],\mathbb {Z}_p(n))[2n]$, and $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {syn}(R,\mathbb {Z}_p(n))[2n]$, by results of [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, § 9.1] and the previous section. The main result of this section can be summarized as follows.

Theorem 4.2 To every stack $X$ and every rank $r$ vector bundle $V\to X$, one can assign the Thom class

\begin{align*} \mathrm{Th}_V^\mathcal{F}\in\Omega^\infty\mathcal{F}^r(V,V\setminus0), \end{align*}

where $0$ denotes the zero section of $V$. The assignment is uniquely determined (up to contractible ambiguity) by the following requirements.

Functoriality. For $f\colon Y\to X$ a morphism of stacks, we have $\mathrm {Th}_{f^*V}^\mathcal {F}=f^*\mathrm {Th}_V^\mathcal {F}$. Rigorously speaking, let $\mathsf {VB}_r$ denote the category

\begin{align*} \{V\to X\mid X \text{ is a stack,}\ V \text{ is a rank } r \text{ vector bundle over } X\} \end{align*}

with morphisms the pullback squares. Then $\mathrm {Th}^\mathcal {F}$ is a natural transformation $*\to \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(V,V\setminus 0)$ in the functor category $\mathsf {Fun}(\mathsf {VB}_r^\mathrm {op},\mathsf {Ani})$.

Normalization. After restricting along the zero section $0\colon X\to V$ and taking $\pi _0$, $\mathrm {Th}_V^\mathcal {F}$ becomes the Chern class $c_r(V)$.

Moreover, the Thom classes are natural in $\mathcal {F}$ and have the following properties.

Thom isomorphism. Promote $V$ to the vector bundle $V/\mathbb {G}_m\to X/\mathbb {G}_m=X\times \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$ by scalar multiplication. Then $\mathrm {Th}^\mathcal {F}_{V/\mathbb {G}_m}$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}^\star(X\times\mathrm{B}\mathbb{G}_m)\cong\mathcal{F}^{\star+r}(V/\mathbb{G}_m,\mathbb{P}(V)). \end{align*}

Additivity. If $V=V'\oplus V''$, then $\mathrm {Th}_V^\mathcal {F}=\mathrm {Th}_{V'}^\mathcal {F}\boxtimes \mathrm {Th}_{V''}^\mathcal {F}$, i.e. the product of the pullback of $\mathrm {Th}_{V'}$ in $\Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^{r'}(V,V\setminus V'')$ and the pullback of $\mathrm {Th}_{V''}$ in $\Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^{r''}(V,V\setminus V')$, where $r'=\operatorname {rk}(V')$, $r''=\operatorname {rk}(V'')$.

Note that the category $\mathsf {VB}_r$ has a final object, i.e. the universal rank $r$ vector bundle which we denote by $\mathrm {E}_r\to \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r$. Thus, by the Yoneda lemma, in order to prove Theorem 4.2, we only need to treat the universal case, i.e. $X=\mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r$ and $V=\mathrm {E}_r$. Therefore, let us study the cohomology of $\mathrm {E}_r$ and $\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0$. Recall that, by definition, $\mathrm {E}_r=\mathbb {G}_a^r/\mathrm {GL}_r$, where $\mathrm {GL}_r$ acts on $\mathbb {G}_a^r$ tautologically.

Proposition 4.3 As stacks over $\mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r$ we have $\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0\cong \mathrm {B}\mathrm {Aff}_{r-1}$ where

\begin{align*} \mathrm{Aff}_{r-1}=\mathbb{G}_a^{r-1}\rtimes\mathrm{GL}_{r-1}=\begin{bmatrix} 1 & \mathbb{G}_a^{r-1}\\ 0 & \mathrm{GL}_{r-1} \end{bmatrix}\subseteq\mathrm{GL}_r. \end{align*}

Proof. This is simply because $\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0=(\mathbb {G}_a^r\setminus 0)/\mathrm {GL}_r$, while $\mathrm {GL}_r$ acts transitively on $\mathbb {G}_a^r\setminus 0$ with point stabilizer $\mathrm {Aff}_{r-1}$.

Proposition 4.4 Let $X$ be a stack and $G\subseteq \mathrm {GL}_{r,X}$ be a subgroup smooth over $X$ that contains the central $\mathbb {G}_{m,X}\to \mathrm {GL}_{r,X}$. Then the projection $\mathbb {G}_{a,X}^r/G\to \mathrm {B} G$ induces an isomorphism $\mathcal {F}(\mathrm {B} G)\cong \mathcal {F}(\mathbb {G}_{a,X}^r/G)$. In particular, taking $G=\mathrm {GL}_{r,X}$ we have that the projection $X\times \mathrm {E}_r\to X\times \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r$ induces an isomorphism $\mathcal {F}(X\times \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r)\cong \mathcal {F}(X\times \mathrm {E}_r)$.

Proof. The proposition basically follows from the proof of [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Corollary 9.2.10], but the statement there does not contain the case here, so we redo the proof.

Let everything be over $X$. Let $H=G/\mathbb {G}_m$. Then $H$ is also smooth, and

is a fiber square. View $\mathrm {B} G$ as over $\mathrm {B} H$. If we can prove that for every stack $Y$ over $X$ and every $X$-map $Y\to \mathrm {B} H$, the base change of $\mathbb {G}_a^r/G\to */G$ to $Y$ induces an isomorphism after taking $\mathcal {F}$, then the proposition will follow by descent. Now the base change is nothing but $\mathbb {G}_{a,Y}^r/\mathbb {G}_{m,Y}\to Y/\mathbb {G}_{m,Y}$, where $\mathbb {G}_{m,Y}$ acts on $\mathbb {G}_{a,Y}^r$ by scalar multiplication, so we are done by weighted homotopy invariance.

Proposition 4.5 For any stack $X$, the natural map $\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}\to \mathrm {Aff}_{r-1}$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}(X\times\mathrm{B}\mathrm{Aff}_{r-1})\cong\mathcal{F}(X\times\mathrm{B}\mathrm{GL}_{r-1}). \end{align*}

Proof. Let everything be over $X$ to simplify notation. By $\mathrm {Aff}_{r-1}=\mathbb {G}_a^{r-1}\rtimes \mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$ we have $\mathrm {B}\mathrm {Aff}_{r-1}=\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_a^{r-1}/\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$, where $\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$ tautologically acts on $\mathbb {G}_a^{r-1}$. Under this identification, $\mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}\to \mathrm {B}\mathrm {Aff}_{r-1}$ corresponds to the map $*/\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}\to \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_a^{r-1}/\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$ defined as the canonical covering $*\to \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_a^{r-1}$ quotient by $\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$. By descent, we only need to prove that the Čech nerves of $*/\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}\to \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_a^{r-1}/\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$ and $*/\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}\to */\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$ have the same cohomology on each term, i.e. for each $k\in \mathbb {N}$ the map $(\mathbb {G}_a^{r-1})^k/\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}\to */\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}$ induces an isomorphism after applying $\mathcal {F}$, but this follows immediately from Proposition 4.4.

Proposition 4.6 For any stack $X$ with $\mathcal {F}^{\le 0}(X)$ coconnective, the natural restriction map $\pi _*\mathcal {F}(X\times \mathrm {E}_r)\to \pi _*\mathcal {F}(X\times (\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0))$ is the map

\begin{align*} (\pi_*\mathcal{F}(X))[c_1,\ldots,c_r]\to(\pi_*\mathcal{F}(X))[c_1,\ldots,c_{r-1}] \end{align*}

that leaves $c_1,\ldots,c_{r-1}$ unchanged and maps $c_r$ to $0$. In particular, it is surjective and, thus,

\begin{align*} \pi_*\mathcal{F}(X\times\mathrm{E}_r,X\times(\mathrm{E}_r\setminus0))&=\ker(\pi_*\mathcal{F}(X\times\mathrm{E}_r)\to\pi_*\mathcal{F}(X\times(\mathrm{E}_r\setminus0)))\\ &=c_r(\pi_*\mathcal{F}(X)[c_1,\ldots,c_r]). \end{align*}

Proof. By Propositions 4.3, 4.4, and 4.5, the map $X\times (\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0)\to X\times \mathrm {E}_r$ is cohomologically the same as the map $X\times \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_{r-1}\to X\times \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r$ induced by adding a trivial line bundle. Thus, the proposition follows from the additivity formula of Chern classes.

Proof Proof of Theorem 4.2

By Proposition 4.6,

\begin{align*} \pi_*\mathcal{F}(\mathrm{E}_r,\mathrm{E}_r\setminus0)=c_r(\pi_*\mathcal{F}(\operatorname{Spec}(\mathbb{Z}))[c_1,\ldots,c_r]). \end{align*}

Since $c_i\in \pi _0\mathcal {F}^i$, among the right-hand side only $\pi _*\mathcal {F}^{\le 0}(\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z}))$ may contribute to $\pi _*\mathcal {F}^r(\mathrm {E}_r,\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0)$. By assumption (iii) of Situation 4.1, this implies that $\mathcal {F}^r(\mathrm {E}_r,\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0)$ is coconnective, so $\Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(\mathrm {E}_r,\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0)$ is a $0$-truncated anima, in which $c_r$ is naturally a point. Therefore, by normalization, the Thom class of the universal bundle $\mathrm {E}_r\to \mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r$ can be and must be defined as $c_r\in \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(\mathrm {E}_r,\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0)$, which is unique up to contractible choice. Now the Thom class of a general rank $r$ vector bundle is uniquely determined by the universal case.

To prove the additivity, one reduces to the universal case, where it follows from the additivity of the Chern class. To prove the Thom isomorphism, note by weighted homotopy invariance that $V/\mathbb {G}_m\to \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m\times X$ induces an isomorphism $\mathcal {F}(\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m\times X)\cong \mathcal {F}(V/\mathbb {G}_m)$, while $(V/\mathbb {G}_m)\setminus (0/\mathbb {G}_m)=\mathbb {P}(V)$ is the projective bundle. Now by additivity and the projective bundle formula, the Thom isomorphism reduces to the case $r=1$, where it follows immediately by the projective bundle formula.

Remark 4.7 It seems magical that, starting with Chern classes in the homotopy groups, we are able to get the desired Thom class up to contractible ambiguity. This is, in fact, because the assumption (iii) of Situation 4.1 essentially guarantees that the ‘candidate space’ $\Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(\mathrm {E}_r, \mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0)$ of the Thom class is discrete, so once we have specified the connected component that the class lives in, we have specified the class up to contractible ambiguity.

Remark 4.8 Alternatively, one can impose the normalization only for line bundles but add the additivity of Thom classes to get the uniqueness statement, because by additivity of Chern classes, the natural map

\begin{align*} \pi_*\mathcal{F}(\mathrm{E}_r,\mathrm{E}_r\setminus0)\to\pi_*\mathcal{F}(\mathrm{E}_1^r,\mathrm{E}_1^r\setminus0) \end{align*}

is injective, sending $c_r$ to the box product of the $r$ different $c_1$'s on the right.

Remark 4.9 (Naturality)

By uniqueness, the Thom class $\mathrm {Th}^\mathcal {F}$ is natural in $\mathcal {F}$, with respect to maps that preserve $c_1$. In particular, it is natural along the map

\begin{align*} \mathbb{Z}_p(n)\to\operatorname{Fil}^n{{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_-\{n\}\to\operatorname{Fil}^n\widehat{\mathrm{dR}_-}\to\widehat{\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_-}[-n] \end{align*}

from the syntomic cohomology to the $p$-completed Hodge cohomology, by [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Theorem 7.6.2].

Remark 4.10 (Identifying $c_1^\mathrm {Hod}$ and $\mathrm {Th}_1^\mathrm {Hod}$)

Take $\mathcal {F}^n(R)=\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_R[n]$. By Example 3.32, $\mathcal {F}^1(\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m)=\mathbb {Z}$, in which $1$ corresponds to the Hodge first Chern class originally defined by the map $\mathrm {dlog}\colon \mathbb {G}_m\to \mathrm {L}\Omega ^1$, thanks to the proof of Proposition 3.30. Therefore, the Thom class is also $1\in \mathbb {Z}$, under the identification of Example 3.33.

Remark 4.11 Our way of stating Situation 4.1 and Theorem 4.2 is convenient for later uses in the paper, but far from optimal.

  • We can use general base stacks in place of $\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Z})$.

  • Formulated properly, the values of $\mathcal {F}$ need not be graded. See [Reference Annala and IwasaAI23, § 3].

  • We only need the smooth weighted homotopy invariance rather than the strong one, except for the Thom isomorphism.

  • With $\mathbb {P}^1$-homotopy techniques as in [Reference Annala and IwasaAI23], one should be able to get rid of all the coconnectivity assumptions in this section. This can be applied, for example, to the Hodge cohomology over an animated ring.

5. Cycle classes

In this section we construct cycle classes, by reducing to Thom classes with deformation to the normal cone, following [Reference ClausenCla21, Lecture 15]. In § 5.1, we define the weighted deformation to the normal cone for a general closed immersion, and prove that for any regular immersion, the cohomology of this deformation space coincides with that of its special fiber, for several cohomology theories. These results are then used in § 5.2 to generate cycle classes from Thom classes.

5.1 Deformation to the normal cone

Classically, deformation to the normal cone is a construction that deforms a regular immersion into the zero section of its normal cone. Here, with derived algebraic geometry in hand, we are able to perform this construction for all closed immersions of derived stacks, and it will behave well especially for derived regular immersions.

Before going into the construction, we first study closed immersions of derived stacks in general.

Definition 5.1 (Animated pairs)

A pair is a map $A\to B$ of animated rings with $\pi _0A\to \pi _0B$ surjective. Let $\mathsf {Pair}$ denote the category of pairs, i.e. the full category of $\mathsf {Fun}(\Delta ^1,\mathsf {Ring})$ spanned by the pairs. We say that a pair $A\to B$ is classical if both $A$ and $B$ are classical. This coincides with the classical notion of a pair: a ring $A$ with an ideal $I=\ker (A\to B)$ of it.

Remark 5.2 (Colimits in $\mathsf {Pair}$)

Let $(A_i\to B_i)_{i\in I}$ be a diagram in $\mathsf {Pair}$. Then its colimit in $\mathsf {Fun}(\Delta ^1,\mathsf {Ring})$ is $\operatorname{colim} A_i\to \operatorname{colim} B_i$. Since $\pi _0\colon \mathsf {Ring}\to \mathsf {Ring}^\heartsuit$ preserves colimits and colimits in $\mathsf {Ring}^\heartsuit$ preserve surjections, we see that $(\operatorname{colim} A_i\to \operatorname{colim} B_i)\in \mathsf {Pair}$, so it is also the colimit of $(A_i\to B_i)_{i\in I}$ in $\mathsf {Pair}$.

Alternatively, one can take the colimit of $(A_i\to B_i)_{i\in I}$ in two steps: first take $A=\operatorname{colim} A_i$ and take base changes $B_i'=B_i\otimes _{A_i}A$, then take $B=\operatorname{colim} B_i'$ in the category of $A$-algebras, and the resulting $A\to B$ will be the desired colimit.

Remark 5.3 (Projective generators of $\mathsf {Pair}$)

Consider two objects $\mathbb {Z}[x]\to \mathbb {Z}$ and $\mathbb {Z}[y]\to \mathbb {Z}[y]$ in $\mathsf {Pair}$, where the maps are $x\mapsto 0$ and $\operatorname {id}$, respectively. It is easy to see that $\mathbb {Z}[x]\to \mathbb {Z}$ corepresents the functor $(A\to B)\mapsto \operatorname {fib}(A\to B)$, while $\mathbb {Z}[y]\to \mathbb {Z}[y]$ corepresents the functor $(A\to B)\mapsto A$. Since both functors commute with sifted colimits, both objects are projective, and hence so are their finite products $\mathbb {Z}[x_1,\ldots,x_r,y_1,\ldots,y_s]\to \mathbb {Z}[y_1,\ldots,y_s]$ for all $r,s\in \mathbb {N}$. In addition, since the functor $\mathsf {Pair}\to \mathsf {Ani}\times \mathsf {Ani}$, $(A\to B)\mapsto (A,\operatorname {fib}(A\to B))$ is conservative, the two objects generate $\mathsf {Pair}$. Let

\begin{align*} \mathsf{Pair}_\mathrm{c}=\{\mathbb{Z}[x_1,\ldots,x_r,y_1,\ldots,y_s]\to\mathbb{Z}[y_1,\ldots,y_s]\mid r,s\in\mathbb{N}\} \end{align*}

be the full subcategory of $\mathsf {Pair}$ spanned by these finite products. Then by [Reference LurieLur09, Proposition 5.5.8.22], $\mathsf {Pair}=\mathsf {P}_\Sigma (\mathsf {Pair}_\mathrm {c})$, namely the animation of $\mathsf {Pair}_\mathrm {c}$.

Remark 5.4 ($n$-truncated objects in $\mathsf {Pair}$)

By Remark 5.3 and [Reference LurieLur09, Remark 5.5.8.26], for $n\in \mathbb {N}$, an object $(A\to B)\in \mathsf {Pair}$ is $n$-truncated if and only if both $A$ and $\operatorname {fib}(A\to B)$ are $n$-truncated as animas. Therefore, a $0$-truncated object in $\mathsf {Pair}$ is not always classical. See also [Reference MaoMao21, Remark 3.9].

Definition 5.5 (Closed immersions)

Let $Y\to X$ be a map of stacks. We say that it is a closed immersion if it is corepresentable by pairs or, in other words, for any ring $A$ and any map $\operatorname {Spec}(A)\to X$, the pullback $Y\times _X\operatorname {Spec}(A)$ is some $\operatorname {Spec}(B)$ with $\pi _0A\twoheadrightarrow \pi _0B$. In this case we also say that $Y$ is a closed substack of $X$.

Definition 5.6 (Regular immersions)

We say that a pair $A\to B$ is regular of codimension $r$ if Zariski locally it is a base change of the pair $\mathbb {Z}[x_1,\ldots,x_r]\to \mathbb {Z}$, $x_1,\ldots,x_r\mapsto 0$. We say that a closed immersion $Y\to X$ of stacks is a regular immersion of codimension $r$ if it is corepresentable by regular pairs of codimension $r$; we say that it is a regular immersion if it is a disjoint union of regular immersions of codimension $r$ for different $r\in \mathbb {N}$.

Definition 5.7 (The classifying stack of pairs)

Consider the functor $\mathsf {Pair}\to \mathsf {Ring}$, $(A\to B)\mapsto A$. It is a cocartesian fibration with small fibers, whose cocartesian edges are

\begin{align*} \{(A\to B)\to(A'\to B')\mid B'=B\otimes_AA'\}. \end{align*}

Therefore, by the Grothendieck construction in [Reference LurieLur09, § 3.2], it corresponds to a functor $\mathsf {Ring}\to \mathsf {Cat}$, taking $A$ to the category of all pairs $A\to B$.

Let $\mathrm {Pair}\colon \mathsf {Ring}\to \mathsf {Ani}$ be the functor taking $A$ to the anima of pairs $A\to B$, corresponding under the Grothendieck construction to the subcategory of $\mathsf {Pair}$ that contains only the cocartesian edges. Then it is obviously a stack, which we call the classifying stack of pairs or the classifying stack of closed immersions. Denote the universal closed immersion by $\mathrm {Closed}\to \mathrm {Pair}$. Then, by definition,

\begin{align*} \mathrm{Closed}(A)=\{\text{a pair $A\to B$ along with a section $B\to A$}\}, \end{align*}

i.e. a closed immersion $\operatorname {Spec}(B)\to \operatorname {Spec}(A)$ with a point of $\operatorname {Spec}(B)$. Denote the universal open complement by $\mathrm {Open}\to \mathrm {Pair}$. Then similarly

\begin{align*} \mathrm{Open}(A)=\{\text{a pair $A\to B$ along with a section $\operatorname{Spec}(A)\to\operatorname{Spec}(A)\setminus\operatorname{Spec}(B)$}\}, \end{align*}

which implies that $\mathrm {Open}=*$, since the section forces $B=0$.

For $r\in \mathbb {N}$, we can also define the classifying stacks of regular immersions of codimension $r$ in exactly the same way, which we denote by $\mathrm {Pair}_r$, and similarly $\mathrm {Closed}_r$ and $\mathrm {Open}_r$ for the universal closed and open substacks. By definition, $\mathrm {Pair}_r$ is the image of the étale sheaf map $\mathbb {A}^r\to \mathrm {Pair}$ classifying the standard immersion $*\to \mathbb {A}^r$. Note that $\mathrm {Open}_r$ is always $*$, except for $r=0$ where it is empty.

The tensor product of $A$-algebras gives $\mathrm {Pair}(A)$ an $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-monoid structure, making $\mathrm {Pair}$ an $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-monoid stack. Note that the point $*=\mathrm {Open}\to \mathrm {Pair}$ is a zero element of this monoid; in other words, $\mathrm {Pair}$ is an $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-monoid in the category of pointed stacks, with respect to the smash product.

Remark 5.8 By base change of the cotangent complex, for $Y\to X$ a regular immersion (of codimension $r$), it is easy to see that $\mathrm {L}_{Y/X}[-1]$ is locally free (of rank $r$) on $Y\!$.

Now we construct the derived Rees algebra. The following proposition is [Reference Clausen and ScholzeCS22, Proposition 13.3].

Proposition 5.9 (Cf. [Reference MaoMao21, Corollary 3.54])

Let $(A\to B)\in \mathsf {Pair}$. Consider the initial animated filtered $A$-algebra $I^\bullet$ equipped with a map of animated $A$-algebras $B\to I^0/I^1$. Then we have $I^n=A$ for $n\le 0$, and $I^0/I^1=B$; in particular, $I=I^1$ is the fiber of $A\to B$. Moreover, we have $I/I^2=\mathrm {L}_{B/A}[-1]$ and $I^n/I^{n+1}=\operatorname {LSym}_B^n(I/I^2)$ for $n\ge 0$. The formation of $I^\bullet$ preserves all colimits as a functor $\mathsf {Pair}\to \mathsf {Fil}\mathsf {Ring}$, commutes with base change in $A$, and if $A\to B$ is classical and is a local complete intersection, then $I^\bullet$ is classical and agrees with the usual filtered $A$-algebra of powers of $I$.

Remark 5.10 Proposition 5.9 can be generalized to general morphisms in $\mathsf {Ring}$, not necessarily surjective on $\pi _0$, but one needs to use derived rings as in [Reference RaksitRak20, Example 4.3.1, Construction 4.3.4], in place of animated rings. It is similar to but different from [Reference RaksitRak20, § 5.3].

In the following definitions, the notation $I^n$ is as in Proposition 5.9.

Definition 5.11 (Rees algebra and deformation to the normal cone)

For a pair $A\to B$, its Rees algebra is the graded $A[t]$-algebra

\begin{align*} \mathcal{R}_{B/A}=\bigoplus_{n\in\mathbb{Z}}I^{-n}t^n, \end{align*}

where $t$ is called the Rees parameter. There is an obvious graded map $\mathcal {R}_{B/A}\to B[t]$, which we denote by $\mathcal {R}(A\to B)\in \mathsf {Pair}$. By Proposition 5.9, $\mathcal {R}$ commutes with all colimits, when viewed as a functor from pairs to graded pairs over the graded ring $\mathbb {Z}[t]$. The (weighted) deformation to the normal cone of $A\to B$ is the closed immersion of Artin stacks obtained by quotienting $\mathcal {R}(A\to B)$ by the $\mathbb {G}_m$-action defined by the grading, i.e. the map

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Spec}(B)\times\mathbb{A}^1/\mathbb{G}_m=\operatorname{Spec}(B[t])/\mathbb{G}_m\to\operatorname{Spec}(\mathcal{R}_{B/A})/\mathbb{G}_m, \end{align*}

viewed as a map of stacks over $\mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$. Its open fiber (the fiber over $\mathbb {G}_m/\mathbb {G}_m\to \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$) is $\operatorname {Spec}(B)\to \operatorname {Spec}(A)$, while its closed fiber (the fiber over $0/\mathbb {G}_m\to \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$) is $\operatorname {Spec}(B)/\mathbb {G}_m\to \operatorname {Spec}(\operatorname {LSym}_B^\star (I/I^2))/\mathbb {G}_m$, which is the quotient by the $\mathbb {G}_m$-multiplication on the normal cone of $\operatorname {Spec}(B)\to \operatorname {Spec}(A)$.

This construction clearly satisfies étale descent and commutes with base change of $A$ and, hence, can be globalized and classified. More precisely, $(A\to B)\mapsto \operatorname {Spec}(\mathcal {R}_{B/A})/\mathbb {G}_m$ defines a stack over $\mathrm {Pair}\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$, denoted by $\mathrm {DNC}$, whose fiber over $\mathrm {Closed}\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ is $\mathrm {Closed}\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ itself. Its restriction to $\mathrm {Pair}\times \mathbb {G}_m/\mathbb {G}_m$ is $\operatorname {id}_\mathrm {Pair}$, while its restriction to $\mathrm {Pair}\times 0/\mathbb {G}_m$ is the quotient by $\mathbb {G}_m$ of the normal cone $\underline {\operatorname {Spec}}_\mathrm {Pair}(\operatorname {LSym}^\star (\mathcal {I}_\mathrm {Closed}/\mathcal {I}_\mathrm {Closed}^2))$ of $\mathrm {Closed}\to \mathrm {Pair}$. For a closed immersion $Y\to X$ of stacks, its deformation to the normal cone can be constructed as the base change of $\mathrm {Closed}\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m\to \mathrm {DNC}$ along the classifying map $X\to \mathrm {Pair}$.

Definition 5.12 (Animated blowup)

The blowup of a pair $A\to B$ is the $A$-scheme $\mathrm {Bl}_B(A)=\operatorname {Proj}\big (\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {N}}I^n\big )$. The natural ‘inclusion’ map $\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {N}}I^{n+1}\to \bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {N}}I^n$ defines a section of the line bundle $\mathcal {O}(-1)$, whose zero locus is, by definition, $\operatorname {Proj}\big (\bigoplus _{n\in \mathbb {N}}I^n/I^{n+1}\big )$, which we call the exceptional divisor. Note that it is the projectivized normal cone $\operatorname {Proj}(\operatorname {LSym}_B^\star (I/I^2))$ of $\operatorname {Spec}(B)$ in $\operatorname {Spec}(A)$. Similarly, this construction can also be globalized and classified. For a closed immersion $Y\to X$ of stacks, we denote its blowup by $\mathrm {Bl}_Y(X)$.

Remark 5.13 The two concepts are closely related. Namely, one can check that:

  • $\mathrm {Bl}_B(A)=(\operatorname {Spec}(\mathcal {R}_{B/A})\setminus (\operatorname {Spec}(B[t])\cup \operatorname {Spec}(A)))/\mathbb {G}_m$;

  • $\operatorname {Spec}(\mathcal {R}_{B/A})=\mathrm {Bl}_B(A[t])\setminus \mathrm {Bl}_B(A)$, where the map $A[t]\to A$ sends $t$ to $0$.

Next we study the cohomology of the deformation to the normal cone. Fix an $r\in \mathbb {N}$, let $Y\to X$ be a regular immersion of stacks of codimension $r$, and let $\mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$ be its deformation to the normal cone, with closed fiber $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$.

We begin with the Hodge cohomology. Recall that stacks affine over $\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$ correspond to graded rings, whose quasicoherent sheaves correspond to graded modules, and taking global section corresponds to taking the $0$th grade.

Proposition 5.14 Let $A\to B$ be a regular pair of codimension $r$. For any $n\in \mathbb {Z}$, the local cohomology $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{\operatorname {Spec}(B[t])}(\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_{\mathcal {R}_{B/A}/\mathbb {Z}[t]})$ and $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{\operatorname {Spec}(B)}(\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_{\operatorname {LSym}_B^\star (I/I^2)/\mathbb {Z}})$ are both nonnegatively graded, and the base change map along $A[t]\to A$, $t\mapsto 0$ identifies the $0$th grade parts of them.

Proof. Localizing, we can assume that $A\to B$ is a base change of $\mathbb {Z}[x_1,\ldots,x_r]\to \mathbb {Z}$. Consider the direct sums

\begin{align*} \bigoplus_{n\in\mathbb{Z}}\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B[t])}(\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_{\mathcal{R}_{B/A}/\mathbb{Z}[t]}[-n])\in\mathsf{D}(\mathbb{Z}[t]) \end{align*}

and

\begin{align*} \bigoplus_{n\in\mathbb{Z}}\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B)}(\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_{\operatorname{LSym}_B^\star(I/I^2)/\mathbb{Z}}[-n])\in\mathsf{D}(\mathbb{Z}) \end{align*}

instead of individual complexes. Then they commute with sifted colimits in $A$ as $\mathbb {Z}[x_1,\ldots,x_r]$-algebras, and take coproducts of pairs to tensor products, so one reduces to the case $r$ is either $1$ or $0$ and $A\to B$ is either $\mathbb {Z}[x]\to \mathbb {Z}$ or $\mathbb {Z}[y]\to \mathbb {Z}[y]$, respectively. Now $\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n$ is nonzero only when $n=0$ or $n=1$.

In the $\mathbb {Z}[x]\to \mathbb {Z}$ case, $\mathcal {R}_{B/A}=\mathbb {Z}[xt^{-1},t]$ with the surjection to $B[t]=\mathbb {Z}[t]$ killing $xt^{-1}$, so one computes

\begin{gather*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B[t])}(\mathcal{R}_{B/A})=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{xt^{-1}}(\mathbb{Z}[xt^{-1},t])=\bigoplus_{k=1}^\infty\mathbb{Z}[t]t^kx^{-k}[-1],\\ \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B)}(\operatorname{LSym}_B^\star(I/I^2))=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{xt^{-1}}(\mathbb{Z}[xt^{-1}])=\bigoplus_{k=1}^\infty\mathbb{Z} t^kx^{-k}[-1],\\ \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B[t])}(\mathrm{L}_{\mathcal{R}_{B/A}/\mathbb{Z}[t]})=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{xt^{-1}}(\mathbb{Z}[xt^{-1},t]\,d(xt^{-1}))=\bigoplus_{k=1}^\infty\mathbb{Z}[t]t^kx^{-k}\,d(xt^{-1})[-1],\\ \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B)}(\mathrm{L}_{\operatorname{LSym}_B^\star(I/I^2)/\mathbb{Z}})=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{xt^{-1}}(\mathbb{Z}[xt^{-1}]\,d(xt^{-1}))=\bigoplus_{k=1}^\infty\mathbb{Z} t^kx^{-k}\,d(xt^{-1})[-1]. \end{gather*}

In the $\mathbb {Z}[y]\to \mathbb {Z}[y]$ case, $A=B$, $I=0$ and $\mathcal {R}_{B/A}=B[t]=\mathbb {Z}[y,t]$, so the local cohomology does nothing, and one computes

\begin{gather*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B[t])}(\mathcal{R}_{B/A})=\mathbb{Z}[y,t],\\ \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B)}(\operatorname{LSym}_B^\star(I/I^2))=\mathbb{Z}[y],\\ \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B[t])}(\mathrm{L}_{\mathcal{R}_{B/A}/\mathbb{Z}[t]})=\mathbb{Z}[y,t]\,d y,\\ \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B)}(\mathrm{L}_{\operatorname{LSym}_B^\star(I/I^2)/\mathbb{Z}})=\mathbb{Z}[y]\,d y. \end{gather*}

In all these cases one easily verifies the proposition.

Corollary 5.15 For every $n\in \mathbb {N}$, the inclusion $\mathfrak {X}_0\to \mathfrak {X}$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathfrak{Y}(\mathfrak{X},\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_\mathfrak{X})\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\mathfrak{Y}_0}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_{\mathfrak{X}_0}). \end{align*}

Proof. Both sides are sheaves with respect to $X$, so one can assume that $X=\operatorname {Spec}(A)$ is affine and, hence, so is $Y=\operatorname {Spec}(B)$. Let $f\colon \mathfrak {X}\to \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ and $f_0\colon \mathfrak {X}_0\to \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$ be the structure maps. Then we have the fiber sequences

\begin{align*} f^*\mathrm{L}_{\mathbb{A}^1/\mathbb{G}_m}\to\mathrm{L}_\mathfrak{X}\to\mathrm{L}_{\mathfrak{X}/(\mathbb{A}^1/\mathbb{G}_m)} \end{align*}

and

\begin{align*} f_0^*\mathrm{L}_{\mathrm{B}\mathbb{G}_m}\to\mathrm{L}_{\mathfrak{X}_0}\to\mathrm{L}_{\mathfrak{X}_0/\mathrm{B}\mathbb{G}_m}, \end{align*}

which imply that $\mathrm {L}\Omega _\mathfrak {X}^n$ is filtered by $\mathrm {L}\Omega _{\mathfrak {X}/(\mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m)}^i\otimes f^*\mathrm {L}\Omega _{\mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m}^j$ with $i+j=n$, and similarly for $\mathfrak {X}_0$. Now by Example 3.33, $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathfrak {Y}(\mathrm {L}\Omega _{\mathfrak {X}/(\mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m)}^i\otimes f^*\mathrm {L}\Omega _{\mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m}^j)$ is computed by taking the $0$th grade part of

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B[t])}\big(\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_{\mathcal{R}_{B/A}/\mathbb{Z}[t]}\big)\otimes_{\mathbb{Z}[t]}\mathrm{L}\Lambda_{\mathbb{Z}[t]}^j(\mathbb{Z}[-1]), \end{align*}

while by Example 3.32, $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{\mathfrak {Y}_0}(\mathrm {L}\Omega _{\mathfrak {X}_0/\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m}^i\otimes f_0^*\mathrm {L}\Omega _{\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m}^j)$ is computed by taking the $0$th grade part of

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\operatorname{Spec}(B)}\big(\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_{\operatorname{LSym}_B^\star(I/I^2)}\big)\otimes_\mathbb{Z}\mathrm{L}\Lambda_\mathbb{Z}^j(\mathbb{Z}[-1]), \end{align*}

and by Proposition 5.14 it is not hard to see that the two are isomorphic via the natural map.

We then study the étale cohomology.

Proposition 5.16 Suppose $X$ and $Y$ are over $\mathbb {Z}[1/p]$. Let $\tilde {\mathfrak {Y}}\to \tilde {\mathfrak {X}}$ be the deformation to the normal cone without quotient by $\mathbb {G}_m$, and $\tilde {\mathfrak {Y}}_0\to \tilde {\mathfrak {X}}_0$ be the fiber over $0\to \mathbb {A}^1$. Then for every étale $\mathbb {Z}_p$-sheaf $\mathcal {M}$ on $X$, the inclusion $\tilde {\mathfrak {X}}_0\to \tilde {\mathfrak {X}}$ induces an isomorphism on local cohomology

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\mathrm{\acute{e}t},\tilde{\mathfrak{Y}}}(\tilde{\mathfrak{X}},\tilde{f}^*\mathcal{M})\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\mathrm{\acute{e}t},\tilde{\mathfrak{Y}}_0}(\tilde{\mathfrak{X}}_0,\tilde{f}_0^*\mathcal{M}). \end{align*}

Here $\tilde {f}\colon \tilde {\mathfrak {X}}\to X$ and $\tilde {f}_0\colon \tilde {\mathfrak {X}}_0\to \tilde {\mathfrak {X}}\to X$ are the natural maps.

Proof. The proposition is clearly étale local on $X$, so we can assume that $X=\operatorname {Spec}(A)$ is affine and, hence, so is $Y=\operatorname {Spec}(B)$. Then $\tilde {\mathfrak {X}}=\operatorname {Spec}(\mathcal {R}_{B/A})$, $\tilde {\mathfrak {Y}}=\operatorname {Spec}(B[t])$, $\tilde {\mathfrak {X}}_0=\operatorname {Spec}(\operatorname {LSym}_B^\star (I/I^2))$, $\tilde {\mathfrak {Y}}_0=\operatorname {Spec}(B)$, as in Definition 5.11. By excision, we can assume that the pair $A\to B$ is Henselian, i.e. the classical pair $\pi _0A\to \pi _0B$ is Henselian.

Now by Remark 5.13 and excision, the left-hand side is

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{A}^1_X),\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{A}^1_X)\setminus\operatorname{Spec}(\mathbb{A}^1_Y),g^*\mathcal{M}), \end{align*}

where $g\colon \mathrm {Bl}_Y(\mathbb {A}^1_X)\to X$ is the projection. To compute it, we consider the compactification $j\colon \mathrm {Bl}_Y(\mathbb {A}^1_X)\to \mathrm {Bl}_Y(\mathbb {P}^1_X)$, which also compactifies $\mathbb {A}^1_Y$ to $\mathbb {P}^1_Y$. Let $\pi$ denote the projections $\mathrm {Bl}_Y(\mathbb {P}^1_X)\to X$, and $i$ denote the complement of $j$. Since the inclusion $Y\to \mathbb {A}^1_X$ has image in $0\to \mathbb {A}^1_X$, the blowup changes nothing near $\infty \to \mathbb {P}^1_X$. Therefore by the étale Poincaré duality and by excision again, we have $i^!\pi ^*\mathcal {M}=\mathcal {M}(-1)[-2]$. Hence,

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{A}^1_X),g^*\mathcal{M})&=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{P}^1_X),j_*g^*\mathcal{M})\\ &=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{P}^1_X),\operatorname{cofib}(i_!i^!\pi^*\mathcal{M}\to\pi^*\mathcal{M}))\\ &=\operatorname{cofib}(\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(X,\mathcal{M}(-1)[-2])\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{P}^1_X),\pi^*\mathcal{M})). \end{align*}

Note that $\mathrm {Bl}_Y(\mathbb {P}^1_X)$ is proper over $X$, whose fiber over $Y$ is $\mathbb {P}^1_Y\sqcup _Y\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}\oplus \mathcal {O}_Y)$. Here $\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}$ denotes the normal bundle and $\mathbb {P}$ means projectivization. Therefore, by Gabber's affine proper base change [Aut, 09ZI],

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{P}^1_X),\pi^*\mathcal{M})=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathbb{P}^1_Y\sqcup_Y\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}\oplus\mathcal{O}_Y),\bar{\pi}^*\mathcal{M}), \end{align*}

where $\bar {\pi }$ denotes the corresponding projection. Take the pushout out of $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}$, and note that $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(X,\mathcal {M}(-1)[-2])=\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(Y,\mathcal {M}(-1)[-2]|_Y)$ cancels the $\mathbb {P}^1_Y\sqcup _Y-$ again by the affine proper base change, we conclude that

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{A}^1_X),g^*\mathcal{M})=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}\oplus\mathcal{O}_Y),\pi_0^*\mathcal{M}), \end{align*}

where $\pi _0$ denotes the projection $\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}\oplus \mathcal {O}_Y)\to X$. On the other hand, note that $\mathrm {Bl}_Y(\mathbb {A}^1_X)\setminus \operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {A}^1_Y)$ is the total space of $\mathcal {O}(-1)$ on $\mathrm {Bl}_Y(X)$, so by Lemma 3.34 and the affine proper base change,

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{A}^1_X)\setminus\operatorname{Spec}(\mathbb{A}^1_Y),\pi^*\mathcal{M})=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(X),\beta^*\mathcal{M}) =\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}),\beta_0^*\mathcal{M}), \end{align*}

where $\beta \colon \mathrm {Bl}_Y(X)\to X$ and $\beta _0\colon \mathbb {P}(\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})\to X$ are the projections. Recall that the total space of $\mathcal {O}(-1)$ on $\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})$ is $\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}\oplus \mathcal {O}_Y)\setminus 0$, so we finally have

\begin{align*} &\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{A}^1_X),\mathrm{Bl}_Y(\mathbb{A}^1_X)\setminus\operatorname{Spec}(\mathbb{A}^1_Y),g^*\mathcal{M})\\ &\quad =\operatorname{fib}(\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}\oplus\mathcal{O}_Y),\pi_0^*\mathcal{M})\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}),\beta_0^*\mathcal{M}))\\ &\quad =\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}\oplus\mathcal{O}_Y),\mathbb{P}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}\oplus\mathcal{O}_Y)\setminus0,\pi_0^*\mathcal{M}), \end{align*}

but this is exactly the right-hand side

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\tilde{\mathfrak{X}}_0,\tilde{\mathfrak{X}}_0\setminus\tilde{\mathfrak{Y}}_0,\tilde{f}_0^*\mathcal{M}) =\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{\acute{e}t}(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X},\mathcal{N}_{Y/X}\setminus0,\tilde{f}_0^*\mathcal{M}), \end{align*}

by excision.

Corollary 5.17 For every $n\in \mathbb {Z}$, the inclusion $\mathfrak {X}_0\to \mathfrak {X}$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\mathrm{\acute{e}t},\mathfrak{Y}}(\mathfrak{X},\mathbb{Z}_p(n))\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{\mathrm{\acute{e}t},\mathfrak{Y}_0}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathbb{Z}_p(n)). \end{align*}

Proof. This follows immediately from Proposition 5.16 by descent.

We finally study the étale cohomology of the generic fiber. As before, we use the étale comparison of the prismatic cohomology to control it.

Proposition 5.18 The inclusion $\mathfrak {X}_0\to \mathfrak {X}$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} {{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_{\mathfrak{X},\mathfrak{X}\setminus\mathfrak{Y},\mathrm{perf}}\cong{{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}}_{\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathfrak{X}_0\setminus\mathfrak{Y}_0,\mathrm{perf}}. \end{align*}

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Proposition 3.38. Both sides are $\mathrm {arc}_p$ sheaves over $X$, so we can assume that $X=\operatorname {Spec}(R)$ is the spectrum of a perfectoid ring, and then $Y=\operatorname {Spec}(S)$ is the spectrum of an $R$-algebra. Now $S=R/(x_1,\ldots,x_r)$ is a derived complete intersection in $R$. Then $S$ is homotopically bounded and quasi-lci over $R$, so by Lemma 3.24 and Corollary 5.15, we have ${ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\mathfrak {X},\mathfrak {X}\setminus \mathfrak {Y}}={ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{\mathfrak {X}_0,\mathfrak {X}_0\setminus \mathfrak {Y}_0}$. Finally Lemma 3.20 gives us the desired equality.

Corollary 5.19 Let $\mathcal {F}$ be the big étale sheaf $R\mapsto \mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(\operatorname {Spec}(\hat {R}[1/p]),\mathbb {Z}_p(n))$, where $n\in \mathbb {Z}$ is fixed. Then the inclusion $\mathfrak {X}_0\to \mathfrak {X}$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}(\mathfrak{X},\mathfrak{X}\setminus\mathfrak{Y})\cong\mathcal{F}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathfrak{X}_0\setminus\mathfrak{Y}_0). \end{align*}

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Corollary 3.40. Both sides are $\mathrm {arc}_p$ sheaves over $X$, so we can assume that $X=\operatorname {Spec}(R)$ for a $\mathbb {Z}_p^\mathrm {cyc}$-algebra $R$. Since $\mathbb {Z}_p(n)\cong \mathbb {Z}_p$ on $\operatorname {Spec}(\mathbb {Q}_p^\mathrm {cyc})$, we can assume $n=0$. In addition, both are quotients of qcqs schemes by $\mathbb {G}_m$, so we can use Čech nerves to compute them. Since $\mathcal {F}(U)=({ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{U,\mathrm {perf}}[1/I]_p^\wedge )^{\varphi =1}$ for any qcqs scheme $U$ (which follows from the affine case by taking a finite limit), the desired equality follows from Proposition 3.38 and Lemma 3.20.

Finally, we can prove our theorem on the syntomic cohomology of the deformation to the normal cone.

Theorem 5.20 For every integer $n$, the inclusion $\mathfrak {X}_0\to \mathfrak {X}$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{syn}(\mathfrak{X},\mathfrak{X}\setminus\mathfrak{Y},\mathbb{Z}_p(n))\cong\mathrm{R}\Gamma_\mathrm{syn}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathfrak{X}_0\setminus\mathfrak{Y}_0,\mathbb{Z}_p(n)). \end{align*}

Proof. Combine Lemma 3.23 and Corollaries 5.15, 5.17, and 5.19.

Remark 5.21 We wonder whether the same holds for general closed immersions, not necessarily regular. For the étale cohomology the same proof seems to show the general statement, while for the Hodge cohomology and the étale cohomology of the generic fiber we have no idea.

5.2 Constructing cycle classes

We now use what we have computed in the previous subsection to construct cycle classes from Thom classes.

Theorem 5.22 (Characteristic classes of regular pairs)

Let $\mathcal {C}$ be a pointed presentable category and let $\mathcal {F}$ be a big étale sheaf with values in $\mathcal {C}$. Fix $r\in \mathbb {N}$. Let $\mathrm {E}_r$ denotes the universal rank $r$ vector bundle over $\mathrm {B}\mathrm {GL}_r$ and $0_r$ denotes the zero section. Then since $0_r\to \mathrm {E}_r$ is a regular immersion of codimension $r$, it corresponds to a map $\beta _r\colon \mathrm {E}_r\to \mathrm {Pair}_r$ with $\beta _r^{-1}(\mathrm {Closed}_r)=0_r$. Assume that for any regular immersion $Y\to X$ of stacks of codimension $r$, we have

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}(\mathfrak{X},\mathfrak{X}\setminus\mathfrak{Y})=\mathcal{F}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathfrak{X}_0\setminus\mathfrak{Y}_0), \end{align*}

where $\mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$ is the deformation to the normal cone of $Y\to X$ and $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$ is its closed fiber. Then $\beta _r$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \beta_r^*\colon\mathcal{F}(\mathrm{Pair}_r,\mathrm{Open}_r)\cong\mathcal{F}(\mathrm{E}_r,\mathrm{E}_r\setminus0_r). \end{align*}

In other words, all the $\mathcal {F}$-characteristic classes of pairs that vanish on the open loci come from those of zero sections in rank $r$ vector bundles.

Proof. Let $\mathrm {DNC}_r\to \mathrm {Pair}_r\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ denote the deformation to the normal cone of $\mathrm {Pair}_r$, and $\mathrm {Open}_{\mathrm {DNC}_r}$ denote the complement of $\mathrm {Closed}_r\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ in $\mathrm {DNC}_r$. Let $\mathrm {DNC}_{r,0}$ and $\mathrm {Open}_{\mathrm {DNC}_{r,0}}$ denote the fiber of $\mathrm {DNC}_r$ and $\mathrm {Open}_{\mathrm {DNC}_r}$, respectively. By construction, $\mathrm {DNC}_{r,0}$ is the weighted normal bundle of $\mathrm {Closed}_r\to \mathrm {Pair}_r$, so there is a natural classifying map $\mathrm {DNC}_{r,0}\to \mathrm {E}_r$. Consider the diagram

where the lower left map is the natural open immersion identifying $\mathrm {Pair}_r$ with the fiber over $\mathbb {G}_m/\mathbb {G}_m$ of $\mathrm {DNC}_r$. Then it exhibits $\mathrm {Pair}_r$ as a retract of $\mathrm {DNC}_r$. Now take $\mathcal {F}$ relative to the open parts. Since the central vertical map becomes an isomorphism after this operation, the diagram exhibits $\mathcal {F}(\mathrm {Pair}_r,\mathrm {Open}_r)$ as a retract of $\mathcal {F}(\mathrm {E}_r,\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0_r)$, i.e. $\beta _r^*$ has a left inverse.

Note that the above diagram gives an endomorphism of $\mathcal {F}(\mathrm {E}_r,\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0_r)$ by splicing $\beta _r\colon \mathrm {E}_r\to \mathrm {Pair}_r$ to its lower left corner. We will finish the proof by showing that it is the identity, since then the left inverse of $\beta _r^*$ will also be the right inverse. To this end, we can base change the above diagram from $\mathrm {Pair}_r$ to $\mathrm {E}_r$ and get the diagram

where the upper right map is not the projection but the classifying map of the weighted normal bundle. Now by Lemma 5.23 below, there is a map indicated by the dashed arrow that makes the diagram commutes and exhibits $\mathrm {E}_r$ as a retract of $\mathrm {DNC}_r\times _{\mathrm {Pair}_r}\mathrm {E}_r$, therefore completing the proof.

Lemma 5.23 The deformation to the normal cone of the zero section of a vector bundle $V\!$ on a stack $X$ is the zero section of the vector bundle $V(-1)$ on $X\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$, where $(-1)$ denotes the twist by the inverse of the universal bundle on $\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$. Therefore, it restricts to $V\!$ itself on the open fiber, and restricts to the weighted normal bundle on the closed fiber.

Proof. Recall that the deformation to the normal cone of $\mathbb {Z}[x]\to \mathbb {Z}$ is $\mathbb {Z}[xt^{-1},t]\to \mathbb {Z}[t]$. By its compatibility of base change and products, we know that the deformation to the normal cone of $B[x_1,\ldots,x_r]\to B$ is $B[x_1t^{-1},\ldots,x_rt^{-1},t]\to B[t]$, which is the zero section of the $(-1)$-twisted trivial bundle on $\operatorname {Spec}(B)\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ as described. Note that this identification is compatible with change of coordinates, so we can globalize it and conclude.

Remark 5.24 The proof of Theorem 5.22 actually proves a stronger statement: let $\mathcal {F}$ be a big étale sheaf over $\mathrm {Pair}_r$ that satisfies the same assumption with points taken over $\mathrm {Pair}_r$. Then $\beta _r$ induces an isomorphism

\begin{align*} \beta_r^*\colon\mathcal{F}(\mathrm{Pair}_r,\mathrm{Open}_r)\cong\mathcal{F}(\mathrm{E}_r,\mathrm{E}_r\setminus0_r), \end{align*}

still with points taken over $\mathrm {Pair}_r$.

Remark 5.25 Let $\mathcal {F}$ be as in Theorem 5.22, and $Y\to X$ be a map of stacks. Then $\mathcal {G}(-)=\mathcal {F}(X\times -,Y\times -)$ also satisfies the same assumption as $\mathcal {F}$ does, since deformation to the normal cone commutes with $X\times -$ and $Y\times -$. Therefore,

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}((X,Y)\times(\mathrm{Pair}_r,\mathrm{Open}_r))\cong\mathcal{F}((X,Y)\times(\mathrm{E}_r,\mathrm{E}_r\setminus0)), \end{align*}

where the product is understood as

\begin{align*} (X_0,Y_0)\times(X_1,Y_1)=(X_0\times X_1,(Y_0\times X_1)\sqcup_{Y_0\times Y_1}(X_0\times Y_1)). \end{align*}

In the rest of this subsection, let $\mathcal {F}$ be as in Situation 4.1 and suppose $\mathcal {F}$ satisfies the assumption of Theorem 5.22 for all $r\in \mathbb {N}$. By the previous subsection, this holds for $\mathcal {F}^n(R)$ being $\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_R[n]$, $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {\acute {e}t}(R[1/p],\mathbb {Z}_p(n))[2n]$, and $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _\mathrm {syn}(R,\mathbb {Z}_p(n))[2n]$.

Definition 5.26 (Cycle classes)

For $r\in \mathbb {N}$, let $\mathrm {Cl}_r^\mathcal {F}\in \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(\mathrm {Pair}_r,\mathrm {Open}_r)$ be the image of the universal Thom class $\mathrm {Th}_r^\mathcal {F}\in \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(\mathrm {E}_r,\mathrm {E}_r\setminus 0_r)$ under the isomorphism in Theorem 5.22, called the universal cycle class of codimension $r$. For a regular immersion $Y\to X$ of codimension $r$, let $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}^\mathcal {F}\in \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(X,X\setminus Y)$ be the pullback of $\mathrm {Cl}_r^\mathcal {F}$ along the classifying map $X\to \mathrm {Pair}_r$, called the cycle class of $Y$ in $X$. By abuse of notation, we also use $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}^\mathcal {F}$ to denote its image in $\Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(X)$.

Remark 5.27 (Relation with blowup)

Suppose the blowup formula holds, i.e.

is a pullback square for every regular immersion $Y\to X$ of codimension $r$ with blowup $\tilde {X}$ and exceptional divisor $D$ (by [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Theorem 9.4.1] this is the case for syntomic cohomology). Suppose further that we have a decomposition

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}^\star(\tilde{X})=\mathcal{F}^\star(X)\oplus\bigoplus_{i=1}^{r-1}\mathcal{F}^{\star-i}(Y) \end{align*}

functorial on $Y\to X$, extending the projective bundle formula of $D=\mathbb {P}(\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})$. Denoting $U=X\setminus Y=\tilde {X}\setminus D$, one gets from above a similar decomposition

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}^\star(\tilde{X},U)=\mathcal{F}^\star(X,U)\oplus\bigoplus_{i=1}^{r-1}\mathcal{F}^{\star-i}(Y). \end{align*}

In this case, $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}^\mathcal {F}$ can also be defined as the image of $-c_1(-D)^r\in \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(\tilde {X},U)$ under the projection to $\Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^r(X,U)$ (cf. [Reference FujiwaraFuj02, Definition 1.1.2]). In fact, by functoriality and Theorem 5.22, it suffices to check the case $0_r\to \mathrm {E}_r$, which can be easily done by hand.

Remark 5.28 (Uniqueness)

By construction, it is easy to see that the cycle class is uniquely determined by the following requirements.

Functoriality: for $f\colon X'\to X$ a morphism of stacks with $Y'=Y\times _XX'$, we have $\mathrm {Cl}_{Y'/X'}^\mathcal {F}=f^*\mathrm {Cl}_{Y/X}^\mathcal {F}$.

Normalization: for the zero section of a vector bundle, it is the Thom class in Theorem 4.2.

Therefore, the cycle class is natural in $\mathcal {F}$ with respect to maps that preserve $c_1$, cf. Remark 4.9.

Remark 5.29 (Multiplicativity)

By Theorem 5.22 and the additivity of Thom classes, one easily deduces that $\mathrm {Cl}_{r'}^\mathcal {F}\boxtimes \mathrm {Cl}_{r''}^\mathcal {F}=m^*\mathrm {Cl}_r^\mathcal {F}$, where $r=r'+r''$ and $m\colon \mathrm {Pair}_{r'}\times \mathrm {Pair}_{r''}\to \mathrm {Pair}_r$ represents the intersection. By Remark 4.8 and Theorem 5.22, the cycle classes are uniquely determined by multiplicativity and the normalization in codimension $1$, which states that $\mathrm {Cl}_{D/X}=c_1(\mathcal {O}(D))$ for a Cartier divisor $D\to X$.

The multiplicativity in the above remark has no homotopy coherence a priori, but the coconnectivity condition on $\mathcal {F}$ actually forces the coherence. This will not be used in the following.

Lemma 5.30 Let $\mathcal {C}^\otimes$ be a symmetric monoidal category and let $A,B\in \mathsf {CAlg}(\mathcal {C})$. Suppose for every $n\in \mathbb {N}$ that $\operatorname {Hom}_\mathcal {C}(A^{\otimes n},B)$ is $0$-truncated. Then

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathsf{CAlg}(\mathcal{C})}(A,B)=\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathsf{CAlg}(\mathrm{h}\mathcal{C})}(A,B) \end{align*}

and is $0$-truncated, where $\mathrm {h}\mathcal {C}$ means the homotopy $1$-category of $\mathcal {C}$.

Proof. Recall from [Reference LurieLur17, Definition 2.1.3.1] that $\mathsf {CAlg}(\mathcal {C})=\mathsf {Fun}_{\mathsf {Fin}_*}(\mathsf {Fin}_*,\mathcal {C}^\otimes )$, and $A,B\in \mathsf {CAlg}(\mathcal {C})$ are actually functors $A^\otimes,B^\otimes \colon \mathsf {Fin}_*\to \mathcal {C}^\otimes$ that takes $\langle 1\rangle$ to $A,B\in \mathcal {C}$. As $\operatorname {Hom}$ in the functor category, $\operatorname {Hom}_{\mathsf {CAlg}(\mathcal {C})}(A,B)$ is built up as a limit of $\operatorname {Hom}_{\mathcal {C}^\otimes }^f(A^\otimes _{\langle n\rangle },B^\otimes _{\langle m\rangle })$ for $n,m\in \mathbb {N}$ and $f\colon \langle n\rangle \to \langle m\rangle$ in $\mathsf {Fin}_*$. Since, by definition, $\mathcal {C}^\otimes \to \mathsf {Fin}_*$ is a cocartesian fibration, we have

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}^\otimes}^f\big(A^\otimes_{\langle n\rangle},B^\otimes_{\langle m\rangle}\big) =\operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}^\otimes_{\langle m\rangle}}\big(\otimes_f\big(A^\otimes_{\langle n\rangle}\big),B^\otimes_{\langle m\rangle}\big) \end{align*}

in the notation of [Reference LurieLur17, Remark 2.1.2.16]; then by [Reference LurieLur17, Remark 2.1.2.19] one easily computes that

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}^\otimes_{\langle m\rangle}}\big(\otimes_f\big(A^\otimes_{\langle n\rangle}\big),B^\otimes_{\langle m\rangle}\big) =\prod_{i=1}^m\operatorname{Hom}_\mathcal{C}(A^{\otimes f^{-1}(i)},B), \end{align*}

which is $0$-truncated by assumption. Therefore, as a limit of $0$-truncated animas, $\operatorname {Hom}_{\mathsf {CAlg}(\mathcal {C})}(A,B)$ is also $0$-truncated. Finally, we conclude by noting that $\operatorname {Hom}_{\mathsf {CAlg}(\mathrm {h}\mathcal {C})}(A,B)$ is computed by exactly the same limit.

Let $\mathrm {Pair}_\mathrm {reg}\subseteq \mathrm {Pair}$ denote the stack of regular pairs without a fixed dimension; then it inherits the $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-monoid structure of $\mathrm {Pair}$ with respect to the smash product, as described at the end of Definition 5.7. Let $\Sigma ^\infty$ denote the left adjoint of the functor $\Omega ^\infty$ from the category of $\mathsf {Sp}$-valued big étale sheaves to the category of pointed stacks, by abuse of notation. Then since $\mathrm {Pair}_\mathrm {reg}=(\mathrm {Pair}_0)_+\vee \bigvee _{r\in \mathbb {Z}_+}\mathrm {Pair}_r$ is graded, $\Sigma ^\infty \mathrm {Pair}_\mathrm {reg}$ is naturally a graded $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-ring.

Proposition 5.31 The multiplicativity in Remark 5.29 uniquely determines a map $\Sigma ^\infty \mathrm {Pair}_\mathrm {reg}\to \mathcal {F}$ of big étale sheaves with values graded $\mathbb {E}_\infty$-rings.

Proof. By Lemma 5.30, it suffices to check for every $n\in \mathbb {N}$ that

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Hom}_{\mathsf{Fun}(\mathsf{Ring},\mathsf{Gr}\mathsf{Sp})}((\Sigma^\infty\mathrm{Pair}_\mathrm{reg})^{\otimes n},\mathcal{F})\in\mathsf{Ani}_{\le0}. \end{align*}

Passing to each grade and using the fact that $\Sigma ^\infty$ takes the smash product to the tensor product, we need to check that for $r_1,\ldots,r_n\in \mathbb {Z}_+$ and $r=\sum _{i=1}^nr_i$,

\begin{align*} \tilde{\mathcal{F}}^r\bigg(\bigwedge_{i=1}^n\mathrm{Pair}_{r_i}\bigg)\in\mathsf{Sp}_{\le0}. \end{align*}

Now by Remark 5.25,

\begin{align*} \tilde{\mathcal{F}}\bigg(\bigwedge_{i=1}^n\mathrm{Pair}_{r_i}\bigg)=\mathcal{F}\bigg(\prod_{i=1}^n(\mathrm{E}_{r_i},\mathrm{E}_{r_i}\setminus0)\bigg), \end{align*}

so the desired coconnectivity follows by applying Proposition 4.6 $n$ times.

Cycle classes can be upgraded to Gysin maps as follows.

Definition 5.32 (Gysin maps)

Fix $r\in \mathbb {N}$. Let $Y\to X$ be a regular immersion of codimension $r$, $\mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$ be its deformation to the normal cone and $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$ be the closed fiber. Then the Gysin map of $Y\to X$ is constructed as the composition

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}^\star(Y)\to\mathcal{F}^\star(\mathfrak{Y}_0)\to\mathcal{F}^{\star+r}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathfrak{X}_0\setminus\mathfrak{Y}_0) =\mathcal{F}^{\star+r}(\mathfrak{X},\mathfrak{X}\setminus\mathfrak{Y})\to\mathcal{F}^{\star+r}(X,X\setminus Y), \end{align*}

where the first arrow comes from the projection $\mathfrak {Y}_0=Y\times 0/\mathbb {G}_m\to Y$, the second arrow is the Thom map, and the final arrow is restriction to the open fiber. By Theorem 5.22, $\mathrm {Cl}^\mathcal {F}_{Y/X}$ is the image of $1\in \Omega ^\infty \mathcal {F}^0(Y)$ under the Gysin map. By the definition of the Thom map, after composing with the restriction $\mathcal {F}(X,X\setminus Y)\to \mathcal {F}(Y)$, the Gysin map becomes multiplying $c_r(\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})$.

We now identify the Gysin map for the Hodge cohomology. For a regular pair $R\to S$, the functor $i_*\colon \mathsf {D}(S)\to \mathsf {D}(R)$ commutes with colimits, preserves compact objects, and hence has a right adjoint $i^!\colon \mathsf {D}(R)\to \mathsf {D}(S)$ that preserves colimits.

Lemma 5.33 The functor $i^!\colon \mathsf {D}(R)\to \mathsf {D}(S)$ satisfies the projection formula $i^!-=i^!R\otimes _Si^*-$, and is compatible with base change of pairs.

Proof. For $M\in \mathsf {D}(R)$, the natural map

\begin{align*} M=\operatorname{\underline{Hom}}_R(R,M)\to\operatorname{\underline{Hom}}_R(i_*i^!R,M)=i_*\operatorname{\underline{Hom}}_S(i^!R,i^!M) \end{align*}

gives by adjunction the desired map

\begin{align*} i^!R\otimes_Si^*M\to i^!M. \end{align*}

Now it is an isomorphism when $M=R$, and both sides commute with colimits in $M$, so it is an isomorphism for all $M\in \mathsf {D}(R)$. For the compatibility with base change, one can check after $i_*$, which follows from the fact that $i_*i^!-=\operatorname {\underline {Hom}}_R(S,-)=S^\vee \otimes _R-$, since by assumption $S$ is dualizable in $\mathsf {D}(R)$.

Now consider a regular immersion $i\colon Y\to X$ of stacks of codimension $r$. Recall by Remark 3.6 that we still have the functor $i_*\colon \mathsf {D}(Y)\to \mathsf {D}(X)$. Since colimits of quasicoherent sheaves can be computed locally, $i_*$ still commutes with colimits, is compatible with base change, and thus has a right adjoint $i^!$ that also has these properties and satisfies the projection formula.

Lemma 5.34 There is a natural identification of $i^!\mathcal {O}_X=\det (\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})[-r]$ compatible with base change and product of pairs, where $\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}$ denotes the normal bundle.

Proof. Computing locally, we see that $i^!\mathcal {O}_X$ is an invertible object in $\mathsf {D}(Y)$. To identify it, we first consider the case where $\pi \colon X\to Y$ is a rank $r$ vector bundle and $i\colon Y\to X$ is the immersion of the zero section. Let $\mathcal {O}=\mathcal {O}_Y$, $\mathcal {N}=\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}$, and $\mathcal {A}=\operatorname {LSym}_\mathcal {O}^\star (\mathcal {N}^\vee )=\pi _*\mathcal {O}_X$. Now the Koszul sequence

\begin{align*} 0\to\mathcal{A}\otimes\Lambda^r\mathcal{N}^\vee\to\cdots\to\mathcal{A}\otimes\mathcal{N}^\vee\to\mathcal{A}\to\mathcal{O}\to0 \end{align*}

gives a natural identification $\operatorname {\underline {Hom}}_\mathcal {A}(\mathcal {O},\mathcal {A})=\det (\mathcal {N})[-r]$ as an $\mathcal {A}$-module, so

\begin{align*} i^!\mathcal{O}_X=\pi_*i_*i^!\mathcal{O}_X=\pi_*\operatorname{\underline{Hom}}_\mathcal{A}(\mathcal{O},\mathcal{A})=\det(\mathcal{N})[-r] \end{align*}

as an $\mathcal {O}$-module.

For a general $i\colon Y\to X$, we consider its deformation to the normal cone $\mathfrak {i}\colon \mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$, whose closed fiber $\mathfrak {i}_0\colon \mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$ is naturally the vector bundle $\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}/\mathbb {G}_m$ on $\mathfrak {Y}_0=Y\times \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$. Therefore, by the previous paragraph, $\mathfrak {i}^!\mathcal {O}_\mathfrak {X}$ is an invertible object in $\mathsf {D}(\mathfrak {Y})$, whose restriction on $\mathfrak {Y}_0=Y\times \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$ is $\det (\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})[-r]$ with $\mathbb {G}_m$ acting by weight $r$. However, $\mathfrak {Y}=Y\times \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$, so $\mathsf {D}(\mathfrak {Y})$ can be viewed as the category of graded quasicoherent $\mathcal {O}_Y[t]$-modules. Now $\mathfrak {i}^!\mathcal {O}_\mathfrak {X}$ is an invertible graded $\mathcal {O}_Y[t]$-modules which gives $\det (\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})[-r]$ on degree $r$ after quotient by $t$. Hence,

\begin{align*} \mathfrak{i}^!\mathcal{O}_\mathfrak{X}=\bigoplus_{n=r}^\infty\det(\mathcal{N}_{Y/X})t^n[-r], \end{align*}

and obviously its restriction to the open part $Y\to \mathfrak {Y}$ is $\det (\mathcal {N}_{Y/X})$.

The compatibility with base change and product follows from the compatibility of both the deformation to the normal cone and the Koszul sequence.

Construction 5.35 Recall from the shifted fiber sequence of cotangent complexes

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}_{Y/X}[-1]\to i^*\mathrm{L}_X\to\mathrm{L}_Y \end{align*}

that the normal bundle $\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}$ can be identified as $\mathrm {L}_{Y/X}[-1]^\vee$. Since $\mathrm {L}_{Y/X}[-1]$ is locally free of rank $r$, the above sequence gives a natural map

\begin{align*} \Lambda^r(\mathrm{L}_{Y/X}[-1])\otimes\mathrm{L}\Omega^n_Y\to i^*\mathrm{L}\Omega^{n+r}_X; \end{align*}

since $\Lambda ^r(\mathrm {L}_{Y/X}[-1])=(i^!\mathcal {O}_X[r])^\vee$ by Lemma 5.34, we can take it to the right-hand side, use the projection formula, and obtain a Gysin map

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}\Omega^n_Y\to i^!\mathcal{O}_X\otimes\mathrm{L}\Omega^{n+r}_X[r]=i^!\mathrm{L}\Omega^{n+r}_X[r]. \end{align*}

Proposition 5.36 The Gysin map for the Hodge cohomology is the global section of the adjunction $i_*\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_Y\to \mathrm {L}\Omega ^{n+r}_X[r]$ of the above map. Since $i_*\mathrm {L}\Omega ^n_Y$ restricts to $0$ on $X\setminus Y$, it actually maps to the relative Hodge cohomology of $(X,X\setminus Y)$.

Proof. Consider the deformation to the normal cone $\mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$ and its closed fiber $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$. Since the immersion of the open part exhibits the pair $Y\to X$ as a retract of $\mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$, it suffices to prove the proposition for $\mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$. Now by Corollary 5.15 the relative Hodge cohomology of $(\mathfrak {X},\mathfrak {X}\setminus \mathfrak {Y})$ coincides with that of $(\mathfrak {X}_0,\mathfrak {X}_0\setminus \mathfrak {Y}_0)$, so it suffices to prove the same for $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$.

Therefore, we can assume that $\pi \colon X\to Y$ is a rank $r$ vector bundle and $i\colon Y\to X$ is the immersion of the zero section, and try to prove that the map described above is the Thom map. In this case, the Hodge cohomology of $X$ is naturally a module of the Hodge cohomology of $Y$ by $\pi ^*$, and the map described is a module map, so it suffices to prove that the image of $1$ is $\mathrm {Th}_{X/Y}$. By Remark 4.8, this reduces to checking the functoriality, the additivity, and the normalization for line bundles for this image. Now both the functoriality and the additivity follow from Lemma 5.34. For the normalization for line bundles, we work in the universal case $\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m\to \mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ by identifying quasicoherent sheaves on $\mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m$ as graded $\mathbb {Z}[t]$-modules, where it is routine to check that the map $i_*\mathcal {O}_{\mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m}\to \mathrm {L}_{\mathbb {A}^1/\mathbb {G}_m}[1]$ is $1$ under the identification of Example 3.33, which coincides with $\mathrm {Th}_1^\mathrm {Hod}$ by Remark 4.10.

Similar method can be used to enhance the Gysin map of the $p$-completed topological cyclic homology to a motivic filtered map. First we recall the filtration.

Proposition 5.37 There is a natural exhaustive filtration $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \mathrm {TC}(R)_p^\wedge$ on the $p$-completed $\mathrm {TC}$, functorial in $R\in \mathsf {Ring}$, such that:

  1. (i) $\operatorname {gr}^i\mathrm {TC}(R)_p^\wedge =\mathbb {Z}_p(i)(\hat {R})[2i]$; in particular, $\operatorname {Fil}^0\mathrm {TC}(R)_p^\wedge =\mathrm {TC}(R)_p^\wedge$;

  2. (ii) the functor $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \mathrm {TC}_p^\wedge \colon \mathsf {Ring}\to \mathsf {Fil}(\mathsf {Sp}_p^\wedge )$ commutes with sifted colimits, and hence is left Kan extended from polynomial rings of finite type over $\mathbb {Z}$;

  3. (iii) $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \mathrm {TC}_p^\wedge$ is a big étale sheaf, and is even a $p$-quasisyntomic sheaf when restricted to classical $p$-bounded $p$-quasisyntomic rings.

Proof. Note that $\mathrm {TC}(R)_p^\wedge$ only depends on $\hat {R}$, since $\mathrm {THH}(R)_p^\wedge$ is so. In addition, by [Reference Clausen, Mathew and MorrowCMM21, Corollary 2.15], the functor $\mathrm {TC}_p^\wedge \colon \mathsf {Ring}\to \mathsf {Sp}_p^\wedge$ commutes with sifted colimits, so we can construct the filtration by left Kan extension from classical $p$-bounded $p$-quasisyntomic rings, where it follows from [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19, § 7.4], which automatically implies part (iii). Now parts (i) and (ii) follow from [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Proposition 7.4.8].

Recall that $\mathrm {TC}(R)$ is actually an invariant of the category $\mathsf {D}(R)^\omega$ of perfect $R$-complexes, since $\mathrm {THH}$ is so, cf. [Reference Blumberg, Gepner and TabuadaBGT13, § 10.1]. Hence, if $R\to S$ is a regular pair, then there is a wrong-way map $\mathsf {D}(S)^\omega \to \mathsf {D}(R)^\omega$, since perfect $S$-complexes are perfect $R$-complexes. This induces a pushforward map $\mathrm {TC}(S)\to \mathrm {TC}(R)$, which can be globalized to a pushforward map $\mathrm {TC}(Y)\to \mathrm {TC}(X)$ associated to every regular immersion $Y\to X$ of stacks. Here the meaning of $\mathrm {TC}(X)$ is as in Remark 3.4. Since the composition $\mathsf {D}(S)^\omega \to \mathsf {D}(R)^\omega \to \mathsf {D}(\operatorname {Spec}(R)\setminus \operatorname {Spec}(S))^\omega$ is functorially zero, the map $\mathrm {TC}(Y)\to \mathrm {TC}(X)$ factors through $\mathrm {TC}(X,X\setminus Y)$.

Theorem 5.38 (The Gysin map for $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \mathrm {TC}_p^\wedge$)

Fix $r\in \mathbb {N}$. There is a unique way (up to contractible choice) to enhance the map $\mathrm {TC}(Y)_p^\wedge \to \mathrm {TC}(X,X\setminus Y)_p^\wedge$ to a filtered map $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet \mathrm {TC}(Y)_p^\wedge \to \operatorname {Fil}^{\bullet +r}\mathrm {TC}(X,X\setminus Y)_p^\wedge$ functorially for all regular immersions $Y\to X$ of codimension $r$. Moreover, its associated graded is the Gysin map for the syntomic cohomology of $p$-formal schemes as in Definition 5.32.

Proof. For notational simplicity, we omit all the $-_p^\wedge$, and use $\mathbb {Z}_p(i)$ to denote the functor $R\mapsto \mathbb {Z}_p(i)(\hat {R})$. It suffices to prove that for integers $n\ge n'$, the map

(6)\begin{equation} \operatorname{Fil}^n\mathrm{TC}(Y)\to\mathrm{TC}(Y)\to\mathrm{TC}(X,X\setminus Y)\to\mathrm{TC}(X,X\setminus Y)/\operatorname{Fil}^{n'+r}\mathrm{TC}(X,X\setminus Y) \end{equation}

has a unique functorial nullhomotopy. As before, let $\mathfrak {Y}\to \mathfrak {X}$ denote the deformation to the normal cone of $Y\to X$, and let $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$ denote its closed fiber. Note that the above map can be written as

\begin{align*} &\operatorname{Fil}^n\mathrm{TC}(Y)\to\operatorname{Fil}^n\mathrm{TC}(\mathfrak{Y}_0)\to\mathrm{TC}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathfrak{X}_0\setminus\mathfrak{Y}_0)/\operatorname{Fil}^{n'+r}\mathrm{TC}(\mathfrak{X}_0,\mathfrak{X}_0\setminus\mathfrak{Y}_0)\\ &\quad \cong\mathrm{TC}(\mathfrak{X},\mathfrak{X}\setminus\mathfrak{Y})/\operatorname{Fil}^{n'+r}\mathrm{TC}(\mathfrak{X},\mathfrak{X}\setminus\mathfrak{Y})\to\mathrm{TC}(X,X\setminus Y)/\operatorname{Fil}^{n'+r}\mathrm{TC}(X,X\setminus Y), \end{align*}

where the first arrow comes from the projection $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to Y$, the second arrow is the map (6) for $\mathfrak {Y}_0\to \mathfrak {X}_0$, the isomorphism is due to Theorem 5.20 since $\mathrm {TC}/\operatorname {Fil}^{n'+r}\mathrm {TC}$ is finitely filtered by $\mathbb {Z}_p(i)[2i]$, and the final arrow is restriction to the open fiber. Recall that $\mathfrak {X}_0=\mathcal {N}_{Y/X}/\mathbb {G}_m$ is the weighted normal bundle over $\mathfrak {Y}_0=Y\times \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$. Therefore, the theorem is reduced to the following statement: the map

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^n\mathrm{TC}(Y)\to\mathrm{TC}(V/\mathbb{G}_m,(V\setminus0)/\mathbb{G}_m)/\operatorname{Fil}^{n'+r}\mathrm{TC}(V/\mathbb{G}_m,(V\setminus0)/\mathbb{G}_m) \end{align*}

has a unique nullhomotopy that is functorial in the rank $r$ vector bundle $V\to Y$. Now the right-hand side is finitely filtered by

\begin{align*} \mathbb{Z}_p(i+r)(V/\mathbb{G}_m,(V\setminus0)/\mathbb{G}_m)[2(i+r)]=\mathbb{Z}_p(i)(Y\times\mathrm{B}\mathbb{G}_m)[2i] \end{align*}

for $i< n'$ by the Thom isomorphism, so it suffices to show that for $i< n'$, any map

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^n\mathrm{TC}(Y)\to\mathbb{Z}_p(i)(Y\times\mathrm{B}\mathbb{G}_m)[2i] \end{align*}

that is functorial in $Y$ is uniquely nullhomotopic. By étale descent we can assume that $Y=\operatorname {Spec}(R)$ is affine. Then by descent along the Čech nerve of $Y\to Y\times \mathrm {B}\mathbb {G}_m$, we reduce to show that, for $i< n'$ and any ring $A$ smooth over $\mathbb {Z}$, any map

\begin{align*} \operatorname{Fil}^n\mathrm{TC}(R)\to\mathbb{Z}_p(i)(R\otimes A)[2i] \end{align*}

that is functorial in $R$ is uniquely nullhomotopic. Since both sides commute with sifted colimits in $R$, we can assume that $R$ is also smooth over $\mathbb {Z}$. Now both sides satisfy quasisyntomic descent, and the theorem follows from the fact that quasisyntomic locally, $\operatorname {Fil}^n\mathrm {TC}$ is $2n$-connective, but $\mathbb {Z}_p(i)[2i]$ lies in homotopical degree $2i<2n'\le 2n$, cf. [Reference Bhatt, Morrow and ScholzeBMS19, § 7.4] and [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Theorem 14.1].

To see that the associated graded gives the Gysin map, by the same deformation to the normal cone argument, we only need to show that for a rank $r$ vector bundle $V\to Y$, it gives the syntomic Thom map

\begin{align*} \mathbb{Z}_p(\star)(Y)[2\star]\to\mathbb{Z}_p(\star+r)(V,V\setminus0)[2(\star+r)] \end{align*}

when applied to the zero section $0\to V$. This is a map of $\mathbb {Z}_p(\star )(Y)[2\star ]$-modules, so it suffices to show that the image of $1\in \mathbb {Z}_p(0)(Y)$ is $\mathrm {Th}_V^\mathrm {syn}\in \mathbb {Z}_p(r)(V,V\setminus 0)[2r]$. By Remark 4.8, this reduces to the functoriality, the additivity, and the normalization for line bundles for this image, which we now check.

Functoriality. This is clear by the functoriality of the Gysin map.

Additivity. By [Reference Clausen, Mathew and MorrowCMM21, Theorem 1.7], the $p$-completed $\mathrm {TC}$ is the étale sheafification of the $p$-completed connective $K$-theory. Now $1\in K(Y)$ is just $[\mathcal {O}_Y]$, and the product is just the tensor product, so the additivity follows from the fact that if $V=V'\oplus V''$ is a direct sum, then $\mathcal {O}_0=\mathcal {O}_{V'}\otimes _{\mathcal {O}_V}\mathcal {O}_{V''}$, where we view $V'$ and $V''$ as closed substacks of $V$.

Normalization for line bundles. As above, viewing $\mathrm {TC}$ as the étale $K$-theory, it suffices to show that for a Cartier divisor $D\to X$, the associated graded class of $[\mathcal {O}_D]\in \operatorname {Fil}^1\mathrm {TC}(X)$ is $c_1(\mathcal {O}(D))\in \Omega ^{\infty -2}\mathbb {Z}_p(1)(X)$. By étale descent, we can assume that $X=\operatorname {Spec}(R)$ is affine. Then by [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Proposition 7.4.8], we can assume that $R$ is smooth over $\mathbb {Z}$. Now by $p$-quasisyntomic descent, we can assume that $R$ is over $\mathbb {Z}_p^\mathrm {cyc}$ and is quasiregular semiperfectoid, where it follows from [Reference Anschütz and Le BrasALB20, Theorem 6.7] and [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Corollary 2.6.11, Proposition 7.5.2].

Remark 5.39 The $p$-completion $K^\mathrm {Sel}(R)_p^\wedge$ of the Selmer $K$-theory introduced in [Reference ClausenCla17, § 2] is an enhancement of $\mathrm {TC}(R)_p^\wedge$ that contains information about $R[1/p]$, cf. [Reference Clausen and MathewCM21, § 6], and it should be motivic filtered by the non-$p$-formal syntomic cohomology sheaf $\mathbb {Z}_p(i)(R)[2i]$. We expect an analog of Theorem 5.38 in this setting.

6. Poincaré duality

We finally prove the prismatic Poincaré duality in this section. First we recall its Hodge version in [Reference ClausenCla21, Lecture 16]. Let $S$ be a stack and $X$ be a stack over $S$. Suppose the structure map $f\colon X\to S$ is representable by algebraic spaces, and is proper smooth of dimension $d\in \mathbb {N}$. Then the relative diagonal $\Delta \colon X\to X\times _SX$ is a regular immersion of codimension $d$. Note by [Aut, 0A1P] that the relative Hodge cohomology $f_*(\mathrm {L}\Omega _{X/S}^\star )[-\star ]$ is dualizable in $\mathsf {D}(S)$.

Theorem 6.1 (Poincaré duality for Hodge cohomology)

The image of the absolute Hodge cycle class $\mathrm {Cl}^\mathrm {Hod}_\Delta \in \Omega ^{\infty -d}\mathrm {R}\Gamma (X\times _SX,\mathrm {L}\Omega _{X\times _SX}^d)$ along

\begin{align*} &\mathrm{R}\Gamma(X\times_SX,\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X\times_SX}^\star)\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma(X\times_SX,\mathrm{L}\Omega_{(X\times_SX)/S}^\star)\\ &\quad=\mathrm{R}\Gamma(S,(f\times_Sf)_*(\mathrm{L}\Omega_{(X\times_SX)/S}^\star))=\mathrm{R}\Gamma(S,f_*(\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^\star)\otimes f_*(\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^\star)) \end{align*}

gives rise to a graded map

\begin{align*} \mathcal{O}_S\to f_*(\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^\star)\otimes f_*(\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^\star)(d)[d], \end{align*}

where $(d)$ and $[d]$ denote the shift on the grade and the homological degree, respectively. This map is a perfect copairing, i.e. the dual map

\begin{align*} p_*(\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^\star)^\vee\to f_*(\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^\star)(d)[d] \end{align*}

is an isomorphism.

Proof. The proof is the same as in [Reference ClausenCla21, Lecture 16], with our Proposition 5.36 in place of its Lemma 2. For convenience and completeness, we reproduce it here.

Since the cycle class is the image of $1$ under the Gysin map, using Proposition 5.36 with $n=0$ we see that the copairing map in the theorem, in individual grades, can be described as follows: take $d$th wedge power of the canonical map from the conormal to the cotangent

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^d=\Lambda^d(\mathrm{L}_{X/(X\times_SX)}[-1])\to\Delta^*\mathrm{L}\Omega_{(X\times_SX)/S}^d; \end{align*}

note that $\Delta ^!\mathcal {O}_{X\times _SX}=(\mathrm {L}\Omega _{X/S}^d)^{-1}[-d]$; tensor this with both sides to get

\begin{align*} \mathcal{O}_X[-d]\to\Delta^*\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X\times_SX}^d\otimes\Delta^!\mathcal{O}_{X\times_SX}=\Delta^!\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X\times_SX}^d; \end{align*}

then move the $\Delta ^!$ to the left, apply $(f\times _Sf)_*$, and finally compose with the canonical map $\mathcal {O}_S\to f_*\mathcal {O}_X$ and the projection to one direct summand in Künneth to get

\begin{align*} \mathcal{O}_S[-d]\to f_*\mathcal{O}_X[-d]\to(f\times_Sf)_*\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X\times_SX}^d\to f_*\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^i\otimes f_*\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^j, \end{align*}

where $i$ and $j$ are fixed with $i+j=d$. To see that this is perfect, we apply Lemma 6.2 to reduce to perfectness of

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^d\to\Delta^*\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X\times_SX}^d=\mathrm{L}\Lambda^d(\mathrm{L}_{X/S}\oplus\mathrm{L}_{X/S})\to\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^i\otimes\mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^j, \end{align*}

where the final map is the projection to one direct summand; now this is a claim on quasicoherent sheaves over $X$, so it can be verified étale locally, where it follows by a straightforward calculation with local coordinates.

Lemma 6.2 (Cf. [Reference ClausenCla21, Lemma 16.3])

Suppose $M$ and $N$ are perfect complexes over $X$ that are in duality via a perfect copairing

\begin{align*} \mathrm{L}\Omega_{X/S}^d[d]=f^!\mathcal{O}_S\to M\otimes N=\Delta^*(M\boxtimes_SN). \end{align*}

Then $f_*M$ and $f_*N$ are in duality via the copairing

\begin{align*} \mathcal{O}_S\to f_*M\otimes f_*N \end{align*}

given as follows: first tensor both sides by $\Delta ^!\mathcal {O}_{X\times _SX}=(f^!\mathcal {O}_S)^{-1}$ to get

\begin{align*} \mathcal{O}_X\to\Delta^*(M\boxtimes_SN)\otimes\Delta^!\mathcal{O}_{X\times_SX}=\Delta^!(M\boxtimes_SN); \end{align*}

then move the $\Delta ^!$ to the left, apply $(f\times _Sf)_*$, and finally compose with the canonical map $\mathcal {O}_S\to f_*\mathcal {O}_X$ to get

\begin{align*} \mathcal{O}_S\to f_*\mathcal{O}_X\to(f\times_Sf)_*(M\boxtimes_SN)=f_*M\otimes f_*N. \end{align*}

Proof. Take a pairing $N\otimes M\to f^!\mathcal {O}_S$ that forms a duality datum with the copairing. Move $f^!$ to the left and use the lax monoidal structure of $f^*$ to get

\begin{align*} f_*N\otimes f_*M\to f_*(N\otimes M)\to\mathcal{O}_S. \end{align*}

It suffices to show that this pairing forms a duality datum with the copairing given above. To this end, we consider the composition

\begin{align*} f^!\mathcal{O}_S\otimes M\to(M\otimes N)\otimes M=M\otimes(N\otimes M)\to M\otimes f^!\mathcal{O}_S. \end{align*}

Tensoring $\Delta ^!\mathcal {O}_{X\times _SX}=(f^!\mathcal {O}_S)^{-1}$, we get

\begin{align*} M\to\Delta^!(M\boxtimes_S(N\otimes M))\to\Delta^!(M\boxtimes_Sf^!\mathcal{O}_S)=M. \end{align*}

Moving $\Delta ^!$ to the left and applying $(f\times _Sf)_*$, we get

\begin{align*} f_*M\to f_*M\otimes f_*(N\otimes M)\to f_*M\otimes f_*f^!\mathcal{O}_S\to f_*M, \end{align*}

where the last map is the counit. Now since we start with a duality datum, the first composition is the map commuting $M$ and $f^!\mathcal {O}_S$, so the second and the third compositions are identity maps. Therefore, it suffices to see that the first map above is given by the composition

\begin{align*} f_*M\to(f_*M\otimes f_*N)\otimes f_*M=f_*M\otimes(f_*N\otimes f_*M)\to f_*M\otimes f_*(N\otimes M), \end{align*}

where the first map is induced by the copairing we constructed. Since we are working with quasicoherent sheaves on $S$, it suffices to show the statement after restricted along every morphism $U\to S$ and composed with every map $\varphi \colon \mathcal {O}_U[n]\to f_*M|_U$ for every $n\in \mathbb {Z}$. Restriction commutes with everything here, so we can assume $U=S$. Then the statement follows from the functorialities of all the above constructions applied to the map $N[n]\to N\otimes M$ induced by $\varphi$.

Now let $(A,I)$ be a prism and take $S=\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$. To prove the Poincaré duality, we need to produce a copairing map using the syntomic cycle class.

Remark 6.3 Let $R$ be a ring over $\bar {A}$. Note that the comparison map $\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_R\{d\}\to (\operatorname {Fil}^\bullet { {\mathbb {\Delta }}}_{R/A}^{(1)})\{d\}$ in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Construction 5.6.1] is compatible with Frobenius, i.e. the following diagram commutes.

By Proposition 2.35, this gives rise to a comparison map

\begin{align*} \mathbb{Z}_p(d)(R)\to\operatorname{Hom}_{{F\text{-}\mathsf{Gauge}}(A,I)}(A,{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}_{R/A}\{d\}). \end{align*}

In addition, it is not hard to see from [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, Remark 5.5.8] that the following diagram commutes.

Therefore, for a regular immersion $Z\to Y$ of stacks over $\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$ of codimension $d$, the cycle class $\mathrm {Cl}^\mathrm {syn}_{Y/X}\in \Omega ^{\infty -2d}\mathbb {Z}_p(d)(X)$ gives rise to a map $A\to \mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)\{d\}[2d]$ that sends $1$ to the Hodge cycle class after Hodge specialization.

Recall that $X$ is a stack over $S=\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$, and the map $X\to S$ is representable by algebraic spaces proper smooth of dimension $d$. Recall by Corollary 2.37 that $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)$ is dualizable in ${F\text {-}\mathsf {Gauge}}(A,I)$.

Theorem 6.4 (Prismatic Poincaré duality)

By Remark 6.3, the syntomic cycle class $\mathrm {Cl}^\mathrm {syn}_\Delta$ of the relative diagonal $\Delta \colon X\to X\times _{\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})}X$ induces a map of $F$-gauges

\begin{align*} A\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}((X\times_{\operatorname{Spf}(\bar{A})}X)/A)\{d\}[2d]=\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)\otimes_A\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)\{d\}[2d]. \end{align*}

This map is a perfect copairing, i.e. the dual map

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)^\vee\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)\{d\}[2d] \end{align*}

is an isomorphism.

Proof. By Proposition 2.22, it suffices to prove that both the Hodge–Tate and the de Rham specializations of the above map are isomorphisms. By Proposition 2.36, both specializations are complete with only finitely many nonzero graded pieces, so we can pass to the graded pieces, which are the Hodge cohomologies, and the theorem follows from Theorem 6.1 and Remark 6.3.

Remark 6.5 (Trace maps)

Theorem 6.4 gives a trace map $\mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)\{d\}[2d]\to A$ as the dual of the structure map $A\to \mathrm {R}\Gamma _{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}(X/A)$, which reduces to the Hodge trace map after specialization. Now if there were a suitably defined dualizable coefficient system $\mathcal {E}$ on $X$, then the pairing $\mathcal {E}\otimes \mathcal {E}^\vee \to \mathcal {O}$ along with the trace map gives a canonical pairing

\begin{align*} \mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A,\mathcal{E})\otimes\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A,\mathcal{E}^\vee)\{d\}[2d]\to\mathrm{R}\Gamma_{{\mathbb {\Delta}}}(X/A)\{d\}[2d]\to A. \end{align*}

If one worked out the theory of relative $F$-gauges as sketched in Remark 2.34, then it would be not hard to prove that the pairing is perfect by Hodge specialization; alternatively, one could also see that it is already perfect for $\mathcal {E}$ being a dualizable prismatic crystal by Hodge–Tate specialization, via a careful study of the cohomology along $\mathrm {WCart}_{X/A}^\mathrm {HT}\to X$, cf. [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22b, Proposition 5.12, Corollary 6.6].

Remark 6.6 (Comparisons)

The comparisons of Theorem 6.4 with the duality maps of several other cohomology theories should follow from the uniqueness of cycle classes in Remark 5.28 and Remark 5.29. More specifically, we have the following.

  • By the proof of Theorem 6.4, it is already clear that the prismatic duality map specializes to the Hodge duality map given by the coherent duality and the de Rham duality map constructed in [Reference ClausenCla21, Lecture 16].

  • For $I=pA$, Theorem 6.4 recovers the crystalline Poincaré duality in [Reference BerthelotBer74, Theorem VII.2.1.3] via [Reference Bhatt and ScholzeBS22, Theorem 5.2]. Indeed, under the Künneth formula, Berthelot's pairing map is the composition of the diagonal pullback with the trace map, so by [Reference BerthelotBer74, Corollary VII.2.3.2] its dual copairing is the cycle class of the diagonal, which is exactly the copairing here.

  • If one started with a perfect prism $(A,I)$ and a smooth and proper algebraic space over $\operatorname {Spec}(\bar {A})$, rather than such a formal algebraic space over $\operatorname {Spf}(\bar {A})$, then the syntomic cycle class would specialize to the étale one after inverting $p$, so the prismatic duality map would also specialize to the étale one after inverting $p$. We are not going into details here, since in future projects, we plan to compare the prismatic Poincaré duality with that of diamonds in [Reference MannMan22, Theorem 3.10.20].

Remark 6.7 In future projects, we hope to explore generalizations of Theorem 6.4 in the following directions:

  • to general coefficients for the prismatic cohomology as in Remark 6.5;

  • to the absolute prismatic cohomology, or more generally to the coherent duality along the map $X^{{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}''}\to S^{{ {\mathbb {\Delta }}}''}$ of prismatizations as in [Reference DrinfeldDri24];

  • to non-proper maps, i.e. to a 6-functor formalism with a condensed lower shriek as in [Reference Clausen and ScholzeCS19];

  • to non-$p$-formal schemes, i.e. gluing with similar structure in the étale cohomology, as in [Reference Bhatt and LurieBL22a, § 8.4].

Acknowledgements

First, I heartily thank my advisor Bhargav Bhatt for encouraging me to work on prismatic Poincaré duality and suggesting that I should imitate the lecture notes [Reference ClausenCla21]. Next, I would like to thank Dustin Clausen for these lecture notes that give a beautiful proof of the duality in the de Rham case. Moreover, I thank Toni Annala, Johannes Anschütz, Benjamin Antieau, Arthur-César Le Bras, Elden Elmanto, Ofer Gabber, Haoyang Guo, Lars Hesselholt, Marc Hoyois, Teruhisa Koshikawa, Dmitry Kubrak, Yixiao Li, Shiji Lyu, Lucas Mann, Akhil Mathew, Emanuel Reinecke, Yuchen Wu, Bogdan Zavyalov, and Daming Zhou for helpful discussions. Finally, I would also like to thank the referee for many helpful comments improving the exposition and precision of the paper, and the Hausdorff Research Institute for Mathematics for their hospitality and support during the trimester program on the arithmetic of the Langlands program.

Conflicts of interest

None.

Journal information

Compositio Mathematica is owned by the Foundation Compositio Mathematica and published by the London Mathematical Society in partnership with Cambridge University Press. All surplus income from the publication of Compositio Mathematica is returned to mathematics and higher education through the charitable activities of the Foundation, the London Mathematical Society and Cambridge University Press.

References

Annala, T., Hoyois, M. and Iwasa, R., Algebraic cobordism and a Conner-Floyd isomorphism for algebraic K-theory, J. Amer. Math. Soc. (2024), doi:10.1090/jams/1045.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annala, T. and Iwasa, R., Motivic spectra and universality of K-theory, Preprint (2023), arXiv:2204.03434.Google Scholar
Anschütz, J. and Le Bras, A.-C., The $p$-completed cyclotomic trace in degree $2$, Ann. of K-Theory 5 (2020), 539580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antieau, B., Krause, A. and Nikolaus, T., On the K-theory of $\mathbb {Z}/p^n$—announcement, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2204.03420.Google Scholar
Berthelot, P., Cohomologie cristalline des schémas de caractéristique $p>0$, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Vol. 407 (Springer, Berlin–New York, 1974); MR 384804.Google Scholar
Blumberg, A. J., Gepner, D. and Tabuada, G., A universal characterization of higher algebraic $K$-theory, Geom. Topol. 17 (2013), 733838.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhatt, B. and Lurie, J., Absolute prismatic cohomology, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2201.06120.Google Scholar
Bhatt, B. and Lurie, J., The prismatization of p-adic formal schemes, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2201.06124.Google Scholar
Bhatt, B. and Mathew, A., The $\mathrm {arc}$-topology, Duke Math. J. 170 (2021), 18991988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhatt, B., Morrow, M. and Scholze, P., Integral $p$-adic Hodge theory, Publ. Math. Inst. Hautes Études Sci. 128 (2018), 219397; MR 3905467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhatt, B., Morrow, M. and Scholze, P., Topological Hochschild homology and integral $p$-adic Hodge theory, Publ. Math. Inst. Hautes Études Sci. 129 (2019), 199310; MR 3949030.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhatt, B. and Scholze, P., Projectivity of the Witt vector affine Grassmannian, Invent. Math. 209 (2017), 329423; MR 3674218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhatt, B. and Scholze, P., Prisms and prismatic cohomology, Ann. of Math. 196 (2022), 11351275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cattani, E., El Zein, F., Griffiths, P. A. and Tráng, L. D. (eds.), Hodge theory, Mathematical Notes, vol. 49 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2014); MR 3288678.Google Scholar
Clausen, D., A K-theoretic approach to Artin maps, Preprint (2017), arXiv:1703.07842.Google Scholar
Clausen, D., Algebraic de Rham cohomology, Online course notes (2021), https://sites.google.com/view/algebraicderham/home.Google Scholar
Clausen, D. and Mathew, A., Hyperdescent and étale $K$-theory, Invent. Math. 225 (2021), 9811076; MR 4296353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clausen, D., Mathew, A. and Morrow, M., $K$-theory and topological cyclic homology of henselian pairs, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 34 (2021), 411473; MR 4280864.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clausen, D. and Scholze, P., Lectures on condensed mathematics, Online course notes (2019), https://people.mpim-bonn.mpg.de/scholze/Condensed.pdf.Google Scholar
Clausen, D. and Scholze, P., Condensed mathematics and complex geometry, Online course notes (2022), https://people.mpim-bonn.mpg.de/scholze/Complex.pdf.Google Scholar
Drinfeld, V., Prismatization, Preprint (2024), arXiv:2005.04746.Google Scholar
Fujiwara, K., A proof of the absolute purity conjecture (after Gabber), in Algebraic geometry 2000, Azumino (Hotaka), Advanced Studies in Pure Mathematics, vol. 36 (Mathematical Society of Japan, Tokyo, 2002), 153183; MR 1971516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hahn, J., Raksit, A. and Wilson, D., A motivic filtration on the topological cyclic homology of commutative ring spectra, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2206.11208.Google Scholar
Kubrak, D. and Prikhodko, A., $p$-adic Hodge theory for Artin stacks, Preprint (2021), arXiv:2105.05319.Google Scholar
Lurie, J., Higher topos theory Annals of Mathematics Studies, Vol. 170 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lurie, J., Higher algebra, Preprint (2017), https://www.math.ias.edu/~lurie/papers/HA.pdf.Google Scholar
Lurie, J., Spectral algebraic geometry, Preprint (2018), https://www.math.ias.edu/~lurie/papers/SAG-rootfile.pdf.Google Scholar
Mann, L., A $p$-adic 6-functor formalism in rigid-analytic geometry, Preprint (2022), arXiv:2206.02022.Google Scholar
Mao, Z., Revisiting derived crystalline cohomology, Preprint (2021), arXiv:2107.02921.Google Scholar
Moulinos, T., The geometry of filtrations, Bull. Lond. Math. Soc. 53 (2021), 14861499.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nizioł, W., $p$-adic motivic cohomology in arithmetic, in Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians, Madrid, Spain, 2006, Vol. II (European Mathematical Society, Zürich, 2006), 459472; MR 2275605.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raksit, A., Hochschild homology and the derived de Rham complex revisited, Preprint (2020), arXiv:2007.02576.Google Scholar
The Stacks Project Authors, Stacks Project, https://stacks.math.columbia.edu.Google Scholar
Suslin, A. and Voevodsky, V., Bloch–Kato conjecture and motivic cohomology with finite coefficients (Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, 2000), 117189.Google Scholar