Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T18:23:38.124Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Aristophanes, Frogs 1463–5

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 February 2009

Extract

This passage has long embarrassed interpreters, and many, beginning with Kock, have condemned it as spurious (generally bracketing 1460–6). But this would mean that Aeschylus' only answer to Dionysus' question (1436) ‘what <way to> safety have you for the city?’ would be, in effect, ‘none’ (1458 ) : and this would hardly justify the general confidence expressed in the final scene (1501 f., 1530 ff.) that Aeschylus will in fact be able to save the city. The most recent editor, Stanford, rightly rejects the idea of interpolation here.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 1974

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 24 note 1 Aristophanes: The Frogs, ed. W. B. Stanford, 2nd edn., London and New York, 1963. Wilamowitz (Hermes, lxiv [1929[, 474) deletes only 1462–6, and sees Aeschylus' refusal (1461) to answer the question while in the underworld as explaining and indeed necessitating Dionysus' decision to take him back to the upper world; this ignores not only 1420 f. (see page 26), but also Dionysus' blunt instruction (1460) ‘Find <a way to save the city>, if you want to go back up there again’.

page 24 note 2 Hermes, lxxxiv (1956), 296–319.Google Scholar

page 24 note 3 Aristophanes: The Frogs and other plays, tr. D. Barrett, Harmondsworth, 1964.

page 24 note 4 In the parabasis the advice is in a purely positive form (, 735), whereas Euripides' advice is both positive and negative—to trust one group of citizens and not to trust another group; but this difference is unlikely to be significant.

page 24 note 5 D. M. MacDowell in C.Q. ix (1959), 261–8. MacDowell's own arrangement of the contest, however, does not meet the objection of Apollonius 5437) that Euripides, after being asked for one (435), is allowed to give two, nor does it satisfactorily account for the of 14.42; and the simple solution proposed long ago by Dindorf still seems the best: that 1437–41+ 1451–3 on the one hand, and 5442–50 on the other, are alternative versions, probably stemming from the two productions of the play (see Hypotheses I and III), which were conflated at an early date. This solution makes transpositions, lacunae, and deletions alike unnecessary.

page 25 note 1 quote as typical the scholia of R: 1463

page 25 note 2 It was the loss of Lampascus, and with it of control over the Hellespont, that brought the Athenian fleet to Aegospotami.

page 26 note 1 Xen. H.G. i. 6. 3 and 38.

page 26 note 2 Xen. H.G. 2. I. 16.

page 26 note 3 Line 1451, as was seen by Dindorf, belongs to the version in which Euripides' advice is a piece of ingenious ludicrousness.