Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T18:13:15.245Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

G.A. Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1995. Pp. x + 277.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Peter Vallentyne*
Affiliation:
Virginia Commonwealth University, Richmond, VA32284-2025, USA

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Critical Notice
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 I skip over Cohen's discussion of defenses of self-ownership that appeal to the claims (1) that people are ends, or (2) that people should not be sacrificed without their consent for the benefit of others.

2 Cohen assumes, as is standard, that self-ownership, as applied to moral agents, includes ownership of one's entire body, but this does not follow from the thesis of self-ownership alone. It depends on facts about personal identity. If, for example, agents are purely mental beings that can, but need not, voluntarily occupy and leave bodies, then bodies (in their initial state) are simply (external) natural resources, just like tracts of land. And even assuming that agents are necessarily embodied, it does not follow automatically that the agents are identical with their entire bodies (as opposed to their central nervous system, say). Self-ownership for moral agents leads to ownership of all of their body parts only if they are identical with their entire bodies. If correct, this point supplements Cohen's criticism of the above argument for full self-ownership.

3 In the new Ch. 2 Cohen indirectly (and not explicitly) raises a criticism of the thesis of full self-ownership that I shall not consider. He there criticizes the principle that whatever arises from a just situation by just steps is itself just, where the justice of steps (or transactions) is conceived of procedurally (e.g., fully voluntarily) and not in terms of the ultimate outcomes. He thereby implicitly questions whether the justice of situations can be captured solely in terms of property rights. Explaining how this is relevant, and why I think the criticism fails (roughly: because his concerns are capturable within a property rights framework), would take me too far astray.

4 The best known contemporary advocate of the equal division of the natural resource rent is Steiner. Equal division is also advocated by Parijs, P. Van in Real Freedom for All (New York: Oxford University Press 1995)Google Scholar, although it is qualified so that the social fund is divided equally only after compensation has been made for unchosen disadvantage. Grunebaum, J. in Private Ownership (New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1987)Google Scholar, holds the natural resources are jointly owned, but holds that typically the most sensible decision is to rent out natural resources. If so rented, the rents are divided equally on his view. Dworkin, R. in ‘What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1981) 283345Google Scholar, develops an equal division approach, but only on the assumption that there is no differential brute luck. See also the discussion in Kolm, S.C. Le Contrat social liberal (Theorie et pratique du liberalisme) (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, ‘L'Allocation des ressources naturelles et le liberalisme,’ Revue economique 37 (1986) 207-41, Modern Theories of Justice (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press 1996); and Roemer, J. Theories of Distributive Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1996)Google Scholar.

5 The control part of self-ownership is, roughly speaking (ignoring some differences), endorsed by Christman, J. in A Theory of Property (New York: Oxford University Press 1994)Google Scholar, and (under the name ‘full act freedom’) by S.C. Kolm in Modern Theories of Justice. They both reject full self-ownership.

6 For arguments against the right to make tax-immune gifts or bequests to members of later generations, see Ackerman, B. Social justice in the Liberal State (New Haven: Yale University Press 1980)Google Scholar; Haslett, D.W.Is Inheritance Justified?Philosophy and Public Affairs 15 (1988) 122–55Google Scholar; Munzer, S. A Theory of Property (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nozick, R. The Examined Life (New York: Simon and Schuster 1989)Google Scholar; Rignano, E. The Social Significance of the Inheritance Tax (New York: A. Knopf 1924)Google Scholar; Sreenivasan, G. The Limits of Lockean Rights in Property (New York: Oxford University Press 1995)Google Scholar; Steiner, H. An Essay on Rights (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell 1994)Google Scholar, P. Van Parijs, Real Freedom for All; and Varian, H.Distributive Justice, Welfare Economics, and the Theory of Fairness,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 4 (1975) 223–47Google Scholar.

7 Two fairly plausible conditions on common use are: (1) no one should be made worse off in a (specified) relevant way compared with non-use (e.g., as when a scarce resource is damaged or destroyed); and (2) when more people want to use a given resource at a given time than can use it, each user must pay a fee equal to the competitive value of the use. These conditions are discussed below with respect to appropriation, but they could also be applied to use.

8 Rothbard, M. For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto, rev. ed. (New York: Libertarian Review Foundation 1978)Google Scholar, The Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Heights: Humanities Press 1982); Kirzner, I.Entrepreneurship, Entitlement, and Economic Justice,’ Eastern Economic Journal 4 (1978)Google Scholar

9 Such as Nozick, R. Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books 1974)Google Scholar

10 There are many extremely important issues that I am here glossing over. The competitive values of rights over resources are relative to a set of market conditions, and specifying and defending a particular set of conditions is crucial. Furthermore, even for a determinate set of initial conditions there can be more than one possible market equilibrium, and hence more than one possible set of competitive prices for resources.

11 George, H. Progress and Poverty (New York: Robert Schalkenbach Foundation 1879)Google Scholar, A Perplexed Philosopher (New York: Robert Schalkenbach Foundation 1892). Other early exponents of some form of self-ownership combined with some form of social ownership of natural resources include Colins, H. Du Pacte sociale, et de la liberte politique consideree comme complement moral de l' homme vol 2 (Paris: Moutardier 1835)Google Scholar; Dove, P.E. The Theory of Human Progression and Natural Probability of a Reign of Justice: The Science of Politics, Part 1 (Edinburgh: Johnstone and Hun ten 1850)Google Scholar, The Elements of Political Science: The Science of Politics, Part 2 (Edinburgh: Johnstone and Hunten 1854); Huet, F. Le Regne social du christianisme (Paris: Firmin Didot Freres 1835)Google Scholar; Ogilvie, W.The Right of Property in Land,’ The Pioneers of Land Reform, Beer, M. ed. (New York: A. Knopf 1920; 1781)Google Scholar; Paine, T.Agrarian Justice,’ The Thomas Paine Reader, Foot, M. and Kramnick, I. eds. (Harmondsworth: Penguin 1987; 1795)Google Scholar; Spence, T.The Real Rights of Man,’ The Pioneers of Land Reform, Beer, M. ed. (New York: A. Knopf 1920; 1793)Google Scholar; Spencer, H. Social Statistics (New York: A.M. Kelley 1851)Google Scholar; and Walras, L. Etudes d'economie sociale, 2me ed. (Paris: R. Pichon et R. Durand-Auzias 1936)Google Scholar. For insightful discussion of some of these early views, see Cunliffe, J.A Mutualist Theory of Exploitation?Modern Theories of Exploitation, Reeve, A. ed. (London: Sage 1987)Google Scholar, ‘The Liberal Rationale of “Rational Socialism,”’ Political Studies 36 (1988) 653-62, ‘The Neglected Background of Radical Liberalism: P.E. Dove's Theory of Property,’ History of Political Thought 11 (1990) 467-90, ‘Intergenerational Justice and Productive Resources: A Nineteenth-Century Socialist Debate,’ History of European Ideas 12 (1990) 227-38.

12 The idea that the rent from natural resources should be first used to equalize advantage (as opposed to being equally divided) is endorsed by P. Van Parijs (Real Freedom for All); Sartorius, R.Persons and Property,’ Utility and Rights Frey, R.G. ed. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1984)Google Scholar; and Brown, P.Food as National Property,’ Food Policy, Brown, P. and Shue, H. eds. (New York: Free Press 1977)Google Scholar.

13 In Ch. 9 (new) Cohen criticizes the claim by Gauthier, D. Morals by Agreement (London: Oxford University Press 1986)Google Scholar, that self-ownership does not include the right to any income in excess of the minimum income necessary to induce one to supply a service or product. A similar criticism is made by Van Parijs (Real Freedom for All). As I note in the text, however, although full ownership of a service or product entitles the owner to the surplus income, this entitlement may be lost if one uses or appropriates resources that belong in part to others. Hence, taxation of surplus income is compatible with initial full self-ownership.

14 The following are some loosely related approaches to self-ownership and the ownership of natural resources: J. Christman (The Myth of Property) defends control self-ownership, but denies that agents (even non-appropriators) have any right to the income they generate. S. White, ‘Justice, Community, and the Inequality of Talents,’ British Journal of Political Science (forthcoming) accepts control self-ownership, but argues that agents owe taxes on their income at a rate (varying depending their talents) that equalizes post-tax potential income. M. Otsuka, ‘Deontology and Equality: A Lockean Reconciliation,’ unpublished (Dept. of Philosophy, UCLA) argues that agents are free to appropriate only as much resources as is compatible with equality of opportunity for welfare (and thus more talented agents are permitted to appropriate less). Brody, B.Redistribution Without Egalitarianism,’ Social Philosophy and Policy 1 (1983) 7187CrossRefGoogle Scholar, argues that the benefits of appropriation may be taxed to ensure that everyone gets a mutually self-interested fair share of the benefits. Gibbard, A.Natural Property Rights,’ Nous 10 (1976) 7786CrossRefGoogle Scholar, explores full self-ownership in conjunction with joint ownership of natural resources. This is like the joint ownership model considered by Cohen except that the non-agreement point is common use rather than non-use. This is a much more plausible model of joint ownership of natural resources, but it is still implausible because it requires the actual consent of others for just appropriation (it fails to be unilateralist). He also considers a hypothetical agreement model.

15 E.g., Cohen, G.A.On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice,’ Ethics 99 (1989) 906–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 For further discussion of the notion of self-ownership, the ownership of natural resources, and the ownership of artifacts, see (in addition to the articles already cited) Becker, L. Property Rights: Philosophical Foundations (Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1977)Google Scholar; Fressola, F.Liberty and Property,’ American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1981) 315–22Google Scholar; Ingram, A. A Political Theory of Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kymlicka, W. Contemporary Political Philosophy (New York: Oxford 1990)Google Scholar; Mack, E.Distributive Justice and the Tensions of Lockeanism,’ Social Philosophy and Policy 1 (1983) 132–50Google Scholar, and ‘Self-Ownership and the Right of Property,’ Monist 73 (1990) 519-43; Mavrodes, G.Property,’ The Personalist 53 (1974) 245–62Google Scholar; Narveson, J. The Libertarian Idea (Philadelphia: Temple University Press 1988)Google Scholar; Thomson, J.J. The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1990)Google Scholar; and Waldron, J. The Right to Private Property (New York: Oxford University Press 1988).Google Scholar

17 Work on this paper was funded in part by a fellowship grant from the American Council of Learned Societies. For comments and criticisms I'm indebted to the members of the discussion groups at Nuffield College, Oxford, and at The University of Manchester, Christian Arnsperger, Jerry Cohen, Tony Ellis, Brad Hooker, Shelly Kagan, Serge Kolm, Michael Lacewing, Trenton Merricks, Gene Mills, Arthur Ripstein, John Roemer, Hillel Steiner, Andrew Williams, and two anonymous referees for this journal.